Boundaries and varieties of republicanism

Pub Date : 2023-11-14 DOI:10.1080/13698230.2023.2280946
Adrián Herranz
{"title":"Boundaries and varieties of republicanism","authors":"Adrián Herranz","doi":"10.1080/13698230.2023.2280946","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTThis paper addresses a neglected question in republican political philosophy: what are the conditions for a set of arguments to be considered republican? While republicanism traditionally confers a fundamental role to the democratic ideal of participation in decision-making, recent contributions argue that freedom could be promoted by facilitating exit where possible. The strong version of the latter argument states that when exit is possible, it constitutes the most important contribution to republican freedom, and it preserves the goal of isolating individual choices, i.e. it precludes collective decision-making from interfering with them, and so it intends to limit the scope of public concern considered legitimate. I examine this argument to discuss the boundaries and varieties of republicanism: (i) the boundaries establish that an argument should be couched and substantively articulated in distinctively republican terms; (ii) the strong version of the exit argument does not fall within the boundaries because it is in tension with core republican commitments to self-government and civic virtues; (iii) once we abide by the boundaries we may encounter a diversity of proposals differing on the more concrete level of institutional design and empirical assumptions – these are the varieties of republicanism.KEYWORDS: Republicanismfreedomvirtuedemocracyliberalism AcknowledgementPrevious versions of this paper were presented in Louvain (Chaire Hoover d’éthique économique et sociale), Pavia, and Braga. I am also grateful to Iñigo González-Ricoy, José Luis Martí, Rubén Marciel, Luke Newberry and the anonymous reviewer for their comments.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. By ‘classical liberalism’ (Freeman, Citation2011; De Dijn, Citation2020, pt. 3) I mean the political tradition that builds its core normative requirements around a defence of private property and related ‘economic freedoms’, including thinkers like Constant, Paley, Guizot, Mises, Hayek or Friedman.2. I do not elaborate on cases that may break this general claim, such as increasing our power by being dependent on other agents on which we rely on collective action, or diminishing our power due to collective action problems produced by exit and uncoordinated choices.3. Taylor highlights that the exit view relies on market-coordinated individual preferences rather than collective decisions or bureaucratic discretion (Taylor, Citation2017, pp. 46–49). Lovett initially considered that introducing a basic income involves a strong reform program in the economic sphere, so that it ‘would replace most other public welfare programs, and eliminate the need for much workplace regulation and the minimum wage’ (Lovett, Citation2010, p. 199). Now, he seems more cautious about introducing a more plural institutional design. He stresses the need to curb economic inequality, the empirically determined nature of institutional design and the possibility of a complementary rather than substitutive role for exit measures in the economic sphere (Lovett, Citation2022, p. 118). Section 3 elaborates on further distinctions between Taylor and Lovett.4. We can appreciate an evolution from his earlier work. There, Lovett highlighted that external constraints, like effective rule of law, render power not arbitrary (Lovett, Citation2010, p. 111). Also, he mentioned civic virtue concerning compliance with the law and government oversight when using ballots rather than focusing on its role for a contestatory citizenry (Lovett, Citation2010, p. 216).5. Arguably, some minimal degree of ‘realism’ or non-ideal characterization of politics, as reflected in discussions about power asymmetries and institutional controls, could be part of the core republican commitments (see Pettit, Citation2017).6. We could propose a more flexible version in which the cornerstone of the theory is (1) a reciprocal relation between freedom and virtue. For this paper, and considering the prevalent contemporary interpretation, I will assume the wording of the main text.7. ‘Thicker’ or Aristotelian views of civic virtues value the display of virtue in itself (Pocock, Citation1981; Schwarzenbach, Citation1996), while the ‘thinner’ less perfectionist versions expressed by Pettit (Citation1997) and Skinner (Citation2011) treat it as a functional requirement for freedom. Also, in the Aristotelian view, virtues are certain character traits, while on the thin version that I endorse here, virtues are dispositions that contribute to promoting and assuring the equal status of republican freedom.8. Technically speaking, republicans are motivational pluralists. Recent behavioural science has contested the explanatory primacy of self-interest, arguing that we find a plurality of motivations in human behaviour (Bowles, Citation2016; Frey, Citation1997; Gintis et al., Citation2005; Ostrom, Citation2000). Side by side with self-interest we find intrinsic motivations or social preferences —like reciprocity, commitment, or sympathy—, by which we also place a value both on others’ welfare or interests and on how we relate to them.9. There is an interesting experiment by Falk and Szech (Citation2013) that gives support to the crowding out thesis. In the experiment, the subjects decided between receiving money or saving the life of a mouse in different settings. The study compared the scenario of a person being asked the choice by the interviewers with the scenarios of bilateral and multilateral bargains with other subjects. They discovered that subjects are more prone to accept the killing of the mouse if the decision is taken in a bargain with others (especially in multilateral bargains).10. Civic education is widely acknowledged as a central part of republican thought. Not to mention ancient paideia, it figures notoriously in Rousseau’s writings. I do not focus on this means to create virtue. My point is that the link between institutions and motivations goes beyond civic education and relates to the other aspects I mention, especially the connection between voice and virtue.Additional informationFundingThis work has benefited from an AGAUR FI grant and has been part of the research project “Justice and work: a normative analysis of non-standard work” funded by the Spanish Ministry of Science, Innovation and Universities.Notes on contributorsAdrián HerranzAdrián Herranz is a PhD candidate at Pompeu Fabra University. His research interests include republican political philosophy, economic democracy, labour relations and social theory related to the former topics.","PeriodicalId":0,"journal":{"name":"","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2023.2280946","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

ABSTRACTThis paper addresses a neglected question in republican political philosophy: what are the conditions for a set of arguments to be considered republican? While republicanism traditionally confers a fundamental role to the democratic ideal of participation in decision-making, recent contributions argue that freedom could be promoted by facilitating exit where possible. The strong version of the latter argument states that when exit is possible, it constitutes the most important contribution to republican freedom, and it preserves the goal of isolating individual choices, i.e. it precludes collective decision-making from interfering with them, and so it intends to limit the scope of public concern considered legitimate. I examine this argument to discuss the boundaries and varieties of republicanism: (i) the boundaries establish that an argument should be couched and substantively articulated in distinctively republican terms; (ii) the strong version of the exit argument does not fall within the boundaries because it is in tension with core republican commitments to self-government and civic virtues; (iii) once we abide by the boundaries we may encounter a diversity of proposals differing on the more concrete level of institutional design and empirical assumptions – these are the varieties of republicanism.KEYWORDS: Republicanismfreedomvirtuedemocracyliberalism AcknowledgementPrevious versions of this paper were presented in Louvain (Chaire Hoover d’éthique économique et sociale), Pavia, and Braga. I am also grateful to Iñigo González-Ricoy, José Luis Martí, Rubén Marciel, Luke Newberry and the anonymous reviewer for their comments.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. By ‘classical liberalism’ (Freeman, Citation2011; De Dijn, Citation2020, pt. 3) I mean the political tradition that builds its core normative requirements around a defence of private property and related ‘economic freedoms’, including thinkers like Constant, Paley, Guizot, Mises, Hayek or Friedman.2. I do not elaborate on cases that may break this general claim, such as increasing our power by being dependent on other agents on which we rely on collective action, or diminishing our power due to collective action problems produced by exit and uncoordinated choices.3. Taylor highlights that the exit view relies on market-coordinated individual preferences rather than collective decisions or bureaucratic discretion (Taylor, Citation2017, pp. 46–49). Lovett initially considered that introducing a basic income involves a strong reform program in the economic sphere, so that it ‘would replace most other public welfare programs, and eliminate the need for much workplace regulation and the minimum wage’ (Lovett, Citation2010, p. 199). Now, he seems more cautious about introducing a more plural institutional design. He stresses the need to curb economic inequality, the empirically determined nature of institutional design and the possibility of a complementary rather than substitutive role for exit measures in the economic sphere (Lovett, Citation2022, p. 118). Section 3 elaborates on further distinctions between Taylor and Lovett.4. We can appreciate an evolution from his earlier work. There, Lovett highlighted that external constraints, like effective rule of law, render power not arbitrary (Lovett, Citation2010, p. 111). Also, he mentioned civic virtue concerning compliance with the law and government oversight when using ballots rather than focusing on its role for a contestatory citizenry (Lovett, Citation2010, p. 216).5. Arguably, some minimal degree of ‘realism’ or non-ideal characterization of politics, as reflected in discussions about power asymmetries and institutional controls, could be part of the core republican commitments (see Pettit, Citation2017).6. We could propose a more flexible version in which the cornerstone of the theory is (1) a reciprocal relation between freedom and virtue. For this paper, and considering the prevalent contemporary interpretation, I will assume the wording of the main text.7. ‘Thicker’ or Aristotelian views of civic virtues value the display of virtue in itself (Pocock, Citation1981; Schwarzenbach, Citation1996), while the ‘thinner’ less perfectionist versions expressed by Pettit (Citation1997) and Skinner (Citation2011) treat it as a functional requirement for freedom. Also, in the Aristotelian view, virtues are certain character traits, while on the thin version that I endorse here, virtues are dispositions that contribute to promoting and assuring the equal status of republican freedom.8. Technically speaking, republicans are motivational pluralists. Recent behavioural science has contested the explanatory primacy of self-interest, arguing that we find a plurality of motivations in human behaviour (Bowles, Citation2016; Frey, Citation1997; Gintis et al., Citation2005; Ostrom, Citation2000). Side by side with self-interest we find intrinsic motivations or social preferences —like reciprocity, commitment, or sympathy—, by which we also place a value both on others’ welfare or interests and on how we relate to them.9. There is an interesting experiment by Falk and Szech (Citation2013) that gives support to the crowding out thesis. In the experiment, the subjects decided between receiving money or saving the life of a mouse in different settings. The study compared the scenario of a person being asked the choice by the interviewers with the scenarios of bilateral and multilateral bargains with other subjects. They discovered that subjects are more prone to accept the killing of the mouse if the decision is taken in a bargain with others (especially in multilateral bargains).10. Civic education is widely acknowledged as a central part of republican thought. Not to mention ancient paideia, it figures notoriously in Rousseau’s writings. I do not focus on this means to create virtue. My point is that the link between institutions and motivations goes beyond civic education and relates to the other aspects I mention, especially the connection between voice and virtue.Additional informationFundingThis work has benefited from an AGAUR FI grant and has been part of the research project “Justice and work: a normative analysis of non-standard work” funded by the Spanish Ministry of Science, Innovation and Universities.Notes on contributorsAdrián HerranzAdrián Herranz is a PhD candidate at Pompeu Fabra University. His research interests include republican political philosophy, economic democracy, labour relations and social theory related to the former topics.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
共和主义的边界和多样性
除了自身利益,我们还会发现内在动机或社会偏好——如互惠、承诺或同情——通过这些,我们也会重视他人的福利或利益,以及我们与他人的关系。Falk和Szech (Citation2013)做了一个有趣的实验,为挤出理论提供了支持。在实验中,受试者在不同的环境中决定是接受钱还是拯救一只老鼠的生命。该研究将一个人被面试官要求做出选择的场景与与其他受试者进行双边和多边交易的场景进行了比较。他们发现,如果这个决定是在与他人的交易中做出的(尤其是在多边交易中),实验对象更倾向于接受杀死老鼠的决定。公民教育被广泛认为是共和思想的核心部分。更不用说古代的paideia,它在卢梭的作品中臭名昭著。我不注重这种创造美德的手段。我的观点是,制度和动机之间的联系超出了公民教育的范畴,还涉及到我提到的其他方面,尤其是声音和美德之间的联系。这项工作受益于AGAUR FI资助,是西班牙科学、创新和大学部资助的“正义与工作:非标准工作的规范分析”研究项目的一部分。关于contributorsAdrián HerranzAdrián的说明Herranz是庞培法布拉大学的博士候选人。他的研究兴趣包括共和政治哲学、经济民主、劳资关系以及与前者相关的社会理论。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1