首页 > 最新文献

Logical Empiricism and the Physical Sciences最新文献

英文 中文
Kurt Grelling and the Idiosyncrasy of the Berlin Logical Empiricism 库尔特·格雷林与柏林逻辑经验主义的特质
Pub Date : 2021-04-02 DOI: 10.4324/9780429429835-4
N. Milkov
: The received view has it that Hans Reichenbach and his friends of the Berlin Group worked close together with the more prominent Vienna Circle. In the wake of this view, Reichenbach was often treated as a logical positivist – despite the fact that he decisively opposed it. In this chapter we follow another thread. We shall show the “third man”– besides Reichenbach and Walter Dubislav – of the Berlin Group, Kurt Grelling, as a man who could grasp the academic trends of the time faster than anybody else, who was better informed about logic and philosophy of nature than his two prominent colleagues and thus, could better delineate, although tentatively, central threads of research of the Berlin Group. Grelling did this on several occasions, but most ostensibly in the last years of his life when he was focused on problems of formal ontology. On the basis of this analysis, we shall see that in the early 1920s, Reichenbach too was led by a project in ontology of science that he elaborated together with the psychologist Kurt Lewin. Moreover, Reichenbach’s later philosophy of nature was also shaped by this project. We present this direction of philosophy of science as a “road less travelled” which, however, if revived, can point to a new direction that will more closely connect philosophy and science.
当前位置公认的观点是汉斯·莱辛巴赫和他的柏林集团的朋友们与更著名的维也纳圈子密切合作。在这一观点之后,莱辛巴赫经常被视为逻辑实证主义者——尽管事实上他坚决反对这一观点。在本章中,我们遵循另一条线索。我们将展示柏林集团的“第三个人”——除了赖兴巴赫和沃尔特·杜比斯拉夫——库尔特·格雷林,他比任何人都能更快地把握当时的学术趋势,他比他的两位杰出的同事更了解逻辑和自然哲学,因此,他能更好地描绘柏林集团研究的中心线索,尽管是暂时的。greling在很多场合都这样做过,但最明显的是在他生命的最后几年,当时他专注于形式本体论的问题。在此分析的基础上,我们将看到,在20世纪20年代早期,莱辛巴赫也被他与心理学家库尔特·勒温(Kurt Lewin)共同阐述的科学本体论项目所引导。此外,莱辛巴赫后来的自然哲学也受到了这个项目的影响。我们把科学哲学的这个方向说成是一条“人迹罕至的道路”,但是,如果重新走上这条道路,就可以指出一条将哲学和科学更紧密地联系在一起的新方向。
{"title":"Kurt Grelling and the Idiosyncrasy of the Berlin Logical Empiricism","authors":"N. Milkov","doi":"10.4324/9780429429835-4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9780429429835-4","url":null,"abstract":": The received view has it that Hans Reichenbach and his friends of the Berlin Group worked close together with the more prominent Vienna Circle. In the wake of this view, Reichenbach was often treated as a logical positivist – despite the fact that he decisively opposed it. In this chapter we follow another thread. We shall show the “third man”– besides Reichenbach and Walter Dubislav – of the Berlin Group, Kurt Grelling, as a man who could grasp the academic trends of the time faster than anybody else, who was better informed about logic and philosophy of nature than his two prominent colleagues and thus, could better delineate, although tentatively, central threads of research of the Berlin Group. Grelling did this on several occasions, but most ostensibly in the last years of his life when he was focused on problems of formal ontology. On the basis of this analysis, we shall see that in the early 1920s, Reichenbach too was led by a project in ontology of science that he elaborated together with the psychologist Kurt Lewin. Moreover, Reichenbach’s later philosophy of nature was also shaped by this project. We present this direction of philosophy of science as a “road less travelled” which, however, if revived, can point to a new direction that will more closely connect philosophy and science.","PeriodicalId":314224,"journal":{"name":"Logical Empiricism and the Physical Sciences","volume":"4 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-04-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115685208","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
From the Periphery to the Center 从外围到中心
Pub Date : 2021-04-02 DOI: 10.4324/9780429429835-19
M. Neuber
{"title":"From the Periphery to the Center","authors":"M. Neuber","doi":"10.4324/9780429429835-19","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9780429429835-19","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":314224,"journal":{"name":"Logical Empiricism and the Physical Sciences","volume":"34 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-04-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"132675127","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Legacy of Logical Empiricism 逻辑经验主义的遗产
Pub Date : 2019-08-26 DOI: 10.4324/9780429429835-14
C. Glymour
Logical empiricism had two competing visions of philosophy of science, one passive from Kant and championed by Carnap, one active championed by Reichenbach. This essay summarizes the effects of these different dispositions on the Logical Empircists' contributions to science, and their reverberations in late 20th and 21st century philosophy of science.
逻辑经验主义有两种相互竞争的科学哲学观点,一种是康德的被动观点,由卡尔纳普倡导,一种是莱辛巴赫的主动观点。本文总结了这些不同的倾向对逻辑经验主义者对科学的贡献的影响,以及它们对20世纪末和21世纪科学哲学的影响。
{"title":"The Legacy of Logical Empiricism","authors":"C. Glymour","doi":"10.4324/9780429429835-14","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9780429429835-14","url":null,"abstract":"Logical empiricism had two competing visions of philosophy of science, one passive from Kant and championed by Carnap, one active championed by Reichenbach. This essay summarizes the effects of these different dispositions on the Logical Empircists' contributions to science, and their reverberations in late 20th and 21st century philosophy of science.","PeriodicalId":314224,"journal":{"name":"Logical Empiricism and the Physical Sciences","volume":"8 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-08-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115236978","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Two Constants in Carnap’s View on Scientific Theories 卡尔纳普科学理论观中的两个常数
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.4324/9780429429835-18
Sebastian Lutz
The received view on the development of the correspondence rules in Carnap’s philosophy of science is that at first, Carnap assumed the explicit definability of all theoretical terms in observational terms and later weakened this assumption. In the end, he conjectured that all observational terms can be explicitly defined in in theoretical terms, but not vice versa. I argue that from the very beginning, Carnap implicitly held this last view, albeit at times in contradiction to his professed position. To establish this point I argue that, first, Carnap’s ‘Über die Aufgabe der Physik’ is a contribution to the philosophy of science of logical empiricism, contrary to Thomas Mormann and in agreement with Herbert Feigl. Second, Michael Friedman misunderstands the ‘Aufgabe’ with his claim that it describes a method for arriving at explicit definitions for theoretical terms. Another received view on Carnap’s philosophy of science is that it assumed a formalization of physical theories that was too detached from actual physics and thus justly disavowed in favor of the semantic view as, for example, developed by van Fraassen. But the ‘Aufgabe’ and related works including the Aufbau show that from the very beginning to his last works, Carnap suggested formalizing physical theories as restrictions in mathematical spaces, as in the state-space conception of scientific theories favored by van Fraassen.
关于卡尔纳普科学哲学中对应规则发展的公认观点是,卡尔纳普首先假定所有理论项在观测项中都具有明确的可定义性,后来又削弱了这一假设。最后,他推测所有的观测项都可以明确地用理论术语来定义,反之则不然。我认为,从一开始,卡尔纳普就含蓄地持有最后一种观点,尽管有时与他公开宣称的立场相矛盾。为了确立这一点,我认为,首先,卡尔纳普的“Über die Aufgabe der Physik”是对逻辑经验主义科学哲学的贡献,与托马斯·莫尔曼(Thomas Mormann)相反,与赫伯特·费格尔(Herbert Feigl)一致。其次,迈克尔·弗里德曼(Michael Friedman)误解了“Aufgabe”,他声称它描述了一种达到理论术语明确定义的方法。另一种关于卡尔纳普科学哲学的观点是,它假设了一种形式化的物理理论,这种理论与实际的物理太过分离,因此理所当然地否定了这种形式化的物理理论,而支持语义观点,比如范·弗拉森(van Fraassen)提出的语义观点。但是《Aufbau》和包括《Aufbau》在内的相关著作表明,从一开始到他最后的作品,卡尔纳普都建议将物理理论形式化为数学空间的限制,就像范·弗拉森所青睐的科学理论的状态空间概念一样。
{"title":"Two Constants in Carnap’s View on Scientific Theories","authors":"Sebastian Lutz","doi":"10.4324/9780429429835-18","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9780429429835-18","url":null,"abstract":"The received view on the development of the correspondence rules in Carnap’s philosophy of science is that at first, Carnap assumed the explicit definability of all theoretical terms in observational terms and later weakened this assumption. In the end, he conjectured that all observational terms can be explicitly defined in in theoretical terms, but not vice versa. I argue that from the very beginning, Carnap implicitly held this last view, albeit at times in contradiction to his professed position. To establish this point I argue that, first, Carnap’s ‘Über die Aufgabe der Physik’ is a contribution to the philosophy of science of logical empiricism, contrary to Thomas Mormann and in agreement with Herbert Feigl. Second, Michael Friedman misunderstands the ‘Aufgabe’ with his claim that it describes a method for arriving at explicit definitions for theoretical terms. Another received view on Carnap’s philosophy of science is that it assumed a formalization of physical theories that was too detached from actual physics and thus justly disavowed in favor of the semantic view as, for example, developed by van Fraassen. But the ‘Aufgabe’ and related works including the Aufbau show that from the very beginning to his last works, Carnap suggested formalizing physical theories as restrictions in mathematical spaces, as in the state-space conception of scientific theories favored by van Fraassen.","PeriodicalId":314224,"journal":{"name":"Logical Empiricism and the Physical Sciences","volume":"205 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114755203","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Logical Empiricism and the Physical Sciences
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1