Seeing life steadily: Dorothy Emmet’s philosophy of perception and the crisis in metaphysics

IF 0.8 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY British Journal for the History of Philosophy Pub Date : 2023-09-19 DOI:10.1080/09608788.2023.2256363
Peter West
{"title":"Seeing life steadily: Dorothy Emmet’s philosophy of perception and the crisis in metaphysics","authors":"Peter West","doi":"10.1080/09608788.2023.2256363","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTThe aim of this paper is to outline Dorothy Emmet's (1904–2000) account of perception in The Nature of Metaphysical Thinking (published in 1945). Emmet's account of perception is part of a wider attempt to rehabilitate metaphysics in the face of logical positivism and verificationism (of the kind espoused most famously by A. J. Ayer). It is thus part of an attempt to stem the tide of anti-metaphysical thought that had become widespread in British philosophy by the middle of the twentieth century. Emmet does not fit neatly into the traditional story of twentieth-century British philosophy. She draws on figures like A. N. Whitehead and Henri Bergson much more extensively than figures like Russell or Moore – and thus straddles the so-called ‘analytic-continental divide.’ My aim in this paper is to put Emmet on the map of twentieth-century British thought by outlining her philosophy of perception, highlighting her proposals for a way forward for metaphysics in a time of crisis, and identifying the ways she preempts movements in contemporary philosophy of perception.KEYWORDS: Dorothy EmmetperceptionWhiteheadBergsonmetaphysics AcknowledgementsMany thanks to Matyáš Moravec and Emily Thomas for constructive feedback on earlier versions of this paper. Thanks also to participants at the Wartime Quartet: Significance, Legacy, Spirit conference, organized by the (women) in parenthesis project (Clare Mac Cumhaill and Rachael Wiseman), for feedback on a version of this paper.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 Henceforth, I abbreviate The Nature of Metaphysical Thinking to ‘NMT’.2 Parts of Chapters VII and IX of NMT were previously published as Emmet, “Analogies in Metaphysics”.3 Exceptions include Leemon McHenry’s entry in a chapter on “Whitehead’s Contemporaries” in Handbook of Whiteheadian Process Thought (McHenry, “Whitehead’s Contemporaries”). See also Turner, “Deflated Functionalism” for a paper on Emmet and the sociologist Robert Merton. Emmet also appears briefly in the conclusion of Wiseman, “Metaphysical Thinking”, 91. In this paper, I go further than these papers, which focus on Emmet’s connection to more established figures, and emphasise the degree to which Emmet was an original thinker. Aside from these papers, I am aware of a handful of scholars working on (or who plan to work on) Emmet’s philosophy in the future, including Lawrence Blum. In particular, my reading of The Nature of Metaphysical Thinking was informed by a talk given by Fraser McBride in Durham in 2022 (https://www.womeninparenthesis.co.uk/british-twentieth-century-women-philosophers-on-science/). When it comes to the biographical details of Emmet’s life, alongside McHenry’s paper, I am indebted to obituaries in The Guardian and The Times from 2000.4 Emmet would continue to discuss the topic of perception in her writings on Whitehead and process philosophy (see, e.g. Emmet, “Whitehead and Alexander”), but NMT contains her most sustained discussion of the topic – and is the most revealing when it comes to her own views.5 The notion of ‘bad questions’ in philosophy has also been explored in contemporary scholarship such as, e.g. Taylor and Vickers, “Conceptual Fragmentation”.6 The ‘Epiphany Philosophers’ were primarily interested in the intersection of philosophy with religion and theology. Emmet was clearly interested in such matters prior to her involvement with the group, as evidenced by the fact that she dedicates three chapters of NMT to religious and theological analogies (Chapters V, VI, and VII).7 For a monograph-length treatment of British philosophy during World War Two and its impact on the careers of several women philosophers (most notably, the ‘Wartime Quartet’ of Foot, Anscombe, Murdoch, and Midgley) – and featuring some fleeting glimpses of Emmet (including the time she collected Ghandi from the airport in her Austin 7) – see Mac Cumhaill and Wiseman, Metaphysical Animals.8 For example (these are not Emmet’s examples but my own), a mechanistic materialist metaphysics might inform us that the universe is a complex mechanism, similar to that of a clock, while a panpsychist metaphysics might inform us that there is something it is like to be the universe, similarly to how there is something it is like to be you or me. More formally, though, Emmet claims that metaphysicians employ one of five distinct kinds of analogy: (1) deductive analogies, which start with “the basic pattern of the macrocosm” and deduce more specific truths from there (NMT, 8–9); (2) phenomenological analogies, where one infers from the structure of one’s experiences to the structure of reality (NMT, 9–10; this is closely related to the ‘isomorphic’ theory of perception she later criticises); (3) “probable hypotheses” (NMT, 11), where one conjectures that since some aspect of reality has such and such a nature, reality itself most likely does too (e.g. William Paley’s watchmaker analogy); (4) coordinating analogies, where one borrows a “key idea” from one domain of experience and employs it in another (NTM, 12–13); and finally (5) “existential analogies” or “analogies of being”, which are employed in order to understand “an object in part experienced and in part not experienced” (NMT, 13). Emmet suggests that a statement like ‘God is Light’ is understood via an existential analogy, since we have a good grasp (via experience) of light but do not have a good grasp of God, so must infer that, to some degree, God’s light is like the light we ordinarily experience (NMT, 14).9 Perhaps she had Ayer’s Language, Truth and Logic, which found popular success, in mind here.10 This is also connected to Emmet’s critique of verificationism (and indeed logical positivism more widely). The verificationist’s mistake, she thinks, is to assume that we can appeal to some neutral, or ‘raw’, kind of experience to verify (or falsify) the kinds of statements that, within the verificationist framework, count as meaningful. Many thanks to an anonymous referee for making this reading of the passage clear to me.11 In that sense, Emmet’s view looks somewhat similar to Kant’s view that space and time are forms of intuition. One might also argue that, in line with contemporary philosophy of perception, for Emmet, all perceptual experience includes the perception of ‘K properties’ (Siegel, “Which Properties”). ‘K properties’ are properties that objects have in virtue of being certain kinds of things (e.g. being a tree, or a pine tree, is a K property). But kinds, on this view, are understood in a nominalist sense; they are categories of thought or interpretation, rather than natural kinds.12 Emmet acknowledges a debt here to Henri Bergson. She approvingly cites the following passage from Bergson’s Matter and Memory: “Here is a system of images which I term my perception of the universe, and which may be entirely altered by a very slight change in a certain privileged image – my body” (NMT, 32). I will say more on the role of the body in Emmet’s approach to metaphysics (and Bergson’s influence) in Section Three.13 Again, for Emmet, the verificationist’s mistake is to think there is a way of verifying propositions that is objective, i.e. from something like a ‘God’s-eye’ perspective.14 This move is what Crane and French call “the spreading step” (this terminology originates in Snowdon, “Direct Perception”): the claim that “the same account of experience must apply to veridical experiences as applies to illusory/hallucinatory experiences” (Crane and French, “The Problem of Perception”, §2). Descartes make a similar move in the Meditations when he argues that if the senses deceive us even once (which they do in cases of dreaming, for instance) then we should regard them as unreliable (Descartes, Meditations, 12).15 It is unclear which idealists Emmet has in mind here. There is a reference to ‘the Hegelians’ (although this is part of a quotation from Russell) (NMT, 28) and to Berkeley (NMT, 22–23). In a later chapter, Emmet mentions Hegel, Bradley, and McTaggart (NMT, 199), suggesting that these are the idealists she is familiar with. As Matyáš Moravec pointed out to me, it is noteworthy that Emmet is attacking idealism in 1944, well after its hey-day (at least in Britain). One explanation for this could be that Emmet saw idealism as a live issue and had contemporary idealists in mind when she put forward these criticisms. In turn, that raises the question: Who? However, a more likely explanation is that, in dealing with naïve realism, idealism, and phenomenalism, Emmet is outlining how debates about perception have proceeded historically or offering a genealogy of those debates. This suggestion is supported by the fact that, as I have noted, Emmet does not tend to pick out any specific idealists, but does identify Wittgenstein, Whitehead, and the ‘gestalt psychologists’ as proponents of isomorphism (indicating, in turn, that she sees isomorphism as a live issue rather than a historical one).16 Emmet’s talk of experimental attitudes might be thought of as pre-empting contemporary claims about ‘cognitive attitudes’ in perception. For example, O’Shaughnessy claims that hearing silence, specifically, requires adopting a certain cognitive attitude (O’Shaughnessy, Consciousness and the World, 329) and, in language reminiscent of that employed by Emmet, characterises the act of listening as one in which we “open the door” or “actively make the attention open to influence at the hands of timbre” (O’Shaughnessy, Consciousness and the World, 397).17 Emmet approvingly cites a passage from Whitehead in which he writes: “sense-perception has a factor which is not thought. I call this factor “sense-awareness”” (Whitehead, The Concept of Nature, 3; cited at NMT, 37, fn. 1). The point that Emmet and Whitehead are making here seems similar to G. E. Moore’s claim that, in sensation, alongside the thing sensed (e.g. a blue sensation) we seem to be aware of our ‘consciousness’ of that thing (Moore, “The Refutation of Idealism”, 450). As Ian Phillips puts it, for Moore, there is a “distinct element in all conscious experience, namely, the relation of conscious awareness itself” (Phillips, “Hearing and Hallucinating Silence”, 345). Phillips thinks Moore is right about this and, on this basis (namely that “listing the objects of experience” does not suffice “to characterize experience” (Phillips, “Hearing and Hallucinating Silence”, 345)), argues that since we can become aware of ourselves as hearing silence (even though such perceptual experiences lack an object) this means that silence is something that can truly be said to be heard. Thanks to an anonymous referee for noting these similarities.18 She has something like Kant’s distinction between the phenomenal and the noumenal in mind here.19 Note that while Emmet acknowledges a debt to Whitehead (and was clearly influenced by his ‘process philosophy’) it is not right to think of her as simply a ‘disciple’. She explicitly seeks to move away from his account of perception (as she reads it) in NMT.20 One might push back against Emmet’s claim here. It might be argued that the structure of a written word, for example, does reflect the structure of its spoken counterpart. The written word ‘Yes’ has one syllable, reflecting the monosyllabic sound of ‘Yes’ as spoken. The written word ‘glockenspiel’, meanwhile, is longer and reflects the three syllables of the spoken word. But it seems likely that Emmet has in mind the relation between words (written or spoken) and their meanings, where (contrary to, e.g. Platonic naturalism about words) the relation does seem to be purely arbitrary.21 Emmet notes that “Russell at one time advocated that a logical language should be so constructed that the word order of a sentence should always exhibit the spatio-temporal order of the things being talked about” (NMT, 58). However, she also notes that even Russell denied that this was the case in natural languages. And yet that does not undermine their validity as languages, and thus as systems of sign-usage (and, in turn, symbols).22 At least, it cannot be solved without resource to phenomenalism or idealism – two positions that Emmet has already shown to be flawed.23 As well as Whitehead, it seems likely that Emmet’s view is influenced by Samuel Alexander – particularly his notion of ‘compresence’ which looks similar to Whitehead’s notion of ‘prehension’ (see Thomas, “Samuel Alexander”, 3.1 for discussion – and thanks to Emily Thomas for pointing out the possible connection here). Alexander maintains that “There is nothing peculiar in the relation itself between mind and its objects; what is peculiar in the situation is the character of one of the terms, its being mind or consciousness. The relation is one of compresence. But there is [also] compresence between two physical things” (Alexander, “The Basis of Realism”, 288). In that sense, Alexander claims, “The relation of mind and object is comparable to that between table and floor”. Alexander’s influence on Emmet is evidenced by (e.g.) her Samuel Hall Oration lecture from 1950, titled “Time is the Mind of Space”, which is dedicated to him (Emmet, “Mind of Space”, 225). Alexander is also referenced several times in The Nature of Metaphysical Thinking (e.g. NMT, 21, 192, 218). Looking ahead towards the end of this section, where I make the case for Bergson’s influence on Emmet, it is worth noting that Alexander (like Whitehead) draws on Bergson in his Space, Time, and Deity (e.g. Alexander, Space, Time, and Deity, 36, 44, 140, 148). Alexander also reviewed Bergson’s Matter and Memory (Alexander, Matière et Mémoire).24 Like Whitehead, Emmet maintains that philosophers of perception have been misled by the fact that we talk as though cases of perceptual experience involved a Subject-Object dichotomy (e.g. we say things like ‘I saw the moon’). Whitehead claims that those who make such an inference – from how we speak to what must be the case – commit ‘the fallacy of misplaced concreteness’, i.e., they mistakenly take themselves to be picking out some concrete features of reality (Whitehead, Modern World, 66 & 74) (many thanks to an anonymous referee for pointing this out). This is the same (erroneous) inferential move that Susan Stebbing calls the ‘fallacy of the substantive’ (Stebbing, “Some Ambiguities”, 117).25 It is radical, but only if viewed from a particular standpoint (namely, traditional approaches to the mind-world relation and the problem of perception), for it has precedents. As we have seen, Emmet draws on the work of Whitehead and Alexander. Bergson, who is cited by Emmet in various places (e.g. NMT, 51, 56, 62, 237) and who influenced Whitehead and Alexander, similarly argues against the Subject-Object distinction (e.g. Bergson, Matter and Memory, vii).26 In this way, Emmet’s project resembles that of G. E. Anscombe in “The Intentionality of Sensation” (Anscombe, “Intentionality of Sensation”; for discussion, see Mac Cumhaill and Wiseman, Metaphysical Animals). Both Anscombe and Emmet agree that there is a reason that the debate between direct (naïve) realists and indirect realists has not been settled – which is that both are trying to answer a ‘bad question’: namely, how the human mind cognizes the external world and what the tripartite relation of mind-mental object-external thing looks like. Emmet and Anscombe’s views differ, however, when it comes to what we should be doing. Anscombe defends a ‘grammatical’ approach to sensation, arguing that the focus ought to be on understanding our (verbal) reports of perceptual experiences, as well as those other forms of life that are shaped by the concept of sensation. Doing so, Anscombe maintains, can in turn reveal the structure of sensation itself. Emmet is less interested in moving away from metaphysical or ontological questions about perception than Anscombe, but nonetheless agrees that we ought to move on from traditional approaches to understanding perception in terms of a subject-object dichotomy. See also Margaret Macdonald’s “Linguistic Philosophy and Perception” where she also sets out to diagnose why debates in the philosophy of perception do not seem to “progress”. Like Anscombe, Macdonald (who also studied with Wittgenstein) suggests that “linguistic philosophy” may offer a way forward.27 There is also a case to be made for including Heidegger as one of the influences on Emmet’s view. Emmet identifies similarities between Heidegger and Whitehead’s approaches to perception. For example, she writes that “[a]lthough the final outcome and emphasis of his philosophy is very different from Whitehead’s, both Heidegger and Whitehead are starting from an analysis … of a subject of experience as arising out of a way of feeling its world” (NMT, 65).28 It is also worth noting that Emmet’s tutor in Oxford, A. D. Lindsay, wrote a book on Bergson (Lindsay, The Philosophy of Bergson) which Emmet may have read. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pointing this out.29 Samuel Alexander, in his review of Matter and Memory, compares Bergson’s ‘images’ to Lockean ‘ideas’, but the comparison with Emmet’s ‘interpretations’ seems closer since Bergson’s images are involved in actively shaping our perception of reality (Alexander, Matière et Mémoire, 572).30 There is more that could be said about the similarities between Bergson and Emmet, and I think a stronger case could be made for a causal connection. The question of why Emmet does not cite Bergson anywhere near as extensively as Whitehead is also worth addressing. The answer may lie in the fate of Bergson’s philosophy in Anglophone philosophy, especially after the publication of Russell’s “The Philosophy of Bergson”. For example, Matyáš Moravec argues that from the 1930s and 1940s onwards, Bergson’s philosophy began to be “treated with suspicion” (Moravec, “Taking Time Seriously”, 2; see also Vrahamis, “Russell’s Critique”). It may well be that, in line with trend, Emmet simply wished to avoid paying too much deference to Bergson’s philosophy.31 Not only is this important for understanding Emmet’s position from a historical perspective but this is also an aspect of Emmet’s view that might be taken up by contemporary philosophers of perception. Debates in (analytic) philosophy of perception still typically resemblance the debates that Emmet is critical of (see, e.g. Crane and French, “The Problem of Perception”). Those readers who are sympathetic to Emmet’s criticisms of such debates might look to her own approach as a way forward – and the ‘accusative’ versus ‘accusative’ perception distinction is an important part of that approach.","PeriodicalId":51792,"journal":{"name":"British Journal for the History of Philosophy","volume":"176 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-09-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"British Journal for the History of Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/09608788.2023.2256363","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

ABSTRACTThe aim of this paper is to outline Dorothy Emmet's (1904–2000) account of perception in The Nature of Metaphysical Thinking (published in 1945). Emmet's account of perception is part of a wider attempt to rehabilitate metaphysics in the face of logical positivism and verificationism (of the kind espoused most famously by A. J. Ayer). It is thus part of an attempt to stem the tide of anti-metaphysical thought that had become widespread in British philosophy by the middle of the twentieth century. Emmet does not fit neatly into the traditional story of twentieth-century British philosophy. She draws on figures like A. N. Whitehead and Henri Bergson much more extensively than figures like Russell or Moore – and thus straddles the so-called ‘analytic-continental divide.’ My aim in this paper is to put Emmet on the map of twentieth-century British thought by outlining her philosophy of perception, highlighting her proposals for a way forward for metaphysics in a time of crisis, and identifying the ways she preempts movements in contemporary philosophy of perception.KEYWORDS: Dorothy EmmetperceptionWhiteheadBergsonmetaphysics AcknowledgementsMany thanks to Matyáš Moravec and Emily Thomas for constructive feedback on earlier versions of this paper. Thanks also to participants at the Wartime Quartet: Significance, Legacy, Spirit conference, organized by the (women) in parenthesis project (Clare Mac Cumhaill and Rachael Wiseman), for feedback on a version of this paper.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 Henceforth, I abbreviate The Nature of Metaphysical Thinking to ‘NMT’.2 Parts of Chapters VII and IX of NMT were previously published as Emmet, “Analogies in Metaphysics”.3 Exceptions include Leemon McHenry’s entry in a chapter on “Whitehead’s Contemporaries” in Handbook of Whiteheadian Process Thought (McHenry, “Whitehead’s Contemporaries”). See also Turner, “Deflated Functionalism” for a paper on Emmet and the sociologist Robert Merton. Emmet also appears briefly in the conclusion of Wiseman, “Metaphysical Thinking”, 91. In this paper, I go further than these papers, which focus on Emmet’s connection to more established figures, and emphasise the degree to which Emmet was an original thinker. Aside from these papers, I am aware of a handful of scholars working on (or who plan to work on) Emmet’s philosophy in the future, including Lawrence Blum. In particular, my reading of The Nature of Metaphysical Thinking was informed by a talk given by Fraser McBride in Durham in 2022 (https://www.womeninparenthesis.co.uk/british-twentieth-century-women-philosophers-on-science/). When it comes to the biographical details of Emmet’s life, alongside McHenry’s paper, I am indebted to obituaries in The Guardian and The Times from 2000.4 Emmet would continue to discuss the topic of perception in her writings on Whitehead and process philosophy (see, e.g. Emmet, “Whitehead and Alexander”), but NMT contains her most sustained discussion of the topic – and is the most revealing when it comes to her own views.5 The notion of ‘bad questions’ in philosophy has also been explored in contemporary scholarship such as, e.g. Taylor and Vickers, “Conceptual Fragmentation”.6 The ‘Epiphany Philosophers’ were primarily interested in the intersection of philosophy with religion and theology. Emmet was clearly interested in such matters prior to her involvement with the group, as evidenced by the fact that she dedicates three chapters of NMT to religious and theological analogies (Chapters V, VI, and VII).7 For a monograph-length treatment of British philosophy during World War Two and its impact on the careers of several women philosophers (most notably, the ‘Wartime Quartet’ of Foot, Anscombe, Murdoch, and Midgley) – and featuring some fleeting glimpses of Emmet (including the time she collected Ghandi from the airport in her Austin 7) – see Mac Cumhaill and Wiseman, Metaphysical Animals.8 For example (these are not Emmet’s examples but my own), a mechanistic materialist metaphysics might inform us that the universe is a complex mechanism, similar to that of a clock, while a panpsychist metaphysics might inform us that there is something it is like to be the universe, similarly to how there is something it is like to be you or me. More formally, though, Emmet claims that metaphysicians employ one of five distinct kinds of analogy: (1) deductive analogies, which start with “the basic pattern of the macrocosm” and deduce more specific truths from there (NMT, 8–9); (2) phenomenological analogies, where one infers from the structure of one’s experiences to the structure of reality (NMT, 9–10; this is closely related to the ‘isomorphic’ theory of perception she later criticises); (3) “probable hypotheses” (NMT, 11), where one conjectures that since some aspect of reality has such and such a nature, reality itself most likely does too (e.g. William Paley’s watchmaker analogy); (4) coordinating analogies, where one borrows a “key idea” from one domain of experience and employs it in another (NTM, 12–13); and finally (5) “existential analogies” or “analogies of being”, which are employed in order to understand “an object in part experienced and in part not experienced” (NMT, 13). Emmet suggests that a statement like ‘God is Light’ is understood via an existential analogy, since we have a good grasp (via experience) of light but do not have a good grasp of God, so must infer that, to some degree, God’s light is like the light we ordinarily experience (NMT, 14).9 Perhaps she had Ayer’s Language, Truth and Logic, which found popular success, in mind here.10 This is also connected to Emmet’s critique of verificationism (and indeed logical positivism more widely). The verificationist’s mistake, she thinks, is to assume that we can appeal to some neutral, or ‘raw’, kind of experience to verify (or falsify) the kinds of statements that, within the verificationist framework, count as meaningful. Many thanks to an anonymous referee for making this reading of the passage clear to me.11 In that sense, Emmet’s view looks somewhat similar to Kant’s view that space and time are forms of intuition. One might also argue that, in line with contemporary philosophy of perception, for Emmet, all perceptual experience includes the perception of ‘K properties’ (Siegel, “Which Properties”). ‘K properties’ are properties that objects have in virtue of being certain kinds of things (e.g. being a tree, or a pine tree, is a K property). But kinds, on this view, are understood in a nominalist sense; they are categories of thought or interpretation, rather than natural kinds.12 Emmet acknowledges a debt here to Henri Bergson. She approvingly cites the following passage from Bergson’s Matter and Memory: “Here is a system of images which I term my perception of the universe, and which may be entirely altered by a very slight change in a certain privileged image – my body” (NMT, 32). I will say more on the role of the body in Emmet’s approach to metaphysics (and Bergson’s influence) in Section Three.13 Again, for Emmet, the verificationist’s mistake is to think there is a way of verifying propositions that is objective, i.e. from something like a ‘God’s-eye’ perspective.14 This move is what Crane and French call “the spreading step” (this terminology originates in Snowdon, “Direct Perception”): the claim that “the same account of experience must apply to veridical experiences as applies to illusory/hallucinatory experiences” (Crane and French, “The Problem of Perception”, §2). Descartes make a similar move in the Meditations when he argues that if the senses deceive us even once (which they do in cases of dreaming, for instance) then we should regard them as unreliable (Descartes, Meditations, 12).15 It is unclear which idealists Emmet has in mind here. There is a reference to ‘the Hegelians’ (although this is part of a quotation from Russell) (NMT, 28) and to Berkeley (NMT, 22–23). In a later chapter, Emmet mentions Hegel, Bradley, and McTaggart (NMT, 199), suggesting that these are the idealists she is familiar with. As Matyáš Moravec pointed out to me, it is noteworthy that Emmet is attacking idealism in 1944, well after its hey-day (at least in Britain). One explanation for this could be that Emmet saw idealism as a live issue and had contemporary idealists in mind when she put forward these criticisms. In turn, that raises the question: Who? However, a more likely explanation is that, in dealing with naïve realism, idealism, and phenomenalism, Emmet is outlining how debates about perception have proceeded historically or offering a genealogy of those debates. This suggestion is supported by the fact that, as I have noted, Emmet does not tend to pick out any specific idealists, but does identify Wittgenstein, Whitehead, and the ‘gestalt psychologists’ as proponents of isomorphism (indicating, in turn, that she sees isomorphism as a live issue rather than a historical one).16 Emmet’s talk of experimental attitudes might be thought of as pre-empting contemporary claims about ‘cognitive attitudes’ in perception. For example, O’Shaughnessy claims that hearing silence, specifically, requires adopting a certain cognitive attitude (O’Shaughnessy, Consciousness and the World, 329) and, in language reminiscent of that employed by Emmet, characterises the act of listening as one in which we “open the door” or “actively make the attention open to influence at the hands of timbre” (O’Shaughnessy, Consciousness and the World, 397).17 Emmet approvingly cites a passage from Whitehead in which he writes: “sense-perception has a factor which is not thought. I call this factor “sense-awareness”” (Whitehead, The Concept of Nature, 3; cited at NMT, 37, fn. 1). The point that Emmet and Whitehead are making here seems similar to G. E. Moore’s claim that, in sensation, alongside the thing sensed (e.g. a blue sensation) we seem to be aware of our ‘consciousness’ of that thing (Moore, “The Refutation of Idealism”, 450). As Ian Phillips puts it, for Moore, there is a “distinct element in all conscious experience, namely, the relation of conscious awareness itself” (Phillips, “Hearing and Hallucinating Silence”, 345). Phillips thinks Moore is right about this and, on this basis (namely that “listing the objects of experience” does not suffice “to characterize experience” (Phillips, “Hearing and Hallucinating Silence”, 345)), argues that since we can become aware of ourselves as hearing silence (even though such perceptual experiences lack an object) this means that silence is something that can truly be said to be heard. Thanks to an anonymous referee for noting these similarities.18 She has something like Kant’s distinction between the phenomenal and the noumenal in mind here.19 Note that while Emmet acknowledges a debt to Whitehead (and was clearly influenced by his ‘process philosophy’) it is not right to think of her as simply a ‘disciple’. She explicitly seeks to move away from his account of perception (as she reads it) in NMT.20 One might push back against Emmet’s claim here. It might be argued that the structure of a written word, for example, does reflect the structure of its spoken counterpart. The written word ‘Yes’ has one syllable, reflecting the monosyllabic sound of ‘Yes’ as spoken. The written word ‘glockenspiel’, meanwhile, is longer and reflects the three syllables of the spoken word. But it seems likely that Emmet has in mind the relation between words (written or spoken) and their meanings, where (contrary to, e.g. Platonic naturalism about words) the relation does seem to be purely arbitrary.21 Emmet notes that “Russell at one time advocated that a logical language should be so constructed that the word order of a sentence should always exhibit the spatio-temporal order of the things being talked about” (NMT, 58). However, she also notes that even Russell denied that this was the case in natural languages. And yet that does not undermine their validity as languages, and thus as systems of sign-usage (and, in turn, symbols).22 At least, it cannot be solved without resource to phenomenalism or idealism – two positions that Emmet has already shown to be flawed.23 As well as Whitehead, it seems likely that Emmet’s view is influenced by Samuel Alexander – particularly his notion of ‘compresence’ which looks similar to Whitehead’s notion of ‘prehension’ (see Thomas, “Samuel Alexander”, 3.1 for discussion – and thanks to Emily Thomas for pointing out the possible connection here). Alexander maintains that “There is nothing peculiar in the relation itself between mind and its objects; what is peculiar in the situation is the character of one of the terms, its being mind or consciousness. The relation is one of compresence. But there is [also] compresence between two physical things” (Alexander, “The Basis of Realism”, 288). In that sense, Alexander claims, “The relation of mind and object is comparable to that between table and floor”. Alexander’s influence on Emmet is evidenced by (e.g.) her Samuel Hall Oration lecture from 1950, titled “Time is the Mind of Space”, which is dedicated to him (Emmet, “Mind of Space”, 225). Alexander is also referenced several times in The Nature of Metaphysical Thinking (e.g. NMT, 21, 192, 218). Looking ahead towards the end of this section, where I make the case for Bergson’s influence on Emmet, it is worth noting that Alexander (like Whitehead) draws on Bergson in his Space, Time, and Deity (e.g. Alexander, Space, Time, and Deity, 36, 44, 140, 148). Alexander also reviewed Bergson’s Matter and Memory (Alexander, Matière et Mémoire).24 Like Whitehead, Emmet maintains that philosophers of perception have been misled by the fact that we talk as though cases of perceptual experience involved a Subject-Object dichotomy (e.g. we say things like ‘I saw the moon’). Whitehead claims that those who make such an inference – from how we speak to what must be the case – commit ‘the fallacy of misplaced concreteness’, i.e., they mistakenly take themselves to be picking out some concrete features of reality (Whitehead, Modern World, 66 & 74) (many thanks to an anonymous referee for pointing this out). This is the same (erroneous) inferential move that Susan Stebbing calls the ‘fallacy of the substantive’ (Stebbing, “Some Ambiguities”, 117).25 It is radical, but only if viewed from a particular standpoint (namely, traditional approaches to the mind-world relation and the problem of perception), for it has precedents. As we have seen, Emmet draws on the work of Whitehead and Alexander. Bergson, who is cited by Emmet in various places (e.g. NMT, 51, 56, 62, 237) and who influenced Whitehead and Alexander, similarly argues against the Subject-Object distinction (e.g. Bergson, Matter and Memory, vii).26 In this way, Emmet’s project resembles that of G. E. Anscombe in “The Intentionality of Sensation” (Anscombe, “Intentionality of Sensation”; for discussion, see Mac Cumhaill and Wiseman, Metaphysical Animals). Both Anscombe and Emmet agree that there is a reason that the debate between direct (naïve) realists and indirect realists has not been settled – which is that both are trying to answer a ‘bad question’: namely, how the human mind cognizes the external world and what the tripartite relation of mind-mental object-external thing looks like. Emmet and Anscombe’s views differ, however, when it comes to what we should be doing. Anscombe defends a ‘grammatical’ approach to sensation, arguing that the focus ought to be on understanding our (verbal) reports of perceptual experiences, as well as those other forms of life that are shaped by the concept of sensation. Doing so, Anscombe maintains, can in turn reveal the structure of sensation itself. Emmet is less interested in moving away from metaphysical or ontological questions about perception than Anscombe, but nonetheless agrees that we ought to move on from traditional approaches to understanding perception in terms of a subject-object dichotomy. See also Margaret Macdonald’s “Linguistic Philosophy and Perception” where she also sets out to diagnose why debates in the philosophy of perception do not seem to “progress”. Like Anscombe, Macdonald (who also studied with Wittgenstein) suggests that “linguistic philosophy” may offer a way forward.27 There is also a case to be made for including Heidegger as one of the influences on Emmet’s view. Emmet identifies similarities between Heidegger and Whitehead’s approaches to perception. For example, she writes that “[a]lthough the final outcome and emphasis of his philosophy is very different from Whitehead’s, both Heidegger and Whitehead are starting from an analysis … of a subject of experience as arising out of a way of feeling its world” (NMT, 65).28 It is also worth noting that Emmet’s tutor in Oxford, A. D. Lindsay, wrote a book on Bergson (Lindsay, The Philosophy of Bergson) which Emmet may have read. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pointing this out.29 Samuel Alexander, in his review of Matter and Memory, compares Bergson’s ‘images’ to Lockean ‘ideas’, but the comparison with Emmet’s ‘interpretations’ seems closer since Bergson’s images are involved in actively shaping our perception of reality (Alexander, Matière et Mémoire, 572).30 There is more that could be said about the similarities between Bergson and Emmet, and I think a stronger case could be made for a causal connection. The question of why Emmet does not cite Bergson anywhere near as extensively as Whitehead is also worth addressing. The answer may lie in the fate of Bergson’s philosophy in Anglophone philosophy, especially after the publication of Russell’s “The Philosophy of Bergson”. For example, Matyáš Moravec argues that from the 1930s and 1940s onwards, Bergson’s philosophy began to be “treated with suspicion” (Moravec, “Taking Time Seriously”, 2; see also Vrahamis, “Russell’s Critique”). It may well be that, in line with trend, Emmet simply wished to avoid paying too much deference to Bergson’s philosophy.31 Not only is this important for understanding Emmet’s position from a historical perspective but this is also an aspect of Emmet’s view that might be taken up by contemporary philosophers of perception. Debates in (analytic) philosophy of perception still typically resemblance the debates that Emmet is critical of (see, e.g. Crane and French, “The Problem of Perception”). Those readers who are sympathetic to Emmet’s criticisms of such debates might look to her own approach as a way forward – and the ‘accusative’ versus ‘accusative’ perception distinction is an important part of that approach.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
稳定地看待生活:多萝西·埃米特的感知哲学与形而上学的危机
在这方面,埃米特的计划类似于g.e.安斯科姆在“感觉的意向性”中的计划(安斯科姆,“感觉的意向性”;有关讨论,请参见Mac Cumhaill和Wiseman的《形而上学的动物》)。Anscombe和Emmet都认为,直接现实主义者(naïve)和间接现实主义者之间的争论没有得到解决是有原因的,因为他们都在试图回答一个“糟糕的问题”:即,人类的心灵是如何认识外部世界的,以及心灵-精神客体-外部事物的三方关系是什么样子的。然而,当谈到我们应该做什么时,埃米特和安斯库姆的观点不同。安斯库姆为感觉的“语法”方法辩护,认为重点应该放在理解我们对感知体验的(口头)报告,以及那些由感觉概念塑造的其他生活形式上。安斯库姆认为,这样做反过来可以揭示感觉本身的结构。与安斯库姆相比,埃米特对远离关于知觉的形而上学或本体论问题不太感兴趣,但他仍然同意,我们应该从传统的方法出发,从主客体二分法的角度来理解知觉。参见玛格丽特·麦克唐纳的《语言哲学与感知》,她在书中也着手诊断为什么感知哲学的辩论似乎没有“进步”。和安斯库姆一样,麦克唐纳(他也曾师从维特根斯坦)认为“语言哲学”可能会提供一条前进的道路我们也可以将海德格尔作为影响埃米特观点的因素之一。埃米特指出了海德格尔和怀特海在感知方法上的相似之处。例如,她写道:“尽管海德格尔哲学的最终结果和重点与怀特黑德的非常不同,但海德格尔和怀特黑德都是从对经验主体的分析开始的……这种分析源于对世界的一种感受方式”(NMT, 65)同样值得注意的是,埃米特在牛津的导师a . D. Lindsay写了一本关于柏格森的书(Lindsay, The Philosophy of Bergson),埃米特可能读过。感谢一位匿名的裁判指出了这一点塞缪尔·亚历山大(Samuel Alexander)在他的《物质与记忆》(Matter and Memory)评论中,将柏格森的“图像”与洛克的“观念”进行了比较,但与埃米特的“解释”的比较似乎更接近,因为柏格森的图像积极地塑造了我们对现实的感知(Alexander, mati<s:1> re et m<s:1> moire, 572)关于柏格森和埃米特之间的相似之处,还有更多可说的,我认为可以提出一个更有力的因果关系的案例。为什么埃米特没有像怀特黑德那样广泛地引用柏格森,这个问题也值得探讨。答案可能在于柏格森哲学在英语哲学中的命运,尤其是在罗素的《柏格森哲学》出版之后。例如,Matyáš Moravec认为,从20世纪30年代和40年代开始,柏格森的哲学开始被“怀疑对待”(Moravec,“Taking Time Seriously”,2;参见弗拉哈米斯的《罗素的批判》)。很可能,为了顺应潮流,埃米特只是希望避免对柏格森的哲学给予过多的尊重这不仅对从历史的角度理解埃米特的立场很重要,而且这也是埃米特观点的一个方面,可能会被当代感知哲学家所接受。(分析)感知哲学的辩论仍然典型地类似于埃米特所批评的辩论(参见,例如Crane和French,“感知问题”)。那些同情埃米特对这种辩论的批评的读者可能会把她自己的方法看作是一种前进的方式——“指责”和“指责”感知的区别是这种方法的重要组成部分。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
1.10
自引率
16.70%
发文量
78
期刊介绍: BJHP publishes articles and reviews on the history of philosophy and related intellectual history from the ancient world to the end of the 20th Century. The journal is designed to foster understanding of the history of philosophy through studying the texts of past philosophers in the context - intellectual, political and social - in which the text was created. Although focusing on the recognized classics, a feature of the journal is to give attention to less major figures and to disciplines other than philosophy which impinge on the history of philosophy including political theory, religion and the natural sciences in so far as they illuminate the history of philosophy.
期刊最新文献
Peter of Mantua and the ‘piecemeal’ conception of substantial change* A taxonomy of divisibilism and Gregory of Rimini’s place Helen Knight and Margaret Macdonald on the meaning of ‘good’ Du Châtelet's causal idealism A resolute reading of Iris Murdoch’s Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1