Why Every Belief is a Choice: Descartes’ Doxastic Voluntarism Reconsidered

IF 0.7 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES Pub Date : 2023-03-15 DOI:10.1080/09672559.2023.2235369
Mark Boespflug
{"title":"Why Every Belief is a Choice: Descartes’ Doxastic Voluntarism Reconsidered","authors":"Mark Boespflug","doi":"10.1080/09672559.2023.2235369","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTDescartes appears to hold that everything we believe is the product of a voluntary choice. Scholars have been reluctant to take this particularly radical version of doxastic voluntarism as Descartes’ considered position. I argue that once Descartes’ compatibilist conception of free will as well as his position on the ‘freedom of indifference’ are taken into account, the primary motivations for the rejection of the aforementioned radical version of doxastic voluntarism lose their force. Consequently, we may take Descartes at his word when he maintains that everything we believe, we believe freely – even if we cannot believe anything we wish.KEYWORDS: Descartesdoxastic voluntarismvoluntary beliefwillassentepistemic deontologism Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. As will be seen below, however, it is a matter of dispute whether Descartes means to be articulating a voluntarist position in the Fourth Meditation. Some scholars directly challenge this interpretation of the Fourth Meditation (O’Hear Citation1979). Others argue that Descartes endorsed the less extreme indirect version of voluntarism (Newman Citation2015; Cottingham Citation2008, ch. 11)—which, in spite of the name, amounts to a rejection of the view that belief is under the voluntary control of the will.2. I will follow that portion of the literature that refrains from drawing a distinction between assent, belief and judgment in Descartes. Della Rocca (Citation2006) makes this explicit. Schuessler (Citation2013, 150) uses the three terms interchangeably. Though Newman (Citation2015, 63) appears to understand judgment to be a discrete concept from belief and assent, he claims that the latter two notions are interchangeable. Cottingham (Citation2008, ch. 11) uses belief and assent interchangeably.3. Though Williams (Citation1978) and Alston (Citation1988) are most explicit about this, their influential interpretations have been taken up by a number of Descartes scholars. Alston, it should be noted, only mentions Descartes in passing.4. Newman (Citation2015, 65); Cottingham (Citation2008, 225-7) seems to reject this as a possibility as well. See also Grant (Citation1976).5. Vitz (Citation2010); Davies (Citation2001); Schuessler (Citation2013).6. Cottingham (Citation2008, ch. 8); Newman (Citation2015); Carriero (Citation2009, ch. 4); Kenny (Citation1973).7. Direct doxastic voluntarism can come in a variety of strengths—from holding that we may exercise direct control over some very specific subset of our beliefs to holding that we exercise direct control over all of our beliefs. Descartes, I argue, falls on the latter end of the spectrum.8. I am thinking here of the seminal attacks on doxastic voluntarism by Alston (Citation1988) and Williams (Citation1970). While there is a great deal of philosophically valuable material in both works, there are also systemic deficiencies such that even if one grants the premises of the arguments in both, the falsity (or even probable falsity) of doxastic voluntarism simply does not follow. This is mainly because of their lack of address of compatibilist conceptions of doxastic voluntarism, which, as we’ll see, Descartes endorsed. Recapitulations of such arguments tend to suffer from the same deficiencies. This is true of Buckareff’s attempt (Citation2014) to resuscitate Williams’ argument as well as Peels’ Alston-style argument (Citation2016, ch. 2).9. Descartes did not hold there is a distinction between an act being voluntary and its being free (as, for instance, Locke did (Essay II.xxi.5–11)). References to Locke, Essay, are to Locke (Citation1975), An Essay concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch, cited in the text as ‘Essay‘, followed by book, chapter, section number. In his replies to Hobbes’ objections to the Meditations, Descartes claims: ‘If we simply consider ourselves, we will all realize in the light of our own experience that voluntariness and freedom are one and the same thing’ (Third Replies AT VII: 191; CSM II: 134). In other places he uses the two terms synonymously. For instance, in the Principles, ‘The supreme perfection of man is that he acts freely or voluntarily, and it is this which makes him deserve praise or blame’ (AT VIIIA: 19; CSM I: 205). The ‘or,’ here, is clearly epexegetical. For he goes on, ‘It is the supreme perfection in man that he acts voluntarily, that is, freely.’ Further on, he continues to use the two terms interchangeably. References to Descartes’ writings are to Descartes (Citation1964–76), Oeuvres de Descartes, ed. Charles Adam and Paul Tannery, 12 vols., cited as ‘AT’ followed by volume and page number, and to Descartes (Citation1984–91), The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, ed. and tr. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch (and Anthony Kenny, vol. 3), cited as ‘CSM’ for vols. 1 and 2, followed by volume and page number.10. Della Rocca (Citation2006, 153); Cottingham (Citation2008, 222). Contemporary expressions of this view are found in Steup (Citation2000, Citation2008, Citation2012, Citation2017) as well as Sharon Ryan (Citation2003, Citation2015).11. A number of authors have pointed out that this is starkly out of keeping with the scholastic conception of judgment and therefore should be viewed as one of the most interesting developments in the Fourth Meditation (Lennon Citation2014, 173; Alanen Citation2003, ch. 7). Yet, as Nuchelmans (Citation1983, 47–55) has pointed out, it is not terribly novel insofar as much the same idea was operative in stoic philosophy, which Descartes certainly admired (Rutherford Citation2014). For the stoic, judging or believing is a function of the will (E.g., Epictetus (Citation2004, 1)).12. Though this seems a rather strong way to put it, this appears to be what Descartes’ framework demands. Della Rocca, for instance, apparently interprets Descartes in precisely this fashion: ‘Descartes assimilates belief to ordinary action: believing that my stupid friends have locked the freezer and wielding an axe to break the lock are each actions in the same sense: they result from an appropriate combination of intellect and will, of representational and non-representational states’ (Citation2006, 124).13. It is not a promising strategy to suggest that Descartes meant that we have indirect control, but that he simply did not have the concepts at hand to adequately articulate this position. For proposals maintaining that the central locus of doxastic control consisted in indirect means had been articulated in scholastic philosophy at least as early as the fourteenth century by the eminent English Dominican, Robert Holcot. See Boespflug (Citation2018).14. This is Williams’ (Citation1970) way of characterizing direct control.15. Alston’s (Citation1988, 260) way of putting it is similar16. See Alston (Citation1988, 269) for a further discussion of this point.17. This is Alston’s example (Citation1988, 263).18. This is true of Alston (Citation1988, 261) and Williams (Citation1970). Plantinga (Citation1993, 23) may interpret Descartes this way as well, though it is less clear. Some of Wilson’s remarks suggest this position. In light of what she takes Descartes’ position, she demurs, ‘We can’t just decide to believe or assent to something, and forthwith believe it or assent to it’ (Citation1978, 145).19. Though Williams’ famous essay, ‘Deciding to Believe,’ is generally taken to fail in its aim to show that believing at will is metaphysically impossible, many authors hold that Williams’ claim about belief possessing a truth-aim does capture something significant about the nature of belief that is in tension with the idea that belief may be voluntary (Citation1970).20. Alston (Citation1988) takes a very different approach than Williams in arguing that doxastic voluntarism is false. Alston attempts to show that it is a mere contingent psychological fact that one cannot believe at will.21. Schuessler (Citation2013, 374–5) has noticed this. It is true that Alston is substantially more sensitive to different varieties of doxastic control than Williams, and deals with a number of them. Nevertheless, he never quite seems to address either Descartes’ view, that of the scholastics, or John Henry Newman (whom he cites).22. Yet, it is important to note that just because I cannot voluntarily believe that the U.S. is a colony of Great Britain, this does not necessarily mean that my believing that it is not a colony of Great Britain is not within my doxastic control (excuse the triple negative). After all, my inability to gouge my eye out with my pen does not mean that I lack voluntary control over not doing so. This is just to say that doxastic compulsion may be perfectly compatible with doxastic freedom or voluntary control. And some would say it certainly is. See, for instance, Steup (Citation2000, Citation2008).23. It is important to note that, even if Descartes’ voluntarism is restricted in the sense that there are some propositions that we are unable to assent to, it is unrestricted in the sense that everything we end up believing is voluntary.24. Della Rocca (Citation2006, 154); Ragland (Citation2006), unpublished manuscript; Patterson (Citation2011); Cottingham (Citation1986, 83, Citation2008, 348–9); Newman (Citation2015, 68).25. Moreover, as has been pointed out by several contemporary pragmatists, believing what is likely to be true is typically of most practical benefit to one (Rinard Citation2017; MacGuire and Wood Citation2020). Thus, the belief that is likely to be true is also probably most practically beneficial. A significant difficulty for the pragmatist position is the existence of beliefs that are the product of self-deception; these seem at once unlikely to be true, yet practically beneficial. This is an issue that requires of the pragmatist a considerable response.26. Descartes would certainly approve of Steup’s referring to this sort of position as a sort of chauvinism. ‘Let’s refer to [this] view as Chauvinism: Whereas responsiveness to practical reasons grounds freedom, responsiveness to epistemic reasons does not’ (Citation2008, 388). Locke, interestingly, holds basically the opposite position. He takes the mind’s natural proclivity toward believing what is likely to be true to exclude the voluntariness, freedom and the will’s direct involvement in general from the process of belief formation (Boespflug Citation2021).27. Newman (Citation2015, 69, 72), for instance, maintains that if one holds that clarity and distinctness determine assent, that assent cannot be voluntary.28. Della Rocca (Citation2006) and Curley (Citation1975) think similarly. There is, in addition, a substantial debate regarding whether Descartes was a compatibilist or libertarian regarding free will. Thomas Lennon (Citation2013, Citation2014) has been one of the most outspoken supporters of the compatibilist take on Descartes, though there are other supporters (e.g., Chappell Citation1994). C.P. Ragland (Citation2006, Citation2016), on the other hand, is a leading defender of interpreting Descartes as a libertarian. Other supporters of this view are Schmaltz (Citation2008) and Wee (Citation2014).29. Or any other plausible version of compatibilism for that matter.30. Cottingham (Citation2008, 355); Kenny (Citation1973, 109); Newman (Citation2014, Citation2015); Carriero (Citation2009, 60–3).31. Cottingham (Citation2008, 225–6). It should be noted that this criticism may be misplaced, given that Cottingham is ambiguous about what he means by Descartes being a doxastic determinist. In certain places he seems to be referring solely to clear and distinct perceptions while in others to all cases of belief formation. His connecting doxastic determinism to involuntarism—as well as his more general insistence that indirect control is the primary kind of doxastic control we have—suggests, however, that he has something fully general in mind. Newman (Citation2015), for instance, is fairly clear that we should interpret Descartes as holding that our assent is determined in that we must acquire a certain doxastic attitude once we direct our attention in certain ways, even if the directing of our attention is within our voluntary control Locke holds something close to the view being described: ‘It depends not on [Man’s] Will to see that Black, which appears Yellow; nor to persuade himself, that what actually scalds him, feels cold: The Earth will not appear painted with Flowers, nor Fields covered with Verdure, whenever he has a Mind to it: in the cold Winter, he cannot help seeing it white and hoary, if he will look abroad. Just thus is it with our Understanding…. As far as Men’s Senses are conversant about external Objects, the Mind cannot but receive those Ideas, which are presented by them, and be informed of the Existence of Things without…. For what a Man sees, he cannot but see; and what he perceives, he cannot but know that he perceives.’ (Essay IV.xiii.2)32. Curley articulates what seems to be a standard interpretation, namely, that the freedom of indifference has a broad scope: ‘Where the perception of the intellect is not clear and distinct, then the will is always more or less indifferent to what is proposed to it and therefore able to choose either’ (Citation1993, 165–6). So, it would seem that all perceptions that fail to be clear and distinct would have an element of indifference. Ragland adds that this sort of indifference is most fundamentally motivational (and, consequently, such situations may furnish a two-way power): ‘Humans who act from indifference are subject to a kind of internal motivational division or conflict rooted in their inability to see clearly’ (unpublished manuscript, 13).33. Principles I.45; AT VIIIa: 22; CSM I: 207–8. Mersenne (Second Objections AT VII: 126–127; CSM II: 90) claims the same thing in his objections, and Descartes (Second Replies AT VII: 149; CSM II: 106) expresses no disagreement.34. While there are reasons to think that the scope of indifference is somewhat narrower than Curley suggests, it is quite difficult to say what exactly it is. For Descartes periodically identifies certain propositions that are not clear and distinct but that, nonetheless, he seems compelled to believe: for example, those things that ‘are quite impossible to doubt’ in the First Meditation, (AT VII: 18; CSM II: 17) and those that produce ‘a great propensity to believe’ in the Sixth (AT VII: 80-81; CSM II: 55–6). The examples Descartes gives are that material objects exist, that he has a body, and that it is as though he is intermingle (quasi permixtum) with that body. Jeremy Hyman offers a different interpretation of this passage, maintaining that Descartes’ reference to the ‘great propensity to believe’ means that such propositions are actually clear and distinct (Citation2019). In any case, whether there is clarity and distinctness on the scene or not, it seems that it would be misleading to maintain that the will is indifferent in such cases. What’s more, surely the freedom I have in believing, for instance, that I am intermingled with my body is at least not quite the lowest grade. My own sense is that we should regard perfect indifference and clarity and distinctness as occupying two ends of a normative, and correspondingly psychological, spectrum: in paradigm cases of clear and distinct perceptions, it is completely obvious which option I ought to choose—and psychological certainty is generated—while in paradigm cases of indifference, the options are on an absolute par—and perhaps suspension of assent is the psychological result. In these latter sorts of situations, we are as it were like Buridan’s ass between two piles of hay. But since clarity and distinctness as well as indifference come in degrees for Descartes, it is difficult to say where the one ends and the other begins. Yet, what does seem clear is that Descartes gives us compelling reason to think that he did not endorse doxastic determinism.35. Ragland offers an insightful discussion of both related problems for Lex Newman’s (Citation2015) indirect voluntarist reading of Descartes as well as some potential solutions.36. Especially Audi (Citation2001).37. Davies, (Citation2001, ch. 5); Vitz (Citation2010); Schuessler (Citation2013). It should be noted that Schuessler’s treatment adds a number of sophisticated nuances to Descartes’ conception of doxastic control. For instance, he maintains that the doxastic control involved in the First Meditation is merely indirect, having been generated by ‘skeptical techniques.’ Schuessler, likewise, isolates other sorts of control operative in other dimensions of Descartes’ philosophy (173). But he ultimately claims that ‘We may thus confidently saddle Descartes with a gatekeeper model of doxastic control’ (157).38. Vitz (Citation2010) offers a similar picture: Descartes held ‘the thesis that people have the ability to suspend, or to withhold, judgment directly by an act of will. Call this negative DDV [direct doxastic voluntarism]’ (108). Vitz also maintains that there is little textual evidence that Descartes held ‘that people have the ability to form a judgment directly by an act of will. Call this positive DDV’ (108). So, the will plays an essentially negative role. While it is able to insert itself into the process of belief formation by putting a halt to acquiring beliefs, it is not correspondingly able to cause beliefs to be formed.39. Though I allow that it is unclear whether Descartes holds that one has the power to suspend judgments regarding clear and distinct perceptions.40. Moreover, with the exception of Schuessler (Citation2013), the above authors could be substantially more sensitive to the indirect means that may be employed in generating the skeptical frame of mind in, for instance, the First Meditation.41. In spite of Vitz’s claim that there is little textual evidence that Descartes held ‘that people have the ability to form a judgment directly by an act of will’ (Citation2010, 115–6), Vitz says little in service of closing off the possibility that this straightforward reading is how Descartes ought to be interpreted.42. Esp. Vitz (Citation2010, section II).43. Vitz (Citation2010, section II).44. This article benefitted from discussions with Robert Pasnau, Matthias Steup, Scott Ragland, and Dan Kaufman. A special thanks also to the editors of this volume—Ruth Boeker and Graham Clay—and to two anonymous reviewers for a number of insightful recommendations.","PeriodicalId":51828,"journal":{"name":"INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"112 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2023-03-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/09672559.2023.2235369","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

ABSTRACTDescartes appears to hold that everything we believe is the product of a voluntary choice. Scholars have been reluctant to take this particularly radical version of doxastic voluntarism as Descartes’ considered position. I argue that once Descartes’ compatibilist conception of free will as well as his position on the ‘freedom of indifference’ are taken into account, the primary motivations for the rejection of the aforementioned radical version of doxastic voluntarism lose their force. Consequently, we may take Descartes at his word when he maintains that everything we believe, we believe freely – even if we cannot believe anything we wish.KEYWORDS: Descartesdoxastic voluntarismvoluntary beliefwillassentepistemic deontologism Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. As will be seen below, however, it is a matter of dispute whether Descartes means to be articulating a voluntarist position in the Fourth Meditation. Some scholars directly challenge this interpretation of the Fourth Meditation (O’Hear Citation1979). Others argue that Descartes endorsed the less extreme indirect version of voluntarism (Newman Citation2015; Cottingham Citation2008, ch. 11)—which, in spite of the name, amounts to a rejection of the view that belief is under the voluntary control of the will.2. I will follow that portion of the literature that refrains from drawing a distinction between assent, belief and judgment in Descartes. Della Rocca (Citation2006) makes this explicit. Schuessler (Citation2013, 150) uses the three terms interchangeably. Though Newman (Citation2015, 63) appears to understand judgment to be a discrete concept from belief and assent, he claims that the latter two notions are interchangeable. Cottingham (Citation2008, ch. 11) uses belief and assent interchangeably.3. Though Williams (Citation1978) and Alston (Citation1988) are most explicit about this, their influential interpretations have been taken up by a number of Descartes scholars. Alston, it should be noted, only mentions Descartes in passing.4. Newman (Citation2015, 65); Cottingham (Citation2008, 225-7) seems to reject this as a possibility as well. See also Grant (Citation1976).5. Vitz (Citation2010); Davies (Citation2001); Schuessler (Citation2013).6. Cottingham (Citation2008, ch. 8); Newman (Citation2015); Carriero (Citation2009, ch. 4); Kenny (Citation1973).7. Direct doxastic voluntarism can come in a variety of strengths—from holding that we may exercise direct control over some very specific subset of our beliefs to holding that we exercise direct control over all of our beliefs. Descartes, I argue, falls on the latter end of the spectrum.8. I am thinking here of the seminal attacks on doxastic voluntarism by Alston (Citation1988) and Williams (Citation1970). While there is a great deal of philosophically valuable material in both works, there are also systemic deficiencies such that even if one grants the premises of the arguments in both, the falsity (or even probable falsity) of doxastic voluntarism simply does not follow. This is mainly because of their lack of address of compatibilist conceptions of doxastic voluntarism, which, as we’ll see, Descartes endorsed. Recapitulations of such arguments tend to suffer from the same deficiencies. This is true of Buckareff’s attempt (Citation2014) to resuscitate Williams’ argument as well as Peels’ Alston-style argument (Citation2016, ch. 2).9. Descartes did not hold there is a distinction between an act being voluntary and its being free (as, for instance, Locke did (Essay II.xxi.5–11)). References to Locke, Essay, are to Locke (Citation1975), An Essay concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch, cited in the text as ‘Essay‘, followed by book, chapter, section number. In his replies to Hobbes’ objections to the Meditations, Descartes claims: ‘If we simply consider ourselves, we will all realize in the light of our own experience that voluntariness and freedom are one and the same thing’ (Third Replies AT VII: 191; CSM II: 134). In other places he uses the two terms synonymously. For instance, in the Principles, ‘The supreme perfection of man is that he acts freely or voluntarily, and it is this which makes him deserve praise or blame’ (AT VIIIA: 19; CSM I: 205). The ‘or,’ here, is clearly epexegetical. For he goes on, ‘It is the supreme perfection in man that he acts voluntarily, that is, freely.’ Further on, he continues to use the two terms interchangeably. References to Descartes’ writings are to Descartes (Citation1964–76), Oeuvres de Descartes, ed. Charles Adam and Paul Tannery, 12 vols., cited as ‘AT’ followed by volume and page number, and to Descartes (Citation1984–91), The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, ed. and tr. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch (and Anthony Kenny, vol. 3), cited as ‘CSM’ for vols. 1 and 2, followed by volume and page number.10. Della Rocca (Citation2006, 153); Cottingham (Citation2008, 222). Contemporary expressions of this view are found in Steup (Citation2000, Citation2008, Citation2012, Citation2017) as well as Sharon Ryan (Citation2003, Citation2015).11. A number of authors have pointed out that this is starkly out of keeping with the scholastic conception of judgment and therefore should be viewed as one of the most interesting developments in the Fourth Meditation (Lennon Citation2014, 173; Alanen Citation2003, ch. 7). Yet, as Nuchelmans (Citation1983, 47–55) has pointed out, it is not terribly novel insofar as much the same idea was operative in stoic philosophy, which Descartes certainly admired (Rutherford Citation2014). For the stoic, judging or believing is a function of the will (E.g., Epictetus (Citation2004, 1)).12. Though this seems a rather strong way to put it, this appears to be what Descartes’ framework demands. Della Rocca, for instance, apparently interprets Descartes in precisely this fashion: ‘Descartes assimilates belief to ordinary action: believing that my stupid friends have locked the freezer and wielding an axe to break the lock are each actions in the same sense: they result from an appropriate combination of intellect and will, of representational and non-representational states’ (Citation2006, 124).13. It is not a promising strategy to suggest that Descartes meant that we have indirect control, but that he simply did not have the concepts at hand to adequately articulate this position. For proposals maintaining that the central locus of doxastic control consisted in indirect means had been articulated in scholastic philosophy at least as early as the fourteenth century by the eminent English Dominican, Robert Holcot. See Boespflug (Citation2018).14. This is Williams’ (Citation1970) way of characterizing direct control.15. Alston’s (Citation1988, 260) way of putting it is similar16. See Alston (Citation1988, 269) for a further discussion of this point.17. This is Alston’s example (Citation1988, 263).18. This is true of Alston (Citation1988, 261) and Williams (Citation1970). Plantinga (Citation1993, 23) may interpret Descartes this way as well, though it is less clear. Some of Wilson’s remarks suggest this position. In light of what she takes Descartes’ position, she demurs, ‘We can’t just decide to believe or assent to something, and forthwith believe it or assent to it’ (Citation1978, 145).19. Though Williams’ famous essay, ‘Deciding to Believe,’ is generally taken to fail in its aim to show that believing at will is metaphysically impossible, many authors hold that Williams’ claim about belief possessing a truth-aim does capture something significant about the nature of belief that is in tension with the idea that belief may be voluntary (Citation1970).20. Alston (Citation1988) takes a very different approach than Williams in arguing that doxastic voluntarism is false. Alston attempts to show that it is a mere contingent psychological fact that one cannot believe at will.21. Schuessler (Citation2013, 374–5) has noticed this. It is true that Alston is substantially more sensitive to different varieties of doxastic control than Williams, and deals with a number of them. Nevertheless, he never quite seems to address either Descartes’ view, that of the scholastics, or John Henry Newman (whom he cites).22. Yet, it is important to note that just because I cannot voluntarily believe that the U.S. is a colony of Great Britain, this does not necessarily mean that my believing that it is not a colony of Great Britain is not within my doxastic control (excuse the triple negative). After all, my inability to gouge my eye out with my pen does not mean that I lack voluntary control over not doing so. This is just to say that doxastic compulsion may be perfectly compatible with doxastic freedom or voluntary control. And some would say it certainly is. See, for instance, Steup (Citation2000, Citation2008).23. It is important to note that, even if Descartes’ voluntarism is restricted in the sense that there are some propositions that we are unable to assent to, it is unrestricted in the sense that everything we end up believing is voluntary.24. Della Rocca (Citation2006, 154); Ragland (Citation2006), unpublished manuscript; Patterson (Citation2011); Cottingham (Citation1986, 83, Citation2008, 348–9); Newman (Citation2015, 68).25. Moreover, as has been pointed out by several contemporary pragmatists, believing what is likely to be true is typically of most practical benefit to one (Rinard Citation2017; MacGuire and Wood Citation2020). Thus, the belief that is likely to be true is also probably most practically beneficial. A significant difficulty for the pragmatist position is the existence of beliefs that are the product of self-deception; these seem at once unlikely to be true, yet practically beneficial. This is an issue that requires of the pragmatist a considerable response.26. Descartes would certainly approve of Steup’s referring to this sort of position as a sort of chauvinism. ‘Let’s refer to [this] view as Chauvinism: Whereas responsiveness to practical reasons grounds freedom, responsiveness to epistemic reasons does not’ (Citation2008, 388). Locke, interestingly, holds basically the opposite position. He takes the mind’s natural proclivity toward believing what is likely to be true to exclude the voluntariness, freedom and the will’s direct involvement in general from the process of belief formation (Boespflug Citation2021).27. Newman (Citation2015, 69, 72), for instance, maintains that if one holds that clarity and distinctness determine assent, that assent cannot be voluntary.28. Della Rocca (Citation2006) and Curley (Citation1975) think similarly. There is, in addition, a substantial debate regarding whether Descartes was a compatibilist or libertarian regarding free will. Thomas Lennon (Citation2013, Citation2014) has been one of the most outspoken supporters of the compatibilist take on Descartes, though there are other supporters (e.g., Chappell Citation1994). C.P. Ragland (Citation2006, Citation2016), on the other hand, is a leading defender of interpreting Descartes as a libertarian. Other supporters of this view are Schmaltz (Citation2008) and Wee (Citation2014).29. Or any other plausible version of compatibilism for that matter.30. Cottingham (Citation2008, 355); Kenny (Citation1973, 109); Newman (Citation2014, Citation2015); Carriero (Citation2009, 60–3).31. Cottingham (Citation2008, 225–6). It should be noted that this criticism may be misplaced, given that Cottingham is ambiguous about what he means by Descartes being a doxastic determinist. In certain places he seems to be referring solely to clear and distinct perceptions while in others to all cases of belief formation. His connecting doxastic determinism to involuntarism—as well as his more general insistence that indirect control is the primary kind of doxastic control we have—suggests, however, that he has something fully general in mind. Newman (Citation2015), for instance, is fairly clear that we should interpret Descartes as holding that our assent is determined in that we must acquire a certain doxastic attitude once we direct our attention in certain ways, even if the directing of our attention is within our voluntary control Locke holds something close to the view being described: ‘It depends not on [Man’s] Will to see that Black, which appears Yellow; nor to persuade himself, that what actually scalds him, feels cold: The Earth will not appear painted with Flowers, nor Fields covered with Verdure, whenever he has a Mind to it: in the cold Winter, he cannot help seeing it white and hoary, if he will look abroad. Just thus is it with our Understanding…. As far as Men’s Senses are conversant about external Objects, the Mind cannot but receive those Ideas, which are presented by them, and be informed of the Existence of Things without…. For what a Man sees, he cannot but see; and what he perceives, he cannot but know that he perceives.’ (Essay IV.xiii.2)32. Curley articulates what seems to be a standard interpretation, namely, that the freedom of indifference has a broad scope: ‘Where the perception of the intellect is not clear and distinct, then the will is always more or less indifferent to what is proposed to it and therefore able to choose either’ (Citation1993, 165–6). So, it would seem that all perceptions that fail to be clear and distinct would have an element of indifference. Ragland adds that this sort of indifference is most fundamentally motivational (and, consequently, such situations may furnish a two-way power): ‘Humans who act from indifference are subject to a kind of internal motivational division or conflict rooted in their inability to see clearly’ (unpublished manuscript, 13).33. Principles I.45; AT VIIIa: 22; CSM I: 207–8. Mersenne (Second Objections AT VII: 126–127; CSM II: 90) claims the same thing in his objections, and Descartes (Second Replies AT VII: 149; CSM II: 106) expresses no disagreement.34. While there are reasons to think that the scope of indifference is somewhat narrower than Curley suggests, it is quite difficult to say what exactly it is. For Descartes periodically identifies certain propositions that are not clear and distinct but that, nonetheless, he seems compelled to believe: for example, those things that ‘are quite impossible to doubt’ in the First Meditation, (AT VII: 18; CSM II: 17) and those that produce ‘a great propensity to believe’ in the Sixth (AT VII: 80-81; CSM II: 55–6). The examples Descartes gives are that material objects exist, that he has a body, and that it is as though he is intermingle (quasi permixtum) with that body. Jeremy Hyman offers a different interpretation of this passage, maintaining that Descartes’ reference to the ‘great propensity to believe’ means that such propositions are actually clear and distinct (Citation2019). In any case, whether there is clarity and distinctness on the scene or not, it seems that it would be misleading to maintain that the will is indifferent in such cases. What’s more, surely the freedom I have in believing, for instance, that I am intermingled with my body is at least not quite the lowest grade. My own sense is that we should regard perfect indifference and clarity and distinctness as occupying two ends of a normative, and correspondingly psychological, spectrum: in paradigm cases of clear and distinct perceptions, it is completely obvious which option I ought to choose—and psychological certainty is generated—while in paradigm cases of indifference, the options are on an absolute par—and perhaps suspension of assent is the psychological result. In these latter sorts of situations, we are as it were like Buridan’s ass between two piles of hay. But since clarity and distinctness as well as indifference come in degrees for Descartes, it is difficult to say where the one ends and the other begins. Yet, what does seem clear is that Descartes gives us compelling reason to think that he did not endorse doxastic determinism.35. Ragland offers an insightful discussion of both related problems for Lex Newman’s (Citation2015) indirect voluntarist reading of Descartes as well as some potential solutions.36. Especially Audi (Citation2001).37. Davies, (Citation2001, ch. 5); Vitz (Citation2010); Schuessler (Citation2013). It should be noted that Schuessler’s treatment adds a number of sophisticated nuances to Descartes’ conception of doxastic control. For instance, he maintains that the doxastic control involved in the First Meditation is merely indirect, having been generated by ‘skeptical techniques.’ Schuessler, likewise, isolates other sorts of control operative in other dimensions of Descartes’ philosophy (173). But he ultimately claims that ‘We may thus confidently saddle Descartes with a gatekeeper model of doxastic control’ (157).38. Vitz (Citation2010) offers a similar picture: Descartes held ‘the thesis that people have the ability to suspend, or to withhold, judgment directly by an act of will. Call this negative DDV [direct doxastic voluntarism]’ (108). Vitz also maintains that there is little textual evidence that Descartes held ‘that people have the ability to form a judgment directly by an act of will. Call this positive DDV’ (108). So, the will plays an essentially negative role. While it is able to insert itself into the process of belief formation by putting a halt to acquiring beliefs, it is not correspondingly able to cause beliefs to be formed.39. Though I allow that it is unclear whether Descartes holds that one has the power to suspend judgments regarding clear and distinct perceptions.40. Moreover, with the exception of Schuessler (Citation2013), the above authors could be substantially more sensitive to the indirect means that may be employed in generating the skeptical frame of mind in, for instance, the First Meditation.41. In spite of Vitz’s claim that there is little textual evidence that Descartes held ‘that people have the ability to form a judgment directly by an act of will’ (Citation2010, 115–6), Vitz says little in service of closing off the possibility that this straightforward reading is how Descartes ought to be interpreted.42. Esp. Vitz (Citation2010, section II).43. Vitz (Citation2010, section II).44. This article benefitted from discussions with Robert Pasnau, Matthias Steup, Scott Ragland, and Dan Kaufman. A special thanks also to the editors of this volume—Ruth Boeker and Graham Clay—and to two anonymous reviewers for a number of insightful recommendations.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
为什么每一种信仰都是一种选择:重新审视笛卡尔的武断唯意志论
德拉·罗卡(Citation2006, 153);科廷厄姆(Citation2008, 222)。这一观点的当代表达见于Steup (Citation2000、Citation2008、Citation2012、Citation2017)和Sharon Ryan (Citation2003、Citation2015)。许多作者指出,这完全不符合学术的判断概念,因此应该被视为第四次冥想中最有趣的发展之一(Lennon引文2014,173;然而,正如Nuchelmans (Citation1983, 47-55)所指出的,就斯多葛派哲学而言,这并不是特别新颖,笛卡尔当然很欣赏斯多葛派哲学(Rutherford Citation2014)。对于斯多葛派来说,判断或相信是意志的功能(例如,爱比克泰德(citation2004,1))。虽然这似乎是一种相当有力的方式,但这似乎是笛卡尔的框架所要求的。例如,德拉·罗卡(Della Rocca)显然正是以这种方式解释笛卡尔:“笛卡尔将信仰与普通行为同化:相信我愚蠢的朋友锁上了冰柜和用斧头开锁都是同一意义上的行为:它们是智力和意志、表征状态和非表征状态的适当结合的结果”(Citation2006, 124)。如果说笛卡尔的意思是我们有间接控制,但他只是没有现成的概念来充分阐明这一立场,这并不是一个有希望的策略。主张专制控制的中心是由间接手段组成的,至少早在14世纪,著名的英国多米尼加人罗伯特·霍尔科特就在学术哲学中阐述了这一观点。参见Boespflug (Citation2018)。这是Williams (Citation1970)描述直接控制的方法。阿尔斯通(Citation1988, 260)的表述方式与此类似。关于这一点的进一步讨论见Alston (Citation1988, 269)。这是阿尔斯通的例子(Citation1988, 263)。阿尔斯通(Citation1988, 261)和威廉姆斯(Citation1970)也是如此。Plantinga (citation1993,23)也可能这样解释笛卡尔,尽管它不太清楚。威尔逊的一些言论表明了这一立场。鉴于她采取笛卡尔的立场,她提出异议,“我们不能只是决定相信或同意某事,然后立即相信或同意它”(Citation1978, 145)。尽管威廉姆斯的著名文章《决定去相信》(Deciding to Believe)被普遍认为未能证明随意相信在形而上学上是不可能的,但许多作者认为,威廉姆斯关于信仰具有真理目标的主张确实抓住了信仰本质中一些重要的东西,这与信仰可能是自愿的观点存在矛盾(Citation1970)。Alston (Citation1988)采用了一种与Williams截然不同的方法来论证武断的唯意志论是错误的。阿尔斯顿试图表明,这仅仅是一个偶然的心理事实,人们不能随意相信。Schuessler (Citation2013, 374-5)注意到了这一点。的确,与Williams相比,Alston对不同种类的寄生虫控制更为敏感,并且处理了许多种类的寄生虫控制。然而,他似乎从来没有提到笛卡尔的观点,即经院哲学家的观点,或者约翰·亨利·纽曼(他引用了他的观点)。然而,重要的是要注意,仅仅因为我不能自愿相信美国是英国的殖民地,这并不一定意味着我相信它不是英国的殖民地不在我的专制控制范围内(请原谅三重否定)。毕竟,我无法用笔挖出自己的眼睛,并不意味着我缺乏对不这么做的自主控制。这只是说,专制强迫可能与专制自由或自愿控制完全相容。有些人会说它确实是。例如,参见Steup (Citation2000, Citation2008)。值得注意的是,即使笛卡尔的唯意志论在某种意义上是受限制的,即有些命题我们无法同意,但在某种意义上,它是不受限制的,即我们最终相信的一切都是自愿的。德拉·罗卡(Citation2006, 154);Ragland (Citation2006),未发表手稿;帕特森(Citation2011);科廷厄姆(Citation1986, 83, Citation2008, 348-9);纽曼(citation), 2015, 68).25。此外,正如几位当代实用主义者所指出的那样,相信可能是真的通常对一个人最有实际的好处(Rinard Citation2017;MacGuire and Wood Citation2020)。因此,可能是正确的信念也可能是最实际有益的。实用主义立场的一个重大困难是存在着自我欺骗的产物;这些似乎不太可能是真的,但实际上是有益的。这是一个需要实用主义者作出相当大的反应的问题。 无论如何,无论现场是否清晰明了,认为意志在这种情况下是无关紧要的,似乎是一种误导。更重要的是,我可以自由地相信,例如,我和我的身体是混合在一起的,至少不是最低的等级。我自己的感觉是,我们应该把完全的冷漠、清晰和清晰视为占据规范性和相应的心理光谱的两端:在清晰和不同感知的范式情况下,我应该选择哪个选项是完全明显的——心理确定性由此产生;而在冷漠的范式情况下,选择是绝对的——也许暂停同意是心理上的结果。在后一种情况下,我们就像布里丹的驴夹在两堆干草之间。但是,既然对笛卡尔来说,清晰、清晰和冷漠都是有等级之分的,那么很难说清楚二者的起点和终点在哪里。然而,似乎很清楚的是,笛卡尔给了我们令人信服的理由,让我们认为他不赞同对立决定论。36. Ragland对Lex Newman (Citation2015)的间接唯意志论解读笛卡尔的相关问题以及一些潜在的解决方案进行了深刻的讨论。尤其是奥迪(Citation2001)。Davies, (Citation2001,第5章);Vitz (Citation2010);Schuessler (Citation2013)。应该指出的是,Schuessler的治疗方法为笛卡儿的随机控制概念增加了许多复杂的细微差别。例如,他坚持认为,第一冥想中所涉及的怀疑控制仅仅是间接的,是由“怀疑技术”产生的。同样,Schuessler也在笛卡尔哲学的其他维度中隔离了其他类型的控制(173)。但他最终声称,“我们因此可以自信地给笛卡儿戴上一种专制控制的守门人模型”(157)。维茨(Citation2010)提供了一个类似的图景:笛卡尔认为“人们有能力通过意志行为直接暂停或保留判断”。我们把这称为消极的DDV(直接随机意志论)。维茨还坚持认为,几乎没有文本证据证明笛卡尔认为“人们有能力通过意志行为直接形成判断”。称之为正DDV '(108)。因此,意志在本质上起着消极的作用。虽然它能够通过停止获取信念而将自己插入到信念形成的过程中,但它并不相应地能够导致信念的形成。40.尽管我承认,笛卡尔是否认为人有能力暂停对清晰而独特的感知的判断尚不清楚。此外,除了Schuessler (Citation2013)之外,上述作者可能对间接手段更加敏感,这些间接手段可能用于产生怀疑的心态,例如,第一次冥想。41。尽管维茨声称,几乎没有文本证据表明笛卡尔认为“人们有能力通过意志行为直接形成判断”(Citation2010, 115-6),但维茨几乎没有说什么来关闭这种直接阅读笛卡尔应该如何解释的可能性。43.尤指Vitz (citation, 2010, section II)。44. Vitz (Citation2010, section II)。本文得益于与Robert Pasnau、Matthias Steup、Scott Ragland和Dan Kaufman的讨论。特别感谢本书的编辑ruth Boeker和Graham clay,以及两位匿名评论者,他们提出了许多有见地的建议。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
0.90
自引率
0.00%
发文量
29
期刊介绍: The International Journal of Philosophical Studies (IJPS) publishes academic articles of the highest quality from both analytic and continental traditions and provides a forum for publishing on a broader range of issues than is currently available in philosophical journals. IJPS also publishes annual special issues devoted to key thematic areas or to critical engagements with contemporary philosophers of note. Through its Discussion section, it provides a lively forum for exchange of ideas and encourages dialogue and mutual comprehension across all philosophical traditions. The journal also contains an extensive book review section, including occasional book symposia. It also provides Critical Notices which review major books or themes in depth.
期刊最新文献
Nietzsche and the Size of Future History as a Normative Criterion Becoming Foucault: The Poitiers Years Transgenerational Frontiers: The Capabilities Approach And the New Challenge of Justice Intuitional Content or Avoiding the Myth of the Given – A Dilemma for McDowell The Philosophy and Psychology of Delusions: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1