:The Natural Laws of Plot: How Things Happen in Realist Novels

IF 0.4 2区 文学 0 LANGUAGE & LINGUISTICS MODERN PHILOLOGY Pub Date : 2023-10-04 DOI:10.1086/727803
Cynthia Wall
{"title":":<i>The Natural Laws of Plot: How Things Happen in Realist Novels</i>","authors":"Cynthia Wall","doi":"10.1086/727803","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Previous articleNext article FreeBook ReviewThe Natural Laws of Plot: How Things Happen in Realist Novels. Yoon Sun Lee. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2023. Pp. 258.Cynthia WallCynthia WallUniversity of Virginia Search for more articles by this author PDFPDF PLUSFull Text Add to favoritesDownload CitationTrack CitationsPermissionsReprints Share onFacebookTwitterLinkedInRedditEmailPrint SectionsMoreIf a body impinge upon another, and by its force change the motion of the other, that body also … will undergo an equal change, in its own motion.(Isaac Newton, Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica [1687])1Newtonian physics is just one of the many new empiricisms employed in learned depth in The Natural Laws of Plot to argue that the plots of novels are as much if not more embedded in their own landscapes, “rely[ing] more deeply and intricately on an environing world to carry along any action” (2), as they are involved with narrative and characters. “Things have shadows and textures, as well as depths and surfaces,” and fictional events are shaped by the “real world of physical forces and laws” (3). Bodies impinge on bodies, motion changes bodies, matter mixes and moves. The real world kept discovering and describing new physical forces and laws, and the well-read British public (and its novelists) kept abreast of and internalized those discoveries as new ways of understanding “how things happen.” The chapters progress through the period, matching up canonical authors’ narrative strategies with natural philosophers and theories: Daniel-Defovian causality and Newtonian physics; the characters of Henry Fielding and Samuel Richardson and the types and orders of Carl Linnaeus and Georges-Louis Leclerc Buffon; Ann Radcliffe, Frances Burney, and chemistry; a molecular Jane Austen; Maria Edgeworth, Anna Lætitia Barbauld, Humphry Davy, and “mechanical objectivity”; Walter Scott, Erasmus Darwin, and vertigo. Throughout, the originally mingled concepts later identified as “objectivity” and “subjectivity” get disentangled, both historically and ideologically. In every historical, scientific, and narratological shift, the “external world” is always, like my uncle Toby’s map of Namur, “far more than an inert backdrop to action. It provides the laws that are then twisted into plot and pinned to the ground” (60).The first chapter, “Novels, Novel-Theory, and the History of Objectivity,” argues that objectivity is not “a way of telling the story with a certain detachment or from a third-person point of view” but “something that has to be built into the plot of the novel” (1) and that will change its appearance dramatically over time, in rhythm with the changing contours of natural philosophy, from the necessary subjectivity—the reliance “on their own accumulated experience, their knowledge, skill, and instincts” (9)—of the early empiricists to the active suppression of the self into the nineteenth century.2 “The novel emerged in tandem” (11) not only with changing perceptions of subjective identity but also with its own discourse about itself: “The novel was a problem for itself from the beginning” (11). While Clara Reeve, in The Progress of Romance (1785), distinguished the novel as “‘a picture of real life and manners, and of the times in which it was written,’” from the romance, which “‘describes what never happened nor is likely to happen’” (quoted on 12), Barbauld and Scott expanded on what Lee sees as a “certain dissatisfaction” (12) they all had digesting this sense of realism. Barbauld notes that the formal coherence of plot in most eighteenth-century novels leads the reader to predict the ending and relish the neat tidyings of loose ends, whereas “‘in real life our reasonable expectations are often disappointed’” (quoted on 13). Scott in fact approves of Defoe’s novels precisely because “‘The incidents are huddled together like paving-stones discharged from a cart, and have as little connexion between the one and the other’” (quoted on 14). Lee concludes, “There seem to be two kinds of possible plot-interest, then: one in which, through the author’s artful planning, we focus on discovering the relations between events widely separated in the novel’s discourse. In the other, we are absorbed in the event itself, the more inconsequential the better, in the way its unfolding suggests something about the world or ‘the real tendencies of things,’ to use Barbauld’s expression. This latter kind of interest seems to be peculiar to the novel, as Scott and others envisioned it at the beginning of the nineteenth century” (16).The second chapter, “Matter, Motion, and the Physical World of the Novel,” explores the ways that the “objective, regular behavior of matter in space and time is fundamental to realist plots and the way that the latter work themselves out” (35). Plot is much more than “intentional human movements” (34); it includes the minute chain of events that cause the window sash in Laurence Sterne’s Tristram Shandy (1759–67) to slam down on the young protagonist and, er, cut things short (33–34). The chapter traces the familiar links between empiricism and the novel but offers as its new claim that the empiricist view of the world provides a “baseline ontology” for the new shapes of novel plots, as captured in John Desagulier’s summary of Cartesian causality: “changes in plot happen because of changes in ‘Situation, Distance … Structure, and Cohesion,’ as well as the spaces between and within bodies” (39).“Defoe’s Outstretched World” celebrates the paving stone model of plot, in which events are conceived “in terms of forces that push, pull, move around, or stabilize the pieces of the world”; thus “physical plot underlies the actions, emotions, and reflections of the characters,” sometimes encouraging them, but more often “undercut[ting] them repeatedly, taking away something that was thought to be settled” (63). Defoe’s important contribution to plot, Lee argues, “isn’t concerned with the inner structure of decision, which he retains. In Robinson Crusoe [1719] rather, it has to do with the relation between action, knowledge, and time, the scale at which they are shown to interact, and, most of all, the specification of intermediating causes as things that produce reliable, precisely calculable physical effects in the external world” (72). Lee cites Defoe’s expert familiarity with early modern science as demonstrated in the General History of Discoveries and Improvements in Useful Arts (1725–26) and the detailed descriptions of experiments made by Robert Boyle and Newton; Defoe’s plots are interesting precisely because things that seem to happen randomly, such as Crusoe’s “miraculous” barley, can be traced back cause by logical cause.Fielding and Richardson are the centerpieces in “Place, Type, and Order: Plot as Natural History.” The “classical idea of plot as formal unity” (84) encounters a new “model of knowledge” in which natural philosophy would “[bring] together disparate phenomena so that gradations of similarity and difference became clearly visible”; the result is “a narrative deeply committed to the idea of order, and to the realm of the visible” (83–84). Fielding’s individuals relate to their types (or “species,” in Fielding’s word); in Richardson’s Clarissa (1747–48), the rake Robert Lovelace is continuously “testing” the virtue of Clarissa to see if she is in fact her very own species. What criteria would be enough? Both Fielding and Richardson “are driven by the need to ascertain the relationship between their protagonists and the type or species to which they apparently belong” (99).Chapter 5, “Tracing Change and Testing Substances: Intimate Objectivity,” brings the plots of Radcliffe and Burney into the realm of chemistry. “Their plots seem less interested in questions of agency, of who made what happen, than in questions of composition, of how something behaves because of what kind of substance it is” (107–8). The ductility of the protagonist in Burney’s Camilla “is what Camilla is” (123, emphasis added); the colors in Radcliffe’s famous descriptions come under the microscope (124). (Tobias Smollett’s Humphry Clinker [1771] gets a good treatment here because of its fascination with mixtures.)Miss Bates’s little monologues in Austen’s Emma (1815) demonstrate the “Molecular Possibility in Austen’s Plot” in chapter 6, “exhibit[ing] a field of minute, chaotic, incessant movements in which rivets, apples, and spectacles, the actions of eating and recommending bounce around, collide without losing any of their motion, and come back again, swirling around endlessly” (131). Indeed, Emma treats her country friend Harriet’s mind with the “detachment of a scientist,” considering it as “a material arrangement” in which one piece could be inserted in place of another to fill vacancies or displace attention—“the model is mechanical” (148).The next chapter takes up this model and its relation to “quixotism,” which “ties the shape of the plot to the distorted beliefs and perceptions of its protagonist,” highlighting the newly reconceived “dangers of subjectivity” (151). Edgeworth’s Belinda (1800) follows in the wake of Charlotte Lennox’s The Female Quixote (1752): “Quixoticism becomes internalized and endemic,” not so much mistaking windmills for giants or men for adorers but for “failing to perceive oneself” (161). Edgeworth’s literature for children, Lee argues, “form[s] a bridge between the novel and natural philosophy at a moment when both were involved in this transition in the model of knowledge” (166). The experimental node in this chapter is the chemist Humphry Davy, who attained “an unprecedented popularity” as a “celebrity scientist” (161); his “experiments with nitrous oxide read almost like journeys into a pure, enclosed interior space of subjectivity” (163). Those experiments, like the new plots, “generat[e] a kind of suspense,” which in the novel becomes “an urgent experience of contiguity” (165). The argument works plausibly, for me, until it stumbles over William Godwin’s peculiar Gothic novel Caleb Williams (1796). “The plot seems not to know what to do with objects” (175) as they often remain unexplained. “The plot cannot even seem to convince itself and collapses aporetically, as shown in the two endings Godwin writes” (176). “The novel is left without a means of verifying, opening up or shutting down subjectivity” (176). Yet from another point of view, all of this precisely captures, in a gothically metaphoric way, the “realist” criteria of Barbauld and Scott: we do not always know what things mean, and “‘in real life our reasonable expectations are often disappointed.’” In other words, Godwin’s subtitle: Things as They Are.The last chapter, “Historical Vertigo and the Laws of Animal Motion,” focuses on Scott’s Waverley novels as examples in the turn toward “normaliz[ing] quixotism” and “posing subjectivity against objective truth” (183). “The historical novel’s plot looks for deeply buried forces that suddenly become manifest in certain conjunctures, driving that change and testing human subjects” (184). And the deeply buried forces here are connected to new theories about the “everyday experience of movement” (185), “a kind of quixotism of the body” (186), called vection or vertigo, a subjective, physiological sensation projecting movement onto the surroundings. Erasmus Darwin’s Zoonomia; or, The Laws of Organic Life (1795–96) becomes the partner here, as this work, like the “modern” novel in Scott’s view, studies and explains the minutiae of everyday life (189). And these detailed experiences, particularly the vertiginous ones, link to notions of empire as well: “the phenomenon of losing the ability to tell whether you’re moving or the world is moving, is the type of vection that Scott uses in Waverley to describe the experience of historical transition. The plot of many Waverley novels might be summarized in this sentence from Darwin: ‘When we are surrounded with unusual motions, we lose our perpendicularity’” (191). This is the source of the new “deep realism” (194): history is perceived as too large, too deep, too forceful, too much out of our control or comprehension; “it pushes and pulls, smooths the way or trips you up” (206).Lee closes her work with an epilogue, “Plot, History, and Totality in Zadie Smith’s White Teeth,” to bring her analysis into our contemporary relevance. “How do these connections between the novel and natural philosophy change? Do they disappear?” (207). Zadie Smith herself declared: “‘It is not the writer’s job … to tell us how somebody felt about something, it’s to tell us how the world works’” (quoted on 208). And with its own full collection of dates and events and scientific experiments, as well as its deliberate reduplications of those events, the novel draws attention to its plot as agent: “‘Every moment happens twice: inside and outside, and they are two different histories’” (quoted on 210). Smith’s novel makes the modern case for Lee’s historical argument.My one serious resistance to Lee’s impressive book is that it (along with Barbauld and Scott) assumes too much of a non-eighteenth-century sense of realism in its “certain dissatisfactions” with the formal coherence of eighteenth-century novels. For one thing, this overlooks or dismisses the Puritan legacy of finding detailed meaning in and divine connection between the smallest things, the smallest events (see, e.g., J. Paul Hunter, Before Novels [1990]). Nor does it seem to understand the devout sensibilities of Richardson and Fielding (“providence” is cited half a dozen times, but always in a cursory sort of way: “Fate, destiny, or providence may offer a semblance of an answer, but not a sufficient one for the realist novel” [7]). Samuel Johnson could remind them all that the “dangers” of the “realist” novel are precisely as threatening as those of the stage: “It is false, that any representation is mistaken for reality; that any dramatick fable in its materiality was ever credible, or, for a single moment, was ever credited.”3 Sure, there are a few gullible Arabellas and Partridges always among us, but (to paraphrase Johnson) the truth is that the reader is always in her senses, and knows, from the first page to the last, that the novel is only a novel, and that the characters are only characters.4 In fact, many of the scientific conclusions related in this book seem to offer satisfactorily coherent wholes, with all the smaller bits gathered into the larger pattern, as in John Desagulier’s description of gravity: “‘a heavy Body by its Descent moves the Axis of a Wheel, that carries round another by its Teeth, which by the Intermediation of other Wheels and Pinions, carries round a hand upon a Dial-Plate to measure Time, or for other Uses’” (A Course of Experimental Philosophy [1734], quoted on 140); or in Georges Cuvier’s sense of biolological logic: “‘Every organized being forms a whole, a unique and closed system, in which all the parts correspond mutually, and contribute to the same definitive action’” (“Preliminary Discourse” [1812], quoted on 155).But I go back and underline the word “impressive.” In its scope, its research, its originality, it is an important paving stone, so to speak, in our understanding of the novel. Lee’s book disarticulates plot from narrative and character, but she does not leave us with a macerated skeleton: plot is fused, living, into description and motion, matter and space, shaped by the forces that were seen shaping the (shall we say it?) real world.Notes1. Isaac Newton, Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica, trans. Andrew Motte, 3 vols. (1687; London, 1803), 1:15.2. This book amply details its overlap with and indebtedness to other past and recent scholars investigating relations between the novel and natural philosophy in the period; so after pointing here to Lorraine Daston and Peter Galison, as well as to Michel Foucault, I won’t cite the rest of the multitudes throughout.3. Samuel Johnson, preface to The Plays of William Shakespeare […], 2nd ed., 10 vols. (London, 1778), 1:xxvi.4. Ibid., 1:xxvii. Previous articleNext article DetailsFiguresReferencesCited by Modern Philology Ahead of Print Article DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1086/727803 HistoryPublished online October 04, 2023 For permission to reuse, please contact [email protected].PDF download Crossref reports no articles citing this article.","PeriodicalId":45201,"journal":{"name":"MODERN PHILOLOGY","volume":"3 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4000,"publicationDate":"2023-10-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"MODERN PHILOLOGY","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1086/727803","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"LANGUAGE & LINGUISTICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Previous articleNext article FreeBook ReviewThe Natural Laws of Plot: How Things Happen in Realist Novels. Yoon Sun Lee. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2023. Pp. 258.Cynthia WallCynthia WallUniversity of Virginia Search for more articles by this author PDFPDF PLUSFull Text Add to favoritesDownload CitationTrack CitationsPermissionsReprints Share onFacebookTwitterLinkedInRedditEmailPrint SectionsMoreIf a body impinge upon another, and by its force change the motion of the other, that body also … will undergo an equal change, in its own motion.(Isaac Newton, Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica [1687])1Newtonian physics is just one of the many new empiricisms employed in learned depth in The Natural Laws of Plot to argue that the plots of novels are as much if not more embedded in their own landscapes, “rely[ing] more deeply and intricately on an environing world to carry along any action” (2), as they are involved with narrative and characters. “Things have shadows and textures, as well as depths and surfaces,” and fictional events are shaped by the “real world of physical forces and laws” (3). Bodies impinge on bodies, motion changes bodies, matter mixes and moves. The real world kept discovering and describing new physical forces and laws, and the well-read British public (and its novelists) kept abreast of and internalized those discoveries as new ways of understanding “how things happen.” The chapters progress through the period, matching up canonical authors’ narrative strategies with natural philosophers and theories: Daniel-Defovian causality and Newtonian physics; the characters of Henry Fielding and Samuel Richardson and the types and orders of Carl Linnaeus and Georges-Louis Leclerc Buffon; Ann Radcliffe, Frances Burney, and chemistry; a molecular Jane Austen; Maria Edgeworth, Anna Lætitia Barbauld, Humphry Davy, and “mechanical objectivity”; Walter Scott, Erasmus Darwin, and vertigo. Throughout, the originally mingled concepts later identified as “objectivity” and “subjectivity” get disentangled, both historically and ideologically. In every historical, scientific, and narratological shift, the “external world” is always, like my uncle Toby’s map of Namur, “far more than an inert backdrop to action. It provides the laws that are then twisted into plot and pinned to the ground” (60).The first chapter, “Novels, Novel-Theory, and the History of Objectivity,” argues that objectivity is not “a way of telling the story with a certain detachment or from a third-person point of view” but “something that has to be built into the plot of the novel” (1) and that will change its appearance dramatically over time, in rhythm with the changing contours of natural philosophy, from the necessary subjectivity—the reliance “on their own accumulated experience, their knowledge, skill, and instincts” (9)—of the early empiricists to the active suppression of the self into the nineteenth century.2 “The novel emerged in tandem” (11) not only with changing perceptions of subjective identity but also with its own discourse about itself: “The novel was a problem for itself from the beginning” (11). While Clara Reeve, in The Progress of Romance (1785), distinguished the novel as “‘a picture of real life and manners, and of the times in which it was written,’” from the romance, which “‘describes what never happened nor is likely to happen’” (quoted on 12), Barbauld and Scott expanded on what Lee sees as a “certain dissatisfaction” (12) they all had digesting this sense of realism. Barbauld notes that the formal coherence of plot in most eighteenth-century novels leads the reader to predict the ending and relish the neat tidyings of loose ends, whereas “‘in real life our reasonable expectations are often disappointed’” (quoted on 13). Scott in fact approves of Defoe’s novels precisely because “‘The incidents are huddled together like paving-stones discharged from a cart, and have as little connexion between the one and the other’” (quoted on 14). Lee concludes, “There seem to be two kinds of possible plot-interest, then: one in which, through the author’s artful planning, we focus on discovering the relations between events widely separated in the novel’s discourse. In the other, we are absorbed in the event itself, the more inconsequential the better, in the way its unfolding suggests something about the world or ‘the real tendencies of things,’ to use Barbauld’s expression. This latter kind of interest seems to be peculiar to the novel, as Scott and others envisioned it at the beginning of the nineteenth century” (16).The second chapter, “Matter, Motion, and the Physical World of the Novel,” explores the ways that the “objective, regular behavior of matter in space and time is fundamental to realist plots and the way that the latter work themselves out” (35). Plot is much more than “intentional human movements” (34); it includes the minute chain of events that cause the window sash in Laurence Sterne’s Tristram Shandy (1759–67) to slam down on the young protagonist and, er, cut things short (33–34). The chapter traces the familiar links between empiricism and the novel but offers as its new claim that the empiricist view of the world provides a “baseline ontology” for the new shapes of novel plots, as captured in John Desagulier’s summary of Cartesian causality: “changes in plot happen because of changes in ‘Situation, Distance … Structure, and Cohesion,’ as well as the spaces between and within bodies” (39).“Defoe’s Outstretched World” celebrates the paving stone model of plot, in which events are conceived “in terms of forces that push, pull, move around, or stabilize the pieces of the world”; thus “physical plot underlies the actions, emotions, and reflections of the characters,” sometimes encouraging them, but more often “undercut[ting] them repeatedly, taking away something that was thought to be settled” (63). Defoe’s important contribution to plot, Lee argues, “isn’t concerned with the inner structure of decision, which he retains. In Robinson Crusoe [1719] rather, it has to do with the relation between action, knowledge, and time, the scale at which they are shown to interact, and, most of all, the specification of intermediating causes as things that produce reliable, precisely calculable physical effects in the external world” (72). Lee cites Defoe’s expert familiarity with early modern science as demonstrated in the General History of Discoveries and Improvements in Useful Arts (1725–26) and the detailed descriptions of experiments made by Robert Boyle and Newton; Defoe’s plots are interesting precisely because things that seem to happen randomly, such as Crusoe’s “miraculous” barley, can be traced back cause by logical cause.Fielding and Richardson are the centerpieces in “Place, Type, and Order: Plot as Natural History.” The “classical idea of plot as formal unity” (84) encounters a new “model of knowledge” in which natural philosophy would “[bring] together disparate phenomena so that gradations of similarity and difference became clearly visible”; the result is “a narrative deeply committed to the idea of order, and to the realm of the visible” (83–84). Fielding’s individuals relate to their types (or “species,” in Fielding’s word); in Richardson’s Clarissa (1747–48), the rake Robert Lovelace is continuously “testing” the virtue of Clarissa to see if she is in fact her very own species. What criteria would be enough? Both Fielding and Richardson “are driven by the need to ascertain the relationship between their protagonists and the type or species to which they apparently belong” (99).Chapter 5, “Tracing Change and Testing Substances: Intimate Objectivity,” brings the plots of Radcliffe and Burney into the realm of chemistry. “Their plots seem less interested in questions of agency, of who made what happen, than in questions of composition, of how something behaves because of what kind of substance it is” (107–8). The ductility of the protagonist in Burney’s Camilla “is what Camilla is” (123, emphasis added); the colors in Radcliffe’s famous descriptions come under the microscope (124). (Tobias Smollett’s Humphry Clinker [1771] gets a good treatment here because of its fascination with mixtures.)Miss Bates’s little monologues in Austen’s Emma (1815) demonstrate the “Molecular Possibility in Austen’s Plot” in chapter 6, “exhibit[ing] a field of minute, chaotic, incessant movements in which rivets, apples, and spectacles, the actions of eating and recommending bounce around, collide without losing any of their motion, and come back again, swirling around endlessly” (131). Indeed, Emma treats her country friend Harriet’s mind with the “detachment of a scientist,” considering it as “a material arrangement” in which one piece could be inserted in place of another to fill vacancies or displace attention—“the model is mechanical” (148).The next chapter takes up this model and its relation to “quixotism,” which “ties the shape of the plot to the distorted beliefs and perceptions of its protagonist,” highlighting the newly reconceived “dangers of subjectivity” (151). Edgeworth’s Belinda (1800) follows in the wake of Charlotte Lennox’s The Female Quixote (1752): “Quixoticism becomes internalized and endemic,” not so much mistaking windmills for giants or men for adorers but for “failing to perceive oneself” (161). Edgeworth’s literature for children, Lee argues, “form[s] a bridge between the novel and natural philosophy at a moment when both were involved in this transition in the model of knowledge” (166). The experimental node in this chapter is the chemist Humphry Davy, who attained “an unprecedented popularity” as a “celebrity scientist” (161); his “experiments with nitrous oxide read almost like journeys into a pure, enclosed interior space of subjectivity” (163). Those experiments, like the new plots, “generat[e] a kind of suspense,” which in the novel becomes “an urgent experience of contiguity” (165). The argument works plausibly, for me, until it stumbles over William Godwin’s peculiar Gothic novel Caleb Williams (1796). “The plot seems not to know what to do with objects” (175) as they often remain unexplained. “The plot cannot even seem to convince itself and collapses aporetically, as shown in the two endings Godwin writes” (176). “The novel is left without a means of verifying, opening up or shutting down subjectivity” (176). Yet from another point of view, all of this precisely captures, in a gothically metaphoric way, the “realist” criteria of Barbauld and Scott: we do not always know what things mean, and “‘in real life our reasonable expectations are often disappointed.’” In other words, Godwin’s subtitle: Things as They Are.The last chapter, “Historical Vertigo and the Laws of Animal Motion,” focuses on Scott’s Waverley novels as examples in the turn toward “normaliz[ing] quixotism” and “posing subjectivity against objective truth” (183). “The historical novel’s plot looks for deeply buried forces that suddenly become manifest in certain conjunctures, driving that change and testing human subjects” (184). And the deeply buried forces here are connected to new theories about the “everyday experience of movement” (185), “a kind of quixotism of the body” (186), called vection or vertigo, a subjective, physiological sensation projecting movement onto the surroundings. Erasmus Darwin’s Zoonomia; or, The Laws of Organic Life (1795–96) becomes the partner here, as this work, like the “modern” novel in Scott’s view, studies and explains the minutiae of everyday life (189). And these detailed experiences, particularly the vertiginous ones, link to notions of empire as well: “the phenomenon of losing the ability to tell whether you’re moving or the world is moving, is the type of vection that Scott uses in Waverley to describe the experience of historical transition. The plot of many Waverley novels might be summarized in this sentence from Darwin: ‘When we are surrounded with unusual motions, we lose our perpendicularity’” (191). This is the source of the new “deep realism” (194): history is perceived as too large, too deep, too forceful, too much out of our control or comprehension; “it pushes and pulls, smooths the way or trips you up” (206).Lee closes her work with an epilogue, “Plot, History, and Totality in Zadie Smith’s White Teeth,” to bring her analysis into our contemporary relevance. “How do these connections between the novel and natural philosophy change? Do they disappear?” (207). Zadie Smith herself declared: “‘It is not the writer’s job … to tell us how somebody felt about something, it’s to tell us how the world works’” (quoted on 208). And with its own full collection of dates and events and scientific experiments, as well as its deliberate reduplications of those events, the novel draws attention to its plot as agent: “‘Every moment happens twice: inside and outside, and they are two different histories’” (quoted on 210). Smith’s novel makes the modern case for Lee’s historical argument.My one serious resistance to Lee’s impressive book is that it (along with Barbauld and Scott) assumes too much of a non-eighteenth-century sense of realism in its “certain dissatisfactions” with the formal coherence of eighteenth-century novels. For one thing, this overlooks or dismisses the Puritan legacy of finding detailed meaning in and divine connection between the smallest things, the smallest events (see, e.g., J. Paul Hunter, Before Novels [1990]). Nor does it seem to understand the devout sensibilities of Richardson and Fielding (“providence” is cited half a dozen times, but always in a cursory sort of way: “Fate, destiny, or providence may offer a semblance of an answer, but not a sufficient one for the realist novel” [7]). Samuel Johnson could remind them all that the “dangers” of the “realist” novel are precisely as threatening as those of the stage: “It is false, that any representation is mistaken for reality; that any dramatick fable in its materiality was ever credible, or, for a single moment, was ever credited.”3 Sure, there are a few gullible Arabellas and Partridges always among us, but (to paraphrase Johnson) the truth is that the reader is always in her senses, and knows, from the first page to the last, that the novel is only a novel, and that the characters are only characters.4 In fact, many of the scientific conclusions related in this book seem to offer satisfactorily coherent wholes, with all the smaller bits gathered into the larger pattern, as in John Desagulier’s description of gravity: “‘a heavy Body by its Descent moves the Axis of a Wheel, that carries round another by its Teeth, which by the Intermediation of other Wheels and Pinions, carries round a hand upon a Dial-Plate to measure Time, or for other Uses’” (A Course of Experimental Philosophy [1734], quoted on 140); or in Georges Cuvier’s sense of biolological logic: “‘Every organized being forms a whole, a unique and closed system, in which all the parts correspond mutually, and contribute to the same definitive action’” (“Preliminary Discourse” [1812], quoted on 155).But I go back and underline the word “impressive.” In its scope, its research, its originality, it is an important paving stone, so to speak, in our understanding of the novel. Lee’s book disarticulates plot from narrative and character, but she does not leave us with a macerated skeleton: plot is fused, living, into description and motion, matter and space, shaped by the forces that were seen shaping the (shall we say it?) real world.Notes1. Isaac Newton, Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica, trans. Andrew Motte, 3 vols. (1687; London, 1803), 1:15.2. This book amply details its overlap with and indebtedness to other past and recent scholars investigating relations between the novel and natural philosophy in the period; so after pointing here to Lorraine Daston and Peter Galison, as well as to Michel Foucault, I won’t cite the rest of the multitudes throughout.3. Samuel Johnson, preface to The Plays of William Shakespeare […], 2nd ed., 10 vols. (London, 1778), 1:xxvi.4. Ibid., 1:xxvii. Previous articleNext article DetailsFiguresReferencesCited by Modern Philology Ahead of Print Article DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1086/727803 HistoryPublished online October 04, 2023 For permission to reuse, please contact [email protected].PDF download Crossref reports no articles citing this article.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
《情节的自然法则:现实主义小说中的事情是如何发生的
情节远不止是“有意的人类动作”(34);它包括劳伦斯·斯特恩(Laurence Sterne)的《崔斯特拉姆·珊迪》(Tristram Shandy, 1759-67)中导致窗扇重重地落在年轻主人公身上,缩短了时间的一系列微小事件(33-34页)。这一章追溯了经验主义与小说之间熟悉的联系,但提出了新的主张,即经验主义的世界观为小说情节的新形态提供了一个“基线本体论”,正如约翰·德萨吉耶(John Desagulier)对笛卡尔因果关系的总结所捕捉到的那样:“情节的变化是因为‘情境、距离、结构和凝聚力’以及身体之间和内部空间的变化而发生的”(39)。《笛福伸展的世界》颂扬了铺路石式的情节模式,在这种模式中,事件是“根据推动、拉动、移动或稳定世界碎片的力量”来构思的;因此,“物理情节是人物行为、情感和反思的基础”,有时会鼓励他们,但更多的时候是“反复削弱他们,拿走一些被认为已经解决的东西”(63)。李认为笛福对情节的重要贡献“与他保留的决定的内部结构无关。在《鲁滨逊漂流记》[1719]中,它与行动、知识和时间之间的关系有关,与它们相互作用的尺度有关,最重要的是,将中介原因作为在外部世界中产生可靠的、可精确计算的物理效应的事物进行说明”(72)。李引用笛福对早期现代科学的专业熟悉,这在《实用艺术的发现和改进通史》(1725-26)中得到了证明,他还详细描述了罗伯特·波义耳和牛顿所做的实验;笛福的情节之所以有趣,正是因为那些看似随机发生的事情,比如克鲁索的“神奇”大麦,可以通过逻辑原因追溯到原因。菲尔丁和理查森是《地点、类型和秩序:作为自然史的情节》一书的核心人物。“将情节作为形式统一的经典观念”(84)遇到了一种新的“知识模式”,在这种模式下,自然哲学将“把完全不同的现象汇集在一起,从而使相似和差异的层次变得清晰可见”;其结果是“一种深深致力于秩序观念和可见领域的叙事”(83-84)。菲尔丁的个体与他们的类型(或者用菲尔丁的话来说是“物种”)有关;在理查森的《克拉丽莎》(1747-48)中,浪子罗伯特·洛夫莱斯不断地“测试”克拉丽莎的美德,看她是否真的是她自己的同类。什么样的标准才足够?菲尔丁和理查森都“被确定他们的主人公和他们显然所属的类型或物种之间的关系的需要所驱使”(99)。第五章“追踪变化和测试物质:亲密的客观性”将拉德克利夫和伯尼的情节带入了化学领域。“他们的情节似乎对主体的问题不太感兴趣,谁制造了什么,而更感兴趣的是构成的问题,因为它是什么样的物质而如何表现”(107-8)。在伯尼的《卡米拉》中,主角的延展性“就是卡米拉本身”(123,强调添加);雷德克里夫的著名描述中的色彩被置于显微镜下(124)。(托拜厄斯·斯莫列特的《汉弗莱·克林克》[1771]在这里得到了很好的处理,因为它对混合物很着迷。)贝茨小姐在奥斯丁的《爱玛》(1815)中的独白展示了第六章中“奥斯丁情节中的分子可能性”,“展示了一个微小的、混乱的、不间断的运动领域,其中铆钉、苹果、眼镜、吃东西和推荐的动作来回弹跳,碰撞而不失去任何运动,然后再回来,无休止地旋转”(131)。的确,艾玛以“科学家的超然”对待她的乡村朋友哈丽特的思想,认为它是“一种物质安排”,可以用一块代替另一块来填补空缺或转移注意力——“这个模型是机械的”(148)。下一章将讨论这一模式及其与“堂吉诃德主义”的关系,后者“将情节的形状与主人公扭曲的信仰和感知联系在一起”,强调了新认识的“主体性的危险”(151)。埃奇沃斯的《贝琳达》(1800)紧随夏洛特·伦诺克斯的《女堂吉诃德》(1752):“堂吉诃德主义变得内化和地方化了”,与其说是把风车误认为巨人,或者把男人误认为崇拜者,不如说是“没有认识到自己”(161)。李认为,埃奇沃斯的儿童文学“在小说和自然哲学之间架起了一座桥梁,当时两者都参与了知识模式的转变”(166)。 本章的实验节点是化学家汉弗莱·戴维(Humphry Davy),他作为“名人科学家”获得了“前所未有的知名度”(161);他“对一氧化二氮的实验读起来几乎就像进入一个纯粹的、封闭的主体性内部空间的旅行”(163)。这些实验,就像新的情节一样,“产生了一种悬念”,在小说中成为“一种紧急的相邻体验”(165)。对我来说,这个论点似乎是合理的,直到它被威廉·戈德温(William Godwin)奇特的哥特式小说《迦勒·威廉姆斯》(Caleb Williams, 1796)绊倒。“情节似乎不知道如何处理物体”(175),因为它们经常无法解释。戈德温写道:“情节甚至连自己都无法说服,就像两个结局一样,在悲剧中崩溃了”(176)。“小说失去了验证、开放或关闭主观性的手段”(176)。然而,从另一个角度来看,所有这些都以一种哥特式的隐喻方式,准确地抓住了巴博尔德和斯科特的“现实主义”标准:我们并不总是知道事物的意义,“在现实生活中,我们合理的期望往往会落空。”’”换句话说,戈德温的副标题是:事物的本来面目。最后一章,“历史眩晕和动物运动规律”,将斯科特的韦弗利小说作为转向“堂吉诃德主义正常化”和“以主观性反对客观真理”的例子(183)。“历史小说的情节寻找埋藏在深处的力量,这些力量在某些时刻突然显现出来,推动着这种变化,考验着人类的主体”(184)。在这里,被深深掩埋的力量与“日常运动体验”(185)、“身体的一种堂吉诃德主义”(186)的新理论有关,被称为“矢量”或“眩晕”,一种主观的生理感觉,将运动投射到周围环境中。伊拉斯谟·达尔文的《动物学》;《有机生命的法则》(The Laws of Organic Life, 1795-96)成为了这里的合作伙伴,因为这部作品就像斯科特眼中的“现代”小说一样,研究和解释了日常生活的细枝末节(189)。这些详细的经历,尤其是那些令人眩晕的经历,也与帝国的概念有关:“失去分辨自己在移动还是世界在移动的能力的现象,是斯科特在韦弗利中用来描述历史转型经历的一种流动。韦弗利许多小说的情节可以用达尔文的这句话来概括:“当我们被不寻常的运动包围时,我们就失去了垂直性”(191)。这就是新的“深度现实主义”的来源(194):历史被认为太大,太深,太有力,太超出我们的控制或理解;“它推你拉你,使你走得平坦或使你跌倒”(206)。李以结束语“扎迪·史密斯的白牙中的情节、历史和整体”结束了她的作品,将她的分析带入我们当代的相关性。“小说和自然哲学之间的联系是如何变化的?”它们消失了吗?”(207)。扎迪·史密斯自己宣称:“作家的工作不是告诉我们某人对某事的感受,而是告诉我们世界是如何运转的”(引用于第208页)。凭借自己收集的全部日期、事件和科学实验,以及对这些事件的刻意重复,小说将人们的注意力吸引到作为代理人的情节上:“‘每一刻都发生两次:内部和外部,它们是两种不同的历史’”(引用于第210页)。史密斯的小说为李的历史观点提供了现代的论据。我对李这本令人印象深刻的书的一个严重抵制是,它(以及巴博尔德和斯科特)在对18世纪小说的正式连贯性的“某些不满”中,假设了太多非18世纪的现实主义。首先,这忽略或忽视了清教徒的遗产,即在最小的事物和最小的事件之间寻找详细的意义和神圣的联系(例如,参见J. Paul Hunter的《小说之前》[1990])。它似乎也不理解理查森和菲尔丁的虔诚情感(“天意”被引用了六次,但总是以一种粗略的方式:“命运、宿命或天意可能提供了一个表面上的答案,但对现实主义小说来说还不够”[7])。塞缪尔·约翰逊可以提醒他们所有人,“现实主义”小说的“危险”恰恰与舞台上的“危险”一样具有威胁性:“任何表现都被误认为是现实,这是错误的;任何戏剧性的寓言在它的物质性上都是可信的,或者,哪怕是一瞬间,都是可信的。当然,我们身边总有一些容易上当受骗的阿拉贝拉和帕特里奇,但(用约翰逊的话来说)事实是,读者总是有自己的感觉,从第一页到最后一页,他都知道小说只是小说,小说中的人物也只是人物。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
MODERN PHILOLOGY
MODERN PHILOLOGY Multiple-
CiteScore
0.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
64
期刊介绍: Founded in 1903, Modern Philology sets the standard for literary scholarship, history, and criticism. In addition to innovative and scholarly articles (in English) on literature in all modern world languages, MP also publishes insightful book reviews of recent books as well as review articles and research on archival documents. Editor Richard Strier is happy to announce that we now welcome contributions on literature in non-European languages and contributions that productively compare texts or traditions from European and non-European literatures. In general, we expect contributions to be written in (or translated into) English, and we expect quotations from non-English languages to be translated into English as well as reproduced in the original.
期刊最新文献
:Black Shakespeare: Reading and Misreading Race :Pain, Penance, and Protest: Peine Forte et Dure in Medieval England :The Politics of Speech in Later Twentieth-Century Poetry: Local Tongues in Heaney, Brooks, Harrison, and Clifton :Melville, Beauty, and American Literary Studies: An Aesthetics in All Things :Heroic Awe: The Sublime and the Remaking of Renaissance Epic
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1