We Can Act Only Under the Idea of Freedom

H. Allison
{"title":"We Can Act Only Under the Idea of Freedom","authors":"H. Allison","doi":"10.5840/APAPA201372","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"In his address to the Pacific Division last year, Barry Stroud called attention both to the ubiquity of appeals to naturalism in the contemporary philosophical arena and the lack of anything approaching a consensus concerning the meaning of the term.' As he noted, the varieties of naturalism run the gamut from highly restrictive forms, such as physicalism and naturalized epistemology, which are exceedingly controversial, to more inclusive forms, which preserve their popularity by avoiding a commitment to anything recognizably \"naturalistic\" beyond the rejection of appeals to the super-natural. In the case of the latter forms, Stroud remarks sensibly, the term 'naturalism' is often reduced to an empty slogan, which could more appropriately be rendered by 'open-mindedness.'2 There is, however, at least one central area of philosophical inquiry where naturalism is not only alive and well but has a fairly determinate sense, namely the question of free will or agency. In spite of an ongoing debate around the edges of this topic, for some time the ruling orthodoxy has been a form of compatibilism that is naturalistic in the sense that it dismisses any account of agency that is not positively related to the framework of nomological explanation operative in the natural sciences. For upholders of this point of view, action descriptions may have their own language (that of reasons) and need not be reducible to physicalistic or neurophysiological accounts; but at the end of the day these descriptions must be mappable on to the causal order of nature, which, in contemporary terms, is usually thought to involve either token-token identity or supervenience.3 Moreover, there appears to be much in favor of this approach, since human beings are parts of nature and their intentional actions can be regarded as events in the natural order, even if, considered as actions, they are taken under different descriptions. Nevertheless, not all philosophers have been willing to accept this naturalized conception of agency, which, in one form or another, has been with us at least since the 17th century. One who did not is Immanuel Kant, and it is his views that I shall discuss tonight. My main text will be Kant's famous remark in the Groundwork that \"to every rational being possessed of a will we must also lend the Idea of freedom as the only one under which he can act.\"4 In his metaphysical lectures he makes essentially the same point by claiming that, \"Freedom is a mere Idea and to act according to this Idea is what it means to be free in the practical sense.\" And he adds that, \"Freedom...is practically necessary-man must therefore act according to an Idea of freedom, and he cannot act otherwise.\"5","PeriodicalId":443144,"journal":{"name":"The American Philosophical Association Centennial Series","volume":"138 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"1997-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"21","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"The American Philosophical Association Centennial Series","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.5840/APAPA201372","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 21

Abstract

In his address to the Pacific Division last year, Barry Stroud called attention both to the ubiquity of appeals to naturalism in the contemporary philosophical arena and the lack of anything approaching a consensus concerning the meaning of the term.' As he noted, the varieties of naturalism run the gamut from highly restrictive forms, such as physicalism and naturalized epistemology, which are exceedingly controversial, to more inclusive forms, which preserve their popularity by avoiding a commitment to anything recognizably "naturalistic" beyond the rejection of appeals to the super-natural. In the case of the latter forms, Stroud remarks sensibly, the term 'naturalism' is often reduced to an empty slogan, which could more appropriately be rendered by 'open-mindedness.'2 There is, however, at least one central area of philosophical inquiry where naturalism is not only alive and well but has a fairly determinate sense, namely the question of free will or agency. In spite of an ongoing debate around the edges of this topic, for some time the ruling orthodoxy has been a form of compatibilism that is naturalistic in the sense that it dismisses any account of agency that is not positively related to the framework of nomological explanation operative in the natural sciences. For upholders of this point of view, action descriptions may have their own language (that of reasons) and need not be reducible to physicalistic or neurophysiological accounts; but at the end of the day these descriptions must be mappable on to the causal order of nature, which, in contemporary terms, is usually thought to involve either token-token identity or supervenience.3 Moreover, there appears to be much in favor of this approach, since human beings are parts of nature and their intentional actions can be regarded as events in the natural order, even if, considered as actions, they are taken under different descriptions. Nevertheless, not all philosophers have been willing to accept this naturalized conception of agency, which, in one form or another, has been with us at least since the 17th century. One who did not is Immanuel Kant, and it is his views that I shall discuss tonight. My main text will be Kant's famous remark in the Groundwork that "to every rational being possessed of a will we must also lend the Idea of freedom as the only one under which he can act."4 In his metaphysical lectures he makes essentially the same point by claiming that, "Freedom is a mere Idea and to act according to this Idea is what it means to be free in the practical sense." And he adds that, "Freedom...is practically necessary-man must therefore act according to an Idea of freedom, and he cannot act otherwise."5
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
我们只有在自由的理念下才能行动
在去年的太平洋分部演讲中,巴里·斯特劳德(Barry Stroud)呼吁人们注意当代哲学舞台上对自然主义的普遍诉求,以及对该术语的含义缺乏任何接近共识的东西。正如他所指出的,自然主义的各种形式从高度限制的形式,如物理主义和自然化认识论,这些形式极具争议,到更包容的形式,这些形式通过避免承诺任何可识别的“自然主义”而保持其受欢迎程度,除了拒绝对超自然的呼吁。斯特劳德明智地指出,在后一种形式中,“自然主义”一词经常被简化为空洞的口号,可以更恰当地用“开放思想”来表达。然而,至少有一个哲学研究的中心领域,自然主义不仅活跃,而且具有相当确定的意义,即自由意志或能动性的问题。尽管围绕这一主题的边缘存在着持续的争论,但一段时间以来,主流的正统观点一直是一种自然主义的相容主义形式,即它否定了任何与自然科学中运作的法理学解释框架没有积极联系的代理解释。对于持这种观点的人来说,行为描述可能有自己的语言(理由的语言),不需要简化为物理主义或神经生理学的描述;但在一天结束时,这些描述必须映射到自然的因果秩序,这在当代术语中通常被认为涉及标记-标记身份或监督此外,似乎有很多人赞成这种方法,因为人类是自然的一部分,他们的有意行为可以被视为自然秩序中的事件,即使被视为行动,它们是在不同的描述下发生的。然而,并不是所有的哲学家都愿意接受这种自然化的代理概念,这种概念至少从17世纪以来就以这样或那样的形式出现在我们身边。伊曼努尔·康德不这么认为,今晚我将讨论他的观点。我的主要文本将是康德在《基础》中的著名评论,“对于每一个拥有意志的理性个体,我们也必须赋予自由的理念,作为他唯一能够行动的理念。”在他的形而上学讲座中,他在本质上也提出了同样的观点,他说:“自由不过是一种理念,按照这种理念行动,即是实践意义上的自由。”他还补充道:“自由……因此,人必须按照自由的理念行动,否则他就不能行动。“5
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
The APA Presidential Addresses 1901–1910 Philosophical Legacies of the 1920s Philosophy in America during the 1970s Continental Philosophy: Idealism and Critique,1921–1940 Philosophy in the Age of Fascism: Reflections on the Presidential Addresses of The APA, 1931–1940
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1