Political Reasoning and the Nation-State: A MacIntyrean Consideration of a Thomistic Debate

Q4 Social Sciences Perspectives on Political Science Pub Date : 2023-09-18 DOI:10.1080/10457097.2023.2255097
John Macias
{"title":"Political Reasoning and the Nation-State: A MacIntyrean Consideration of a Thomistic Debate","authors":"John Macias","doi":"10.1080/10457097.2023.2255097","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"AbstractThe Traditional Natural Law (TNL) considers the political community a good human beings desire as one of the greatest goods of practical life, while those within the New Natural Law (NNL) camp argue instead that the political community is an instrumental good. Neither side has been able to offer a decisive refutation of the other, despite each offering strong arguments supported by both philosophical argument and textual evidence. In response, I will present Alasdair MacIntyre’s approach to practical reason and political community in hopes of shedding new light on this debate. From a MacIntyrean perspective, the TNL and NNL disagreement is more apparent than real, because the two sides in fact address different objects. MacIntyre presents political community as a constitutive aspect of excellent practical reasoning, but he denies the modern nation-state can be such a community. Disclosure StatementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Theories of Natural Law in the Culture of Advanced Modernity,” in Common Truths: New Perspectives in Natural Law, ed. Edward B. McLean (Wilmington, Delaware: ISI Books, 200), 94. See also Alasdair MacIntyre, “Intractable Moral Disagreements,” in Intractable Disputes about the Natural Law: Alasdair MacIntyre and Critics, ed. Lawrence S. Cunningham (Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 2009), 1–52.2 MacIntyre, “Theories of Natural Law,” 92.3 For the background of this debate, see Germain Grisez, “The First Principle of Practical Reason: A Commentary on the Summa Theologiae, 1–2, Question 94, Article 2,” in Aquinas: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Anthony Kenny (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1976), 340–382; Ralph McInerny, Aquinas on Human Action: A Theory of Practice (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1); Christopher Tollefsen, “The New Natural Law Theory,” Lyceum 10, (2008): 1–17; John Finnis, Aquinas: Moral, Political, and Legal Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998); Steven Jensen, Knowing the Natural Law: From Precepts and Inclinations to Deriving Oughts (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 2015); John Macias, “John Finnis and Alasdair MacIntyre on Our Knowledge of the Precepts of Natural Law,” Res Philosophica 93 (2016): 103–123; Ryan T. Anderson, editor, “Defense of the New Natural Law,” National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly (2019): 165–329.4 John Finnis, “Is Natural Law Theory Compatible with Limited Government?,” in Natural Law, Liberalism, and Morality, ed. Robert P. George (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), 5.5 Finnis, Aquinas, 247.6 Ibid, 247–248.7 Michael Pakaluk, “Is the Common Good of Political Society Limited and Instrumental?” The Review of Metaphysics 55 (2001): 91.8 John Goyette, “On the Transcendence of the Political Common Good: Aquinas versus the New Natural Law Theory,” The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 13 (2013): 155.9 Goyette, 141; Pakaluk, “Common Good of Political Society,” 9310 Finnis, Aquinas: Moral, Political, and Legal Theory, 235.11 Ibid, 235–237.12 St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, II-II, q.101, a.1 (Rome: Editiones Paulinae, 1962), 1512.13 Thomas Osborne, “MacIntyre, Thomism and the Contemporary Common Good,” Analyse & Kritik 30 (2008): 84.14 Daniel Mark, “New Natural Law Theory and the Common Good of the Political Community,” National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 19 (2019): 299. Mark, “New Natural Law Theory,” 299.15 Ibid.16 Finnis, Aquinas: Moral, Political, and Legal Theory, 226–227.17 Alasdair MacIntyre, Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity: An Essay on Desire, Practical Reasoning, and Narrative (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2016), 51. Alasdair MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues (Chicago: Open Court, 1999), 107.18 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” in The MacIntyre Reader, ed. Kelvin Knight (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1998), 240. For commentators on MacIntyre’s emphasis on practical reasoning, see Christopher Stephen Lutz, Reading Alasdair MacIntyre’s After Virtue (New York: Continuum International Publishing Group, 2012) and “Alasdair MacIntyre’s Ethics of Practical Reasoning: Morality in Practice,” Politics & Poetics 4 (2018); Kelvin Knight, Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2007); Caleb Bernacchio and Kelvin Knight, “MacIntyre and Political Philosophy,” in Learning from MacIntyre, ed. Ron Beadle and Geoff Moore (Eugene, Oregon: Pickwick Publications, 2020), 117–139.19 Alasdair MacIntyre, “How Aristotelianism can become Revolutionary: Ethics, Resistance, and Utopia,” Virtue and Politics: Alasdair MacIntyre’s Revolutionary Aristotelianism, ed. Paul Blackledge and Kelvin Knight (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2011), 1620 MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 241.21 Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2007), 187.22 Jeffrey L. Nicholas, “Who Stands for Un̳čí Makhá: The Liberal Nation-State, Racism, Freedom, and Nature,” in Liberty and the Ecological Crisis: Freedom on a Finite Planet, eds. Christhoper J. Orr, Kaitlin Kish, and Bruce Jennings (Oxfordshire, UK: Routledge, 2019), 114.23 MacIntyre “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 248.24 MacIntyre, “Intractable Moral Disagreements,” 23.25 MacIntyre, “Theories of Natural Law in the Cultures of Adavnced Modernity,” 93. See also MacIntyre, Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity, 89; MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 247; MacIntyre, “Natural Law as Subversive,” 48.26 MacIntyre, “Natural Law as Subversive,” 49.27 MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 248.28 MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals, 135–136.29 Ibid, 108.30 Gregory Froelich, “The Equivocal Status of Bonum Commune” The New Scholasticism 63 (1989): 38–57.31 MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals, 108.32 Ibid, 123.33 MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 242.34 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Poetry as Political Philosophy: Notes on Burke and Yeats,” in Ethics and Politics: Selected Essays, Volume 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 206), 163. See also Alasdair MacIntyre, “A Partial Response to my Critics,” in After MacIntyre: Critical Perspectives on the Work of Alasdair MacIntyre, ed. John Horton and Susan Mendus (Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1994), 303.35 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Is Patriotism a Virtue?” (Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas, 1984), 13.36 Ibid, 11.37 MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 236. For commentators on MacIntyre’s critique of the nation-state, see Mark C. Murphy, “MacIntyre’s Political Philosophy,” in Alasdair MacIntyre, ed. Mark C. Murphy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 152–175; Peter McMylor, “Compartmentalization and Social Roles: MacIntyre’s Critical Theory of Modernity,” in Virtue and Politics: Alasdair MacIntyre’s Revolutionary Aristotelianism, ed. Paul Blackledge and Kelvin Knight (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2011), 228–240; Ronald Beiner, “Community versus Citizenship: MacIntyre’s Revolt against the Modern State,” Critical Review 14 (2000): 459–479; Keith Breen, “The State, Compartmentalization and the Turn to Local Community: A Critique of the Political Thought of Alasdair MacIntyre,” The European Legacy 10 (2005): 485–501.38 Caleb Bernacchio and Kelvin Knight, “MacIntyre and Political Philosophy,” in Learning from MacIntyre, ed. Ron Beadle and Geoff Moore (Eugene, Oregon: Pickwick Publications, 2020), 119.39 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Three Perspectives on Marxism: 1953, 1968, 1995,” in Ethics and Politics: Selected Essays, Volume 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 154.40 Ibid.41 MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 242.42 Alasdair MacIntyre, “The Idea of America” London Review of Books 6 (1980): 14. See also MacIntyre’s “The American Idea,” in America and Ireland, 1776–1976: The American Identity and the Irish Connection, ed. David Noel Doyle and Owen Dudley Edwards (Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Press, 1980), 57–68.43 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Power and Virtue in the American Republic,” in The Case For and Against Power for the Federal Government (Ripon, Wisconsin: Ripon College Press, 1976), 18.44 Jeffery L. Nicholas, “The Common Good, Rights, and Catholic Social Thought: Prolegomena to Any Future Account of Common Goods,” Solidarity: The Journal of Catholic Social Thought and Secular Ethics 5 (2015): 14.45 MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals, 132.46 MacIntyre, “Intractable Moral Disagreements,” 20.47 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Social Structures and their Threats to Moral Agency,” in Ethics and Politics: Selected Essays, Volume 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 197. See also MacIntyre, “How Aristotelianism can become Revolutionary,” 12; Alasdair MacIntyre’s, “Some Enlightenment Projects Reconsidered,” in Ethics and Politics: Selected Essays, Volume 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 172–185.48 MacIntyre, “How Aristotelianism can become Revolutionary,” 12.49 MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals, 141.50 St. Thomas, ST, I-II, q.90, a.2 and q.92, a.1.51 Sean Sayers, “MacIntyre and Modernity,” in Virtue and Politics: Alasdair MacIntyre’s Revolutionary Aristotelianism ed. Paul Blackledge and Kelvin Knight (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2011), 83–84; Timothy Chappell, “Utopias and the Art of the Possible,” Analyse & Kritik 30 (2008): 186–187; Patrick J. Deneen, Why Liberalism Failed (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2018), 21–22; Jason W. Blakely, “Does Liberalism Lack Virtue? A Critique of Alasdair MacIntyre’s Reactionary Politics,” Interpretation 44 (2017): 10.52 Aristotle, Politics, III, c.6, trans. Benjamin Jowett, in The Complete Works of Aristotle, vol. 2, ed. Jonathan Barnes (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984), 2029–2030; St. Thomas Aquinas, Sententia Libri Politicorum, III, c.6 (Rome: Leonine, 1971), 204.53 William T. Cavanaugh, “Killing for the Telephone Company: Why the Nation-State is not the Keeper of the Common Good,” Modern Theology 20 (2004): 246–250.54 V. Bradley Lewis, “The Common Good against the Modern State? On MacIntyre’s Political Philosophy,” Josephinum Journal of Theology 16 (2009): 367.55 See Thomas S. Hibbs, “MacIntyre, Aquinas, and Politics,” The Review of Politics 66 (2004): 357–383, Osborne, “Contemporary Common Good,” 84–88, and Lewis, “Modern State,” 374–375.56 Osborne, “Contemporary Common Good,” 87.57 Lewis, “Modern State,” 374. See also Nathan J. Pinkoski, “Manent and Perreau-Saussine on MacIntyre’s Aristotelianism,” Perspectives on Political Science 48 (2019): 1–11.58 Osborne, “Contemporary Common Good,” 87; Hibbs, “MacIntyre, Aquinas, and Politics,” 372–374.59 Lewis, “Modern State,” 367.60 See Herbert C. Kelman, “Nationalism, Patriotism, and National Identity: Social-Psychological Dimensions,” in Patriotism in the Lives of Individuals and Nations, ed. David Bar-Tal and Ervin Staub (Chicago: Nelson-Hall Publishers, 1997), 165–189; Robert M. Kunovich, “The Sources and Consequences of National Identification,” American Sociological Review 74 (2009): 573–593; Tim Edensor, National Identity, Popular Culture and Everyday Life (Oxford: Berg, 2002).61 Jacques Maritain, Man and the State (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 1998), 3–4.62 MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 241.63 Cf. MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 236–237, and Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity, 126–127.64 MacIntyre, Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity, 296–297.65 Ibid, 176–183.66 Yves R. Simon, A General Theory of Authority (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1980), 157–158.67 St. Thomas, ST, I-II, 96, a.4.68 MacIntyre, “Natural Law as Subversive,” 49.69 Bernacchio and Knight, “MacIntyre and Political Philosophy,” 129.70 MacIntyre, “Three Perspectives on Marxism,” 146.71 MacIntyre, After Virtue, 263.72 Alasdair MacIntyre (2017, April 25). Keynote: Common Goods, Frequent Evils, YouTube, accessed February 2, 2023, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=9nx0Kvb5U04.73 Knight, A Revolutionary Aristotelianism, 187.74 MacIntyre, “How Aristotelianism can be Revolutionary,” 19.75 Osborne, “Contemporary Common Good,” 89.76 Ibid.77 For more on this new approach, see Lutz, Tradition in the Ethics of Alasdair MacIntyre, 141–155, and Macias, “John Finnis and Alasdair MacIntyre.”78 Mark, “New Natural Law Theory and the Common Good,” 299.79 MacIntyre, “Natural Law Reconsidered,” 98.80 Ibid, 99.81 MacIntyre, Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity, 125.82 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Toleration and the Goods of Conflict,” in Ethics and Politics: Selected Essays, Volume 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 211.83 Goyette, “On the Transcendence of the Political Common Good,” 141.84 Mark, “New Natural Law and the Political Common Good,” 301.85 Goyette, “On the Transcendence of the Political Common Good,” 155.86 See MacIntyre, “Social Structures and their Threats to Moral Agency.”87 Cavanaugh, “Killing for the Telephone Company,” 267.88 For MacIntyre’s account of revolutionary Aristotelianism, see MacIntyre, “How Aristotelianism can be Revolutionary,” and Kelvin Knight, “Revolutionary Aristotelianism,” in Virtue and Politics: Alasdair MacIntyre’s Revolutionary Aristotelianism, ed. Paul Blackledge and Kelvin Knight (Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame, 2011), 20–34. For criticisms of MacIntyre’s view, see Keith Breen, “Alasdair MacIntyre and the Hope for a Politics of Virtuous Acknowledge Dependence,” Contemporary Political Theory 1 (2002): 181–201, and Tony Burns, “Revolutionary Aristotelianism? The Political Thought of Aristotle, Marx, and MacIntyre,” in Virtues and Politics: Alasdair MacIntyre’s Revolutionary Aristotelianism,” ed. Paul Blackledge and Kelvin Knight (Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 2011), 35–53.89 Bernacchio and Knight, “MacIntyre and Political Philosophy,” 137.90 See MacIntyre, “How Aristotelianism can become Revolutionary,” 17, and Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity, 176–183.91 Cavanaugh, “Killing for the Telephone Company,” 267.92 Charles Taylor, Patrizia Nanz, Madeleine Beaubien Taylor, Reconstructing Democracy: How Citizens Are Building from the Ground Up (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2020).93 See Christopher Tollefsen, “The New Natural Law Theory,” Lyceum 10 (2008): 2–3.94 See Jacques Maritain, Scholasticism & Politics, trans. Mortimer Adler (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 2011); Yves Simon, Philosophy of Democratic Government (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1993).","PeriodicalId":55874,"journal":{"name":"Perspectives on Political Science","volume":"57 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2023-09-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Perspectives on Political Science","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/10457097.2023.2255097","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q4","JCRName":"Social Sciences","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

AbstractThe Traditional Natural Law (TNL) considers the political community a good human beings desire as one of the greatest goods of practical life, while those within the New Natural Law (NNL) camp argue instead that the political community is an instrumental good. Neither side has been able to offer a decisive refutation of the other, despite each offering strong arguments supported by both philosophical argument and textual evidence. In response, I will present Alasdair MacIntyre’s approach to practical reason and political community in hopes of shedding new light on this debate. From a MacIntyrean perspective, the TNL and NNL disagreement is more apparent than real, because the two sides in fact address different objects. MacIntyre presents political community as a constitutive aspect of excellent practical reasoning, but he denies the modern nation-state can be such a community. Disclosure StatementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Theories of Natural Law in the Culture of Advanced Modernity,” in Common Truths: New Perspectives in Natural Law, ed. Edward B. McLean (Wilmington, Delaware: ISI Books, 200), 94. See also Alasdair MacIntyre, “Intractable Moral Disagreements,” in Intractable Disputes about the Natural Law: Alasdair MacIntyre and Critics, ed. Lawrence S. Cunningham (Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 2009), 1–52.2 MacIntyre, “Theories of Natural Law,” 92.3 For the background of this debate, see Germain Grisez, “The First Principle of Practical Reason: A Commentary on the Summa Theologiae, 1–2, Question 94, Article 2,” in Aquinas: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Anthony Kenny (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1976), 340–382; Ralph McInerny, Aquinas on Human Action: A Theory of Practice (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1); Christopher Tollefsen, “The New Natural Law Theory,” Lyceum 10, (2008): 1–17; John Finnis, Aquinas: Moral, Political, and Legal Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998); Steven Jensen, Knowing the Natural Law: From Precepts and Inclinations to Deriving Oughts (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 2015); John Macias, “John Finnis and Alasdair MacIntyre on Our Knowledge of the Precepts of Natural Law,” Res Philosophica 93 (2016): 103–123; Ryan T. Anderson, editor, “Defense of the New Natural Law,” National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly (2019): 165–329.4 John Finnis, “Is Natural Law Theory Compatible with Limited Government?,” in Natural Law, Liberalism, and Morality, ed. Robert P. George (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), 5.5 Finnis, Aquinas, 247.6 Ibid, 247–248.7 Michael Pakaluk, “Is the Common Good of Political Society Limited and Instrumental?” The Review of Metaphysics 55 (2001): 91.8 John Goyette, “On the Transcendence of the Political Common Good: Aquinas versus the New Natural Law Theory,” The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 13 (2013): 155.9 Goyette, 141; Pakaluk, “Common Good of Political Society,” 9310 Finnis, Aquinas: Moral, Political, and Legal Theory, 235.11 Ibid, 235–237.12 St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, II-II, q.101, a.1 (Rome: Editiones Paulinae, 1962), 1512.13 Thomas Osborne, “MacIntyre, Thomism and the Contemporary Common Good,” Analyse & Kritik 30 (2008): 84.14 Daniel Mark, “New Natural Law Theory and the Common Good of the Political Community,” National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 19 (2019): 299. Mark, “New Natural Law Theory,” 299.15 Ibid.16 Finnis, Aquinas: Moral, Political, and Legal Theory, 226–227.17 Alasdair MacIntyre, Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity: An Essay on Desire, Practical Reasoning, and Narrative (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2016), 51. Alasdair MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues (Chicago: Open Court, 1999), 107.18 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” in The MacIntyre Reader, ed. Kelvin Knight (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1998), 240. For commentators on MacIntyre’s emphasis on practical reasoning, see Christopher Stephen Lutz, Reading Alasdair MacIntyre’s After Virtue (New York: Continuum International Publishing Group, 2012) and “Alasdair MacIntyre’s Ethics of Practical Reasoning: Morality in Practice,” Politics & Poetics 4 (2018); Kelvin Knight, Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2007); Caleb Bernacchio and Kelvin Knight, “MacIntyre and Political Philosophy,” in Learning from MacIntyre, ed. Ron Beadle and Geoff Moore (Eugene, Oregon: Pickwick Publications, 2020), 117–139.19 Alasdair MacIntyre, “How Aristotelianism can become Revolutionary: Ethics, Resistance, and Utopia,” Virtue and Politics: Alasdair MacIntyre’s Revolutionary Aristotelianism, ed. Paul Blackledge and Kelvin Knight (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2011), 1620 MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 241.21 Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2007), 187.22 Jeffrey L. Nicholas, “Who Stands for Un̳čí Makhá: The Liberal Nation-State, Racism, Freedom, and Nature,” in Liberty and the Ecological Crisis: Freedom on a Finite Planet, eds. Christhoper J. Orr, Kaitlin Kish, and Bruce Jennings (Oxfordshire, UK: Routledge, 2019), 114.23 MacIntyre “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 248.24 MacIntyre, “Intractable Moral Disagreements,” 23.25 MacIntyre, “Theories of Natural Law in the Cultures of Adavnced Modernity,” 93. See also MacIntyre, Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity, 89; MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 247; MacIntyre, “Natural Law as Subversive,” 48.26 MacIntyre, “Natural Law as Subversive,” 49.27 MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 248.28 MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals, 135–136.29 Ibid, 108.30 Gregory Froelich, “The Equivocal Status of Bonum Commune” The New Scholasticism 63 (1989): 38–57.31 MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals, 108.32 Ibid, 123.33 MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 242.34 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Poetry as Political Philosophy: Notes on Burke and Yeats,” in Ethics and Politics: Selected Essays, Volume 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 206), 163. See also Alasdair MacIntyre, “A Partial Response to my Critics,” in After MacIntyre: Critical Perspectives on the Work of Alasdair MacIntyre, ed. John Horton and Susan Mendus (Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1994), 303.35 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Is Patriotism a Virtue?” (Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas, 1984), 13.36 Ibid, 11.37 MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 236. For commentators on MacIntyre’s critique of the nation-state, see Mark C. Murphy, “MacIntyre’s Political Philosophy,” in Alasdair MacIntyre, ed. Mark C. Murphy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 152–175; Peter McMylor, “Compartmentalization and Social Roles: MacIntyre’s Critical Theory of Modernity,” in Virtue and Politics: Alasdair MacIntyre’s Revolutionary Aristotelianism, ed. Paul Blackledge and Kelvin Knight (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2011), 228–240; Ronald Beiner, “Community versus Citizenship: MacIntyre’s Revolt against the Modern State,” Critical Review 14 (2000): 459–479; Keith Breen, “The State, Compartmentalization and the Turn to Local Community: A Critique of the Political Thought of Alasdair MacIntyre,” The European Legacy 10 (2005): 485–501.38 Caleb Bernacchio and Kelvin Knight, “MacIntyre and Political Philosophy,” in Learning from MacIntyre, ed. Ron Beadle and Geoff Moore (Eugene, Oregon: Pickwick Publications, 2020), 119.39 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Three Perspectives on Marxism: 1953, 1968, 1995,” in Ethics and Politics: Selected Essays, Volume 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 154.40 Ibid.41 MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 242.42 Alasdair MacIntyre, “The Idea of America” London Review of Books 6 (1980): 14. See also MacIntyre’s “The American Idea,” in America and Ireland, 1776–1976: The American Identity and the Irish Connection, ed. David Noel Doyle and Owen Dudley Edwards (Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Press, 1980), 57–68.43 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Power and Virtue in the American Republic,” in The Case For and Against Power for the Federal Government (Ripon, Wisconsin: Ripon College Press, 1976), 18.44 Jeffery L. Nicholas, “The Common Good, Rights, and Catholic Social Thought: Prolegomena to Any Future Account of Common Goods,” Solidarity: The Journal of Catholic Social Thought and Secular Ethics 5 (2015): 14.45 MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals, 132.46 MacIntyre, “Intractable Moral Disagreements,” 20.47 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Social Structures and their Threats to Moral Agency,” in Ethics and Politics: Selected Essays, Volume 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 197. See also MacIntyre, “How Aristotelianism can become Revolutionary,” 12; Alasdair MacIntyre’s, “Some Enlightenment Projects Reconsidered,” in Ethics and Politics: Selected Essays, Volume 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 172–185.48 MacIntyre, “How Aristotelianism can become Revolutionary,” 12.49 MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals, 141.50 St. Thomas, ST, I-II, q.90, a.2 and q.92, a.1.51 Sean Sayers, “MacIntyre and Modernity,” in Virtue and Politics: Alasdair MacIntyre’s Revolutionary Aristotelianism ed. Paul Blackledge and Kelvin Knight (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2011), 83–84; Timothy Chappell, “Utopias and the Art of the Possible,” Analyse & Kritik 30 (2008): 186–187; Patrick J. Deneen, Why Liberalism Failed (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2018), 21–22; Jason W. Blakely, “Does Liberalism Lack Virtue? A Critique of Alasdair MacIntyre’s Reactionary Politics,” Interpretation 44 (2017): 10.52 Aristotle, Politics, III, c.6, trans. Benjamin Jowett, in The Complete Works of Aristotle, vol. 2, ed. Jonathan Barnes (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984), 2029–2030; St. Thomas Aquinas, Sententia Libri Politicorum, III, c.6 (Rome: Leonine, 1971), 204.53 William T. Cavanaugh, “Killing for the Telephone Company: Why the Nation-State is not the Keeper of the Common Good,” Modern Theology 20 (2004): 246–250.54 V. Bradley Lewis, “The Common Good against the Modern State? On MacIntyre’s Political Philosophy,” Josephinum Journal of Theology 16 (2009): 367.55 See Thomas S. Hibbs, “MacIntyre, Aquinas, and Politics,” The Review of Politics 66 (2004): 357–383, Osborne, “Contemporary Common Good,” 84–88, and Lewis, “Modern State,” 374–375.56 Osborne, “Contemporary Common Good,” 87.57 Lewis, “Modern State,” 374. See also Nathan J. Pinkoski, “Manent and Perreau-Saussine on MacIntyre’s Aristotelianism,” Perspectives on Political Science 48 (2019): 1–11.58 Osborne, “Contemporary Common Good,” 87; Hibbs, “MacIntyre, Aquinas, and Politics,” 372–374.59 Lewis, “Modern State,” 367.60 See Herbert C. Kelman, “Nationalism, Patriotism, and National Identity: Social-Psychological Dimensions,” in Patriotism in the Lives of Individuals and Nations, ed. David Bar-Tal and Ervin Staub (Chicago: Nelson-Hall Publishers, 1997), 165–189; Robert M. Kunovich, “The Sources and Consequences of National Identification,” American Sociological Review 74 (2009): 573–593; Tim Edensor, National Identity, Popular Culture and Everyday Life (Oxford: Berg, 2002).61 Jacques Maritain, Man and the State (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 1998), 3–4.62 MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 241.63 Cf. MacIntyre, “Politics, Philosophy and the Common Good,” 236–237, and Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity, 126–127.64 MacIntyre, Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity, 296–297.65 Ibid, 176–183.66 Yves R. Simon, A General Theory of Authority (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1980), 157–158.67 St. Thomas, ST, I-II, 96, a.4.68 MacIntyre, “Natural Law as Subversive,” 49.69 Bernacchio and Knight, “MacIntyre and Political Philosophy,” 129.70 MacIntyre, “Three Perspectives on Marxism,” 146.71 MacIntyre, After Virtue, 263.72 Alasdair MacIntyre (2017, April 25). Keynote: Common Goods, Frequent Evils, YouTube, accessed February 2, 2023, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=9nx0Kvb5U04.73 Knight, A Revolutionary Aristotelianism, 187.74 MacIntyre, “How Aristotelianism can be Revolutionary,” 19.75 Osborne, “Contemporary Common Good,” 89.76 Ibid.77 For more on this new approach, see Lutz, Tradition in the Ethics of Alasdair MacIntyre, 141–155, and Macias, “John Finnis and Alasdair MacIntyre.”78 Mark, “New Natural Law Theory and the Common Good,” 299.79 MacIntyre, “Natural Law Reconsidered,” 98.80 Ibid, 99.81 MacIntyre, Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity, 125.82 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Toleration and the Goods of Conflict,” in Ethics and Politics: Selected Essays, Volume 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 211.83 Goyette, “On the Transcendence of the Political Common Good,” 141.84 Mark, “New Natural Law and the Political Common Good,” 301.85 Goyette, “On the Transcendence of the Political Common Good,” 155.86 See MacIntyre, “Social Structures and their Threats to Moral Agency.”87 Cavanaugh, “Killing for the Telephone Company,” 267.88 For MacIntyre’s account of revolutionary Aristotelianism, see MacIntyre, “How Aristotelianism can be Revolutionary,” and Kelvin Knight, “Revolutionary Aristotelianism,” in Virtue and Politics: Alasdair MacIntyre’s Revolutionary Aristotelianism, ed. Paul Blackledge and Kelvin Knight (Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame, 2011), 20–34. For criticisms of MacIntyre’s view, see Keith Breen, “Alasdair MacIntyre and the Hope for a Politics of Virtuous Acknowledge Dependence,” Contemporary Political Theory 1 (2002): 181–201, and Tony Burns, “Revolutionary Aristotelianism? The Political Thought of Aristotle, Marx, and MacIntyre,” in Virtues and Politics: Alasdair MacIntyre’s Revolutionary Aristotelianism,” ed. Paul Blackledge and Kelvin Knight (Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 2011), 35–53.89 Bernacchio and Knight, “MacIntyre and Political Philosophy,” 137.90 See MacIntyre, “How Aristotelianism can become Revolutionary,” 17, and Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity, 176–183.91 Cavanaugh, “Killing for the Telephone Company,” 267.92 Charles Taylor, Patrizia Nanz, Madeleine Beaubien Taylor, Reconstructing Democracy: How Citizens Are Building from the Ground Up (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2020).93 See Christopher Tollefsen, “The New Natural Law Theory,” Lyceum 10 (2008): 2–3.94 See Jacques Maritain, Scholasticism & Politics, trans. Mortimer Adler (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 2011); Yves Simon, Philosophy of Democratic Government (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1993).
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
政治推理与民族国家:对托马斯主义辩论的麦金太尔式思考
摘要传统自然法认为政治共同体是人类的一种美好愿望,是现实生活中最伟大的善,而新自然法则认为政治共同体是一种工具性善。尽管双方都提供了强有力的论据,得到了哲学论证和文本证据的支持,但双方都无法对对方提出决定性的反驳。作为回应,我将介绍阿拉斯代尔·麦金泰尔(Alasdair MacIntyre)对实践理性和政治共同体的研究方法,希望能对这场辩论提供新的启示。从麦金太尔的角度来看,TNL和NNL的分歧是明显的,而不是真实的,因为双方实际上处理的是不同的对象。麦金太尔将政治共同体视为优秀实践推理的一个构成方面,但他否认现代民族国家可以是这样一个共同体。披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。注1 Alasdair MacIntyre,“先进现代性文化中的自然法理论”,载于Edward B. McLean主编的《共同真理:自然法的新视角》(Wilmington, Delaware: ISI Books, 2000),第94页。参见Alasdair MacIntyre,“棘手的道德分歧”,见《关于自然法的棘手争端:Alasdair MacIntyre和评论家》,劳伦斯·s·坎宁安主编(印第安纳州圣母大学:圣母大学出版社,2009年),1-52.2。MacIntyre,“自然法理论”,92.3关于这场辩论的背景,见Germain Grisez,“实践理性的第一原则:对神学总论的评论,1-2,问题94,第二条”,《阿奎那》。安东尼·肯尼(圣母大学,印第安纳州:圣母大学出版社,1976),340-382;拉尔夫·麦金纳尼,《阿奎那论人类行为:实践理论》(华盛顿特区:美国天主教大学出版社,第1版);Christopher Tollefsen:《新自然法理论》,《学刊》2008年第10期,第1-17页;约翰·菲尼斯,《阿奎那:道德、政治和法律理论》(牛津:牛津大学出版社,1998年);史蒂文·詹森:《认识自然法:从戒律和倾向到派生义务》(华盛顿特区:美国天主教大学出版社,2015年);约翰·马西亚斯:《约翰·菲尼斯和阿拉斯代尔·麦金泰尔对自然法规则的认识》,《哲学研究》2016年第93期:103-123;瑞安·t·安德森,编辑,“新自然法的辩护”,国家天主教生物伦理学季刊(2019):165-329.4约翰·菲尼斯,“自然法理论与有限政府兼容吗?《自然法、自由主义与道德》,罗伯特·p·乔治主编(牛津:牛津大学出版社,1996年),5.5芬尼斯,阿奎那,247.6同上,247-248.7迈克尔·帕卡鲁克,“政治社会的共同利益是有限的和工具性的吗?”《形而上学评论》55 (2001):91.8 John Goyette,“论政治共同利益的超越性:阿奎那与新自然法理论”,《国家天主教生命伦理学季刊》13 (2013):155.9 Goyette, 141;帕卡卢克,“政治社会的共同利益”,芬尼斯,《阿奎那:道德、政治和法律理论》,235.11同上,235-237.12圣托马斯·阿奎那,《神学总论》,II-II, q101, a.1(罗马:版保利纳,1962),1512.13托马斯·奥斯本,“麦金太尔,托马斯主义和当代共同利益,”分析与批判30(2008):84.14丹尼尔·马克,“新自然法理论和政治共同体的共同利益,”国家天主教生命伦理学季刊19(2019):299。16菲尼斯:《阿奎那:道德、政治与法律理论》,226-227.17阿拉斯代尔·麦金泰尔:《现代性冲突中的伦理:欲望、实践推理与叙事》(剑桥:剑桥大学出版社,2016),第51页。阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔,《依赖理性动物:为什么人类需要美德》(芝加哥:Open Court, 1999), 107.18阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔,《政治、哲学和共同利益》,载于《麦金太尔读本》,开尔文·奈特主编(圣母大学,印第安纳州:圣母大学出版社,1998),240页。关于麦金太尔强调实践推理的评论,请参见克里斯托弗·斯蒂芬·卢茨,《阅读阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔的《美德之后》(纽约:连续国际出版集团,2012)》和《阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔的实践推理伦理:实践中的道德》,《政治与诗学》第4期(2018);开尔文·奈特,《亚里士多德哲学:从亚里士多德到麦金太尔的伦理与政治》(剑桥:政体出版社,2007);凯莱布·伯纳奇奥和开尔文·奈特,《麦金太尔与政治哲学》,见《向麦金太尔学习》,罗恩·比德尔和杰夫·摩尔主编(俄勒冈州尤金:匹克威克出版社,2020年),117-139.19。阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔,《亚里士多德主义如何成为革命的:伦理、抵抗和乌托邦》,《美德与政治:阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔的革命亚里士多德主义》,保罗·布莱克利奇和开尔文·奈特主编(印第安纳州圣母大学):圣母大学出版社,2011),1620麦金泰尔,“政治,哲学和共同利益,”241。 21 Alasdair MacIntyre,《美德之后:道德理论研究》(Notre Dame, in: University of Notre Dame Press, 2007), 187.22 Jeffrey L. Nicholas,“谁代表Un čí makh<e:1>:自由的民族国家、种族主义、自由和自然”,《自由与生态危机:有限星球上的自由》,主编。克里斯托弗·j·奥尔、凯特琳·基什和布鲁斯·詹宁斯(英国牛津郡:劳特利奇出版社,2019),114.23麦金太尔,“政治、哲学和共同利益”,248.24麦金太尔,“棘手的道德分歧”,23.25麦金太尔,“先进现代性文化中的自然法理论”,93。参见麦金太尔,《现代性冲突中的伦理学》,1989;麦金太尔,《政治、哲学和共同利益》,第247页;麦金太尔,“作为颠覆性的自然法”,48.26麦金太尔,“作为颠覆性的自然法”,49.27麦金太尔,“政治、哲学和共同利益”,248.28麦金太尔,“依赖理性的动物”,135-136.29同上,108.30格雷戈里·弗罗利奇,“Bonum公社的模棱两可地位”,新士林哲学63(1989):38-57.31麦金太尔,“依赖理性的动物”,108.32同上,123.33麦金太尔,“政治、哲学和共同利益”,242.34 Alasdair麦金太尔,“诗歌作为政治哲学”;伯克和叶芝注释”,选自《伦理与政治:散文选集》第二卷(剑桥:剑桥大学出版社,206),163页。另见阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔,“对我的批评者的部分回应”,见《麦金太尔之后:对阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔作品的批判观点》,约翰·霍顿和苏珊·门杜斯主编(印第安纳州圣母大学:圣母大学出版社,1994年),303.35阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔,“爱国主义是一种美德吗?”(Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas, 1984), 13.36同上,11.37麦金泰尔,《政治、哲学与共同利益》,236页。关于麦金太尔对民族国家批判的评论,见Mark C. Murphy,“麦金太尔的政治哲学”,收录于Alasdair MacIntyre主编。Mark C. Murphy(剑桥:剑桥大学出版社,2003),152-175页;彼得·麦克迈勒,“划分和社会角色:麦金太尔的现代性批判理论”,载于《美德与政治:阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔的革命亚里士多德主义》,保罗·布莱克利奇和开尔文·奈特主编(圣母大学,印第安纳州:圣母大学出版社,2011),228-240页;罗纳德·贝纳:《社区与公民权:麦金太尔对现代国家的反抗》,《批判评论》2000年第14期,第459-479页;Keith Breen,“国家、划分和转向地方社区:对阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔政治思想的批判”,《欧洲遗产》10 (2005):485-501.38 Caleb Bernacchio和Kelvin Knight,“麦金太尔与政治哲学”,见《向麦金太尔学习》,Ron Beadle和Geoff Moore主编(俄勒冈州尤金:匹克威克出版社,2020),119.39 Alasdair麦金太尔,“马克思主义的三个视角:1953、1968、1995”,刊于《伦理与政治》;《散文选集》第2卷(剑桥:剑桥大学出版社,2006年),154.40同上41麦金太尔,《政治、哲学和共同利益》,242.42阿拉斯代尔麦金太尔,《美国的理念》,《伦敦书评》第6期(1980年):14。另见麦金太尔的《美国观念》,《1776-1976年的美国和爱尔兰:美国人的身份和爱尔兰人的联系》,大卫·诺埃尔·多伊尔和欧文·达德利·爱德华兹(韦斯特波特,康涅狄格州:格林伍德出版社,1980年),57-68.43阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔,《美利坚共和国的权力和美德》,《支持和反对联邦政府权力的案件》(威斯康星州里彭:里彭学院出版社,1976年),18.44杰弗里·l·尼古拉斯,《共同利益、权利和天主教社会思想:《共同利益的未来展望》,《团结:天主教社会思想与世俗伦理杂志》5(2015):14.45麦金太尔,依赖理性动物,132.46麦金太尔,“难以处理的道德分歧”,20.47阿拉斯代尔麦金太尔,“社会结构及其对道德代理的威胁”,《伦理与政治:论文集》第二卷(剑桥:剑桥大学出版社,2006),197。参见麦金太尔,“亚里士多德主义如何成为革命”,12;阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔,《重新考虑一些启蒙工程》,载于《伦理与政治:论文集》第二卷(剑桥:剑桥大学出版社,2006年),172-185.48麦金太尔,《亚里士多德主义如何成为革命性的》,12.49麦金太尔,《依赖的理性动物》,141.50圣托马斯,ST, I-II, q90, a.2和q92, a.1.51肖恩·塞耶斯,《麦金太尔与现代性》,载于《美德与政治》;阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔的革命亚里士多德主义,保罗·布莱克利奇和开尔文·奈特(圣母大学,印第安纳州:圣母大学出版社,2011),83-84;蒂莫西·查佩尔:《乌托邦与可能的艺术》,《分析与批判》,2008年第30期:186-187页;帕特里克·j·迪宁,《自由主义为何失败》(康涅狄格州纽黑文:耶鲁大学出版社,2018),第21-22页;Jason W. Blakely,《自由主义缺乏美德吗?》《阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔反动政治批判》,《阐释》第44期(2017):10.52页。本杰明·乔伊特,《亚里士多德全集》,第二卷,编。 乔纳森·巴恩斯(普林斯顿,新泽西州:普林斯顿大学出版社,1984),2029-2030;圣托马斯·阿奎那,《政治图书馆的句子》,三,c.6(罗马:Leonine, 1971), 204.53 William T. Cavanaugh,“为电话公司杀人:为什么民族国家不是共同利益的守护者,”现代神学20 (2004):246-250.54 V。布拉德利·刘易斯,《公共利益对抗现代国家?》《论麦金太尔的政治哲学》,约瑟夫神学杂志16(2009):367.55见托马斯·s·希布斯,《麦金太尔、阿奎那与政治》,《政治评论》66(2004):357-383;奥斯本,《当代共同利益》,84-88;刘易斯,《现代国家》,374 - 375.56;奥斯本,《当代共同利益》,87.57刘易斯,《现代国家》,374。另见Nathan J. Pinkoski,《论麦金太尔的亚里士多德主义》,《政治学透视》48(2019):1-11.58奥斯本,《当代共同利益》,87;参见赫伯特·c·凯尔曼,《民族主义、爱国主义和国家认同:社会心理维度》,载于《个人和国家生活中的爱国主义》,大卫·巴尔塔尔和欧文·斯托布主编(芝加哥:尼尔森-霍尔出版社,1997年),165-189页;Robert M. Kunovich:“国家认同的来源与后果”,《美国社会学评论》(2009),第74期:573-593;《民族认同、流行文化与日常生活》(牛津:伯格出版社,2002),第61页雅克·马里坦,《人与国家》(华盛顿特区:美国天主教大学出版社,1998),第3-4.62页。麦金太尔,《政治、哲学与共同利益》,241.63 Cf.麦金太尔,《政治、哲学与共同利益》,236-237页,《现代性冲突中的伦理学》,126-127.64页。麦金太尔,《现代性冲突中的伦理学》,296-297.65同上,176-183.66伊夫斯·r·西蒙,《权威通论》(巴黎圣母院,印第安纳州:圣母大学出版社,1980),157-158.67圣托马斯,ST, I-II, 96, a.4.68麦金太尔,“自然法作为颠覆性的”,49.69伯纳奇奥和奈特,“麦金太尔与政治哲学”,129.70麦金太尔,“马克思主义的三个视角”,146.71麦金太尔,美德之后,263.72阿拉斯代尔麦金太尔(2017年4月25日)。主题:共同利益,频繁的罪恶,YouTube,访问2023年2月2日,https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=9nx0Kvb5U04.73奈特,革命亚里士多德主义,187.74麦金太尔,“亚里士多德主义如何成为革命”,19.75奥斯本,“当代共同利益”,89.76同上。77关于这种新方法的更多信息,参见卢茨,阿拉斯代尔麦金太尔伦理传统,141-155,和马西亚斯,“约翰·芬尼斯和阿拉斯代尔麦金太尔。78马克,“新自然法理论与共同利益”,299.79麦金太尔,“重新考虑自然法”,98.80同上,99.81麦金太尔,“现代性冲突中的伦理学”,125.82阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔,“宽容与冲突的好处”,《伦理学与政治:论文集》第二卷(剑桥:剑桥大学出版社,2006),211.83 Goyette,“论政治共同利益的超越”,141.84 Mark,“新自然法和政治共同利益”,301.85 Goyette,“论政治共同利益的超越”,155.86见麦金泰尔,“社会结构及其对道德代理的威胁。”87卡瓦诺,“为电话公司杀人”,267.88关于麦金太尔对革命亚里士多德主义的描述,见麦金太尔,“亚里士多德主义如何成为革命的”,以及开尔文·奈特,“革命亚里士多德主义”,《美德与政治:阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔的革命亚里士多德主义》,保罗·布莱克利奇和开尔文·奈特编(印第安纳州圣母大学:圣母大学,2011年),20-34页。对麦金太尔观点的批评,请见基思·布林:《阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔与承认依赖的美德政治的希望》,《当代政治理论》第1期(2002年):181-201页;托尼·伯恩斯:《革命的亚里士多德主义?亚里士多德、马克思和麦金太尔的政治思想,《美德与政治:阿拉斯代尔·麦金太尔的革命亚里士多德主义》,Paul Blackledge和Kelvin Knight编(印第安纳州圣母大学);圣母大学出版社,2011),35-53.89伯纳奇奥和奈特,“麦金太尔和政治哲学,”137.90见麦金太尔,“亚里士多德主义如何成为革命”17,以及现代性冲突中的伦理学,176-183.91卡瓦诺,“为电话公司杀人”267.92查尔斯·泰勒,帕特里齐亚·南兹,玛德琳·博比恩·泰勒,重建民主:公民如何从头开始建设(剑桥:哈佛大学出版社,2020)参见Christopher Tollefsen,“新自然法理论”,学刊10(2008):2-3.94。莫蒂默·阿德勒(印第安纳州印第安纳波利斯:自由基金,2011);伊夫·西蒙,《民主政府哲学》(圣母大学出版社,1993)。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
Perspectives on Political Science
Perspectives on Political Science Social Sciences-Political Science and International Relations
CiteScore
0.20
自引率
0.00%
发文量
24
期刊介绍: Whether discussing Montaigne"s case for tolerance or Nietzsche"s political critique of modern science, Perspectives on Political Science links contemporary politics and culture to the enduring questions posed by great thinkers from antiquity to the present. Ideas are the lifeblood of the journal, which comprises articles, symposia, and book reviews. Recent articles address the writings of Aristotle, Adam Smith, and Plutarch; the movies No Country for Old Men and 3:10 to Yuma; and the role of humility in modern political thought.
期刊最新文献
Paul & Empire Criticism: Why and How? Paul & Empire Criticism: Why and How? by Najeeb T. Haddad, Cascade Books, Publication Date: 2023 Conversation as Political Education Defending Socrates: Political Philosophy Before the Tribunal of Science Defending Socrates: Political Philosophy Before the Tribunal of Science , by Alex Priou, Macon, Georgia: Mercer University Press, 184 pp., ISBN 978-0-88146-914-1, Publication Date: 2023 The Politics of Suicide: Miasma and Katharmos in Plato’s Political Thought “Worse than Nothing: The Dangerous Fallacy of Originalism,” by Erwin Chemerinsky
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1