How Do We Know That 2 + 2 = 4?

C. Jenkins
{"title":"How Do We Know That 2 + 2 = 4?","authors":"C. Jenkins","doi":"10.4324/9780203703809-8","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"This is a survey chapter about issues in the epistemology of elementary arithmetic. Given the title of this volume, it is worth noting right at the outset that the classification of arithmetic as science is itself philosophically debatable, and that this debate overlaps with debates about the epistemology of arithmetic. It is also important to note that a survey chapter should not be mistaken for a comprehensive, definitive, or unbiased introduction to all that is important about its topic. It is rather an exercise in curation: a selection of material is prepared for display, and the selection process is influenced not only by the author’s personal opinions as to what is interesting and/or worthy, but also by various contingencies of her training, and my survey reflects my training in Anglo-American analytic philosophy of mathematics. Although I’m surveying an area of epistemology, I will classify approaches by metaphysical outlook. The reason for this is that the epistemology and metaphysics of arithmetic are so intimately intertwined that I have generally found it difficult to understand the shape of the epistemological terrain except by reference to the corresponding metaphysical landmarks. For instance, it makes little sense to say that arithmetical knowledge is a kind of “maker’s knowledge” unless arithmetic is in some way mind-dependent, or to classify it as a subspecies of logical knowledge unless arithmetical truth is a species of logical truth. I will be discussing 2+2=4 as an easily-graspable example of an elementary arithmetical truth, our knowledge of which stands in need of philosophical explanation. While some of the surveyed approaches to this explanatory demand proceed by rejecting the presumed explanandum—i.e. by denying that 2+2=4 is known (or even true)—for clarity and ease of expression I will proceed as if 2+2=4 is a known truth except when discussing these approaches. The rest of this chapter proceeds as follows. In the next section, I identify two key challenges for an epistemology of simple arithmetic, and then adduce two constraints on what should count as a successful response. Next, I discuss ways of addressing these challenges, grouped according to their corresponding metaphysical outlook. The subsequent sections survey non-reductive Platonist approaches, look at reductions (often better labelled “identifications”), and consider an array of anti-realist strategies. I conclude with a brief summary, returning to the question of arithmetic’s status as science.","PeriodicalId":183754,"journal":{"name":"What Is Scientific Knowledge?","volume":"52 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2019-06-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"What Is Scientific Knowledge?","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203703809-8","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

This is a survey chapter about issues in the epistemology of elementary arithmetic. Given the title of this volume, it is worth noting right at the outset that the classification of arithmetic as science is itself philosophically debatable, and that this debate overlaps with debates about the epistemology of arithmetic. It is also important to note that a survey chapter should not be mistaken for a comprehensive, definitive, or unbiased introduction to all that is important about its topic. It is rather an exercise in curation: a selection of material is prepared for display, and the selection process is influenced not only by the author’s personal opinions as to what is interesting and/or worthy, but also by various contingencies of her training, and my survey reflects my training in Anglo-American analytic philosophy of mathematics. Although I’m surveying an area of epistemology, I will classify approaches by metaphysical outlook. The reason for this is that the epistemology and metaphysics of arithmetic are so intimately intertwined that I have generally found it difficult to understand the shape of the epistemological terrain except by reference to the corresponding metaphysical landmarks. For instance, it makes little sense to say that arithmetical knowledge is a kind of “maker’s knowledge” unless arithmetic is in some way mind-dependent, or to classify it as a subspecies of logical knowledge unless arithmetical truth is a species of logical truth. I will be discussing 2+2=4 as an easily-graspable example of an elementary arithmetical truth, our knowledge of which stands in need of philosophical explanation. While some of the surveyed approaches to this explanatory demand proceed by rejecting the presumed explanandum—i.e. by denying that 2+2=4 is known (or even true)—for clarity and ease of expression I will proceed as if 2+2=4 is a known truth except when discussing these approaches. The rest of this chapter proceeds as follows. In the next section, I identify two key challenges for an epistemology of simple arithmetic, and then adduce two constraints on what should count as a successful response. Next, I discuss ways of addressing these challenges, grouped according to their corresponding metaphysical outlook. The subsequent sections survey non-reductive Platonist approaches, look at reductions (often better labelled “identifications”), and consider an array of anti-realist strategies. I conclude with a brief summary, returning to the question of arithmetic’s status as science.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
我们怎么知道2 + 2 = 4?
这是关于初等算术认识论问题的概括性章节。鉴于本卷的标题,一开始就值得注意的是,算术作为科学的分类本身在哲学上是有争议的,而且这种辩论与关于算术认识论的辩论重叠。同样重要的是要注意,调查章节不应该被误认为是对其主题的所有重要内容的全面,确定或公正的介绍。这更像是一种策展练习:准备展示的材料选择,选择过程不仅受到作者关于有趣和/或有价值的个人意见的影响,还受到她所受训练的各种偶然事件的影响,我的调查反映了我在英美数学分析哲学方面的训练。虽然我调查的是认识论的一个领域,但我将根据形而上学的观点对方法进行分类。原因在于,算术的认识论和形而上学是如此紧密地交织在一起,以至于我通常发现,除非参考相应的形而上学地标,否则很难理解认识论地形的形状。例如,除非算术在某种程度上依赖于心灵,否则说算术知识是一种“创造者的知识”是没有意义的,或者除非算术真理是逻辑真理的一种,否则把它归类为逻辑知识的亚种是没有意义的。我将把2+2=4作为一个简单易懂的例子来讨论,这是一个基本的算术真理,我们的知识需要哲学的解释。虽然对这种解释性要求的一些调查方法是通过拒绝假定的解释来进行的。通过否认2+2=4是已知的(甚至是正确的)——为了清晰和便于表达,我将继续进行,好像2+2=4是已知的真理,除非在讨论这些方法时。本章其余部分的内容如下。在下一节中,我将确定简单算术认识论面临的两个关键挑战,然后引用两个限制条件,说明什么应该算作成功的回应。接下来,我将讨论解决这些挑战的方法,根据它们相应的形而上学观点进行分组。接下来的章节调查了非还原柏拉图主义的方法,看看还原(通常更好地称为“识别”),并考虑了一系列反现实主义策略。最后,我作一个简短的总结,回到算术作为科学的地位问题上来。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
What Are the Limits of Scientific Explanation? How Do Medical Researchers Make Causal Inferences? Is Science Really Value Free and Objective? How Can We Tell Science from Pseudoscience? What Grounds Do We Have for the Validity of Scientific Findings?
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1