Return to the Cave: Philia , Eros, and the Erotic-Hermetic Structure of the Philosophical Life

Q4 Social Sciences Perspectives on Political Science Pub Date : 2023-10-18 DOI:10.1080/10457097.2023.2265781
Thomas Holman
{"title":"Return to the Cave: <i>Philia</i> , Eros, and the Erotic-Hermetic Structure of the Philosophical Life","authors":"Thomas Holman","doi":"10.1080/10457097.2023.2265781","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"AbstractIn the scholarly literature on Plato’s Republic, one of the abiding questions has been and remains: why must the philosopher return to the cave? Socrates’s claim that philosophers will do so willingly thanks to their feeling of duty to the polis is rather unsatisfying and doesn’t mesh with the ethical framework presented by the Republic as a whole. Here, I draw on the work of Eric Voegelin and John von Heyking, in order to propose a two-axis model of what I call the erotic-hermetic structure of the philosophical life. By emphasizing the horizontal (i.e. hermetic, or interpersonal) element of the philosophical life, I argue that the philosopher, in order to be what he or she is in the fullest sense, must return to the cave. Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.Notes1 All references to Plato’s Republic are cited using Stephanus numbers. The edition cited throughout is Plato, The Republic of Plato, trans. Francis MacDonald Cornford (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1941).2 For a concise statement of the nature of the problem, see Timothy A. Mahoney, “Do Plato’s Philosopher-Rulers Sacrifice Self-Interest to Justice?,” Phronesis 37, no. 3 (1992): 265–7.3 Julia Annas, An Introduction to Plato’s Republic (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981), 269; Zdravko Planinc, Plato’s Political Philosophy: Prudence in the Republic and the Laws (Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press, 1991), 36.4 Planinc, Plato’s Political Philosophy: Prudence in the Republic and the Laws, 36. It should also be noted that others have attempted to solve the problem by arguing that Plato's “real” definition of justice is found in Book I, where Socrates asserts that justice really means not harming others (335e). See Roslyn Weiss, Philosophers in the Republic: Plato’s Two Paradigms (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2012), 189–90.5 Gabriel Zamosc, “The Political Significance of Plato’s Allegory of the Cave,” Ideas y Valores 66, no. 165 (2017): 238.6 Nettleship provides the classic statement on the parallels between the divided line and the allegory of the cave. See Richard Lewis Nettleship, Lectures on the Republic of Plato (London: Macmillan and Co. Ltd., 1901), Ch. X.7 A. S. Ferguson, “Plato's Simile of Light. Part I. The Similes of the Sun and the Line,” The Classical Quarterly 15, no. 3/4 (1921); A. S. Ferguson, “Plato's Simile of Light. Part II. The Allegory of the Cave,” The Classical Quarterly 16, no. 1 (1922); C. Strang, “Plato’s Analogy of the Cave,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 4 (1986); Stanley Rosen, Nihilism: A Philosophical Essay (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1969), 191-3; Hans-Georg Gadamer, The Idea of the Good in Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1986), 66ff; Eric Voegelin, Order and History, Volume 3: Plato and Aristotle, ed. Dante Germino, The Collected Works of Eric Voegelin, Vol. 16, (Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press, 2000), 166-71.8 For a helpful discussion of the development of the thinking of this second camp, see: Zamosc, “The Political Significance of Plato’s Allegory of the Cave,” 237; Planinc, Plato’s Political Philosophy: Prudence in the Republic and the Laws, Ch. 1.9 Planinc, Plato’s Political Philosophy: Prudence in the Republic and the Laws, 46.10 Ferguson, “Plato's Simile of Light. Part I. The Similes of the Sun and the Line,” 133.11 Ferguson, 134.12 Voegelin, Plato and Aristotle, 166.13 Voegelin, 166.14 Voegelin, 167–8; Plato, The Republic of Plato, trans. Francis MacDonald Cornford (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1941), 227 (518e).15 Voegelin, 169.16 Voegelin, 170-1.17 Plato, Five Dialogues, trans. G.M.A. Grube (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 2002), 118 (80d).18 For a full description of this structure, which can be applied in a range of philosophical contexts, see Eric Voegelin, “Reason: The Classic Experience,” in The Eric Voegelin Reader: Politics, History, Consciousness, ed. Charles R. Embry and Glenn Hughes (Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press, 2017).19 Eric Voegelin, Order and History, Volume 4: The Ecumenic Age, ed. Michael Franz, The Collected Works of Eric Voegelin, Vol. 17, (Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press, 2000), 56.20 Voegelin, Plato and Aristotle, 167.21 Plato, The Symposium, trans. M. C. Howatson, ed. M. C. Howatson and Frisbee C. C. Sheffield (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), 38–9 (202d–e).22 Plato, 37–8 (202a–b).23 Plato, 39 (203a).24 Voegelin, “Reason: The Classic Experience,” 232–3.25 Eric Voegelin, Anamnesis: On the Theory of History and Politics, trans. Gerhart Niemeyer, ed. David Walsh, The Collected Works of Eric Voegelin, Vol. 6, (Columbia, MO: University of Columbia Press, 2002), 352.26 Voegelin, 324–5.27 Voegelin, 325.28 Plato, Five Dialogues, 117–8 (79a–c).29 Plato, 118 (80b).30 Voegelin highlights that the dialogue begins with the words “war and battle,” a foreshadowing of the failure of Socrates's efforts to establish some sort of meaningful communication with his interlocutors. Voegelin, Plato and Aristotle, 83.31 Plato, Gorgias, trans. Chris Emlyn-Jones (New York: Penguin, 2004), 65 (481d).32 Plato, 65 (481d).33 Voegelin, Plato and Aristotle, 83.34 “Discussion between you and me is an absurd affair; all the time we have been talking we have never ceased to revolve in an endless circle of mutual misunderstanding” Plato, Gorgias, 123 (517c).35 As Voegelin points out, the possibility that one's love will be misdirected away from the good and toward evil becomes a key them in the later books of the Republic. Voegelin, Plato and Aristotle, 83.36 Voegelin, Plato and Aristotle, 90.37 Voegelin, 90.38 Eric Voegelin, “Science, Politics and Gnosticism,” in Modernity Without Restraint: The Political Religions, The New Science of Politics, and Science, Politics, and Gnosticism, ed. Thomas A. Hollweck, The Collected Works of Eric Voegelin, Vol. 5 (Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press, 2000), 259.39 This chapter is deeply indebted to the analysis found in John John von Heyking, The Form of Politics: Aristotle and Plato on Friendship (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2016), Ch. 4. It should be noted that there has been much debate over the status of Plato's aims and conclusions in this dialogue subtle and problematic dialogue. These debates turn on the various senses in which φίλοζ (philos) might have been understood in Attic Greek. Interestingly, Robinson sees the dialogue as an expression of the real problem Plato faced when confronting the dissonance between the self-sufficient philosopher who has knowledge of the good and one's need for friends. Of course, this is apposite to the present question on the philosopher's return to the cave. See David B. Robinson, “Plato’s ‘Lysis’: The Structural Problem,” Illinois Classical Studies 11, no. 1 (1986): 72; David K. Glidden, “The Lysis on Loving One’s Own,” The Classical Quarterly 31, no. 1 (1981): 58; A.W. Price, Love and Friendship in Plato and Aristotle (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), Ch. 1.40 Robinson, “Plato’s ‘Lysis’: The Structural Problem,” 72.41 Plato, Plato’s Lysis, trans. Terry Penner and Christopher Rowe (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 4–9 (204c–06c).42 Plato, Plato’s Lysis, 4 (204b).43 Paul Friedländer, Plato: An Introduction (Princeton, NJ: Princeton Legacy Library, 1969), 50.44 Friedländer, 51.45 Francisco J. Gonzalez, “How to read a Platonic prologue: Lysis 203a–207d,” in Plato as Author: The Rhetoric of Philosophy, ed. Ann N. Michelini (Leiden, Netherlands: Brill, 2003), 25.46 Christopher Planeaux, “Socrates, an Unreliable Narrator? The Dramatic Setting of the ‘Lysis’,” Classical Philology 96, no. 1 (2001): 7. Quoted in John von Heyking, The Form of Politics: Aristotle and Plato on Friendship, 106.47 Plato, Plato’s Lysis, 330 (207c); 350 (223a).48 John von Heyking, The Form of Politics: Aristotle and Plato on Friendship, 106.49 Here I am generally drawing on von Heyking’s discussion of the Hymn in von Heyking, The Form of Politics: Aristotle and Plato on Friendship, 116–8.50 Hesiod, The Homeric Hymns, ed. G. P. Goold, trans. Hugh G. Evelyn-White, The Loeb Classical Library, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1914), 393.51 Hesiod, 395.52 Hesiod, The Homeric Hymns, 395.53 John von Heyking, The Form of Politics: Aristotle and Plato on Friendship, 116.54 Jenny Strauss Clay, The Politics of Olympus: Form and Meaning in the Homeric Hymns (London: Bristol Classical Press, 2006), 102.55 F. G. Welcker, Griechische Götterlehre (Göttingen, 1857), I:343. As quoted in Clay, The Politics of Olympus: Form and Meaning in the Homeric Hymns, 102.56 Clay, The Politics of Olympus: Form and Meaning in the Homeric Hymns, 102.57 Plato, Gorgias, 507a.58 Plato, Gorgias, 505e–06b.59 I submit that the very fact that Socrates engages in philosophical discussion to the very last moment of his life is significant in this regard. Plato, Five Dialogues, 104 (67c).60 Eric Voegelin, Order and History, Volume 2: The World of the Polis, ed. Athanasios Moulakis, The Collected Works of Eric Voegelin, Vol. 15, (Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press, 2000), 311. See also Leo Strauss, “What is Poltical Philosophy?,” The Journal of Politics 19, no. 3 (1957): 343.","PeriodicalId":55874,"journal":{"name":"Perspectives on Political Science","volume":"7 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2023-10-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Perspectives on Political Science","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/10457097.2023.2265781","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q4","JCRName":"Social Sciences","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

AbstractIn the scholarly literature on Plato’s Republic, one of the abiding questions has been and remains: why must the philosopher return to the cave? Socrates’s claim that philosophers will do so willingly thanks to their feeling of duty to the polis is rather unsatisfying and doesn’t mesh with the ethical framework presented by the Republic as a whole. Here, I draw on the work of Eric Voegelin and John von Heyking, in order to propose a two-axis model of what I call the erotic-hermetic structure of the philosophical life. By emphasizing the horizontal (i.e. hermetic, or interpersonal) element of the philosophical life, I argue that the philosopher, in order to be what he or she is in the fullest sense, must return to the cave. Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.Notes1 All references to Plato’s Republic are cited using Stephanus numbers. The edition cited throughout is Plato, The Republic of Plato, trans. Francis MacDonald Cornford (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1941).2 For a concise statement of the nature of the problem, see Timothy A. Mahoney, “Do Plato’s Philosopher-Rulers Sacrifice Self-Interest to Justice?,” Phronesis 37, no. 3 (1992): 265–7.3 Julia Annas, An Introduction to Plato’s Republic (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981), 269; Zdravko Planinc, Plato’s Political Philosophy: Prudence in the Republic and the Laws (Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press, 1991), 36.4 Planinc, Plato’s Political Philosophy: Prudence in the Republic and the Laws, 36. It should also be noted that others have attempted to solve the problem by arguing that Plato's “real” definition of justice is found in Book I, where Socrates asserts that justice really means not harming others (335e). See Roslyn Weiss, Philosophers in the Republic: Plato’s Two Paradigms (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2012), 189–90.5 Gabriel Zamosc, “The Political Significance of Plato’s Allegory of the Cave,” Ideas y Valores 66, no. 165 (2017): 238.6 Nettleship provides the classic statement on the parallels between the divided line and the allegory of the cave. See Richard Lewis Nettleship, Lectures on the Republic of Plato (London: Macmillan and Co. Ltd., 1901), Ch. X.7 A. S. Ferguson, “Plato's Simile of Light. Part I. The Similes of the Sun and the Line,” The Classical Quarterly 15, no. 3/4 (1921); A. S. Ferguson, “Plato's Simile of Light. Part II. The Allegory of the Cave,” The Classical Quarterly 16, no. 1 (1922); C. Strang, “Plato’s Analogy of the Cave,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 4 (1986); Stanley Rosen, Nihilism: A Philosophical Essay (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1969), 191-3; Hans-Georg Gadamer, The Idea of the Good in Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1986), 66ff; Eric Voegelin, Order and History, Volume 3: Plato and Aristotle, ed. Dante Germino, The Collected Works of Eric Voegelin, Vol. 16, (Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press, 2000), 166-71.8 For a helpful discussion of the development of the thinking of this second camp, see: Zamosc, “The Political Significance of Plato’s Allegory of the Cave,” 237; Planinc, Plato’s Political Philosophy: Prudence in the Republic and the Laws, Ch. 1.9 Planinc, Plato’s Political Philosophy: Prudence in the Republic and the Laws, 46.10 Ferguson, “Plato's Simile of Light. Part I. The Similes of the Sun and the Line,” 133.11 Ferguson, 134.12 Voegelin, Plato and Aristotle, 166.13 Voegelin, 166.14 Voegelin, 167–8; Plato, The Republic of Plato, trans. Francis MacDonald Cornford (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1941), 227 (518e).15 Voegelin, 169.16 Voegelin, 170-1.17 Plato, Five Dialogues, trans. G.M.A. Grube (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 2002), 118 (80d).18 For a full description of this structure, which can be applied in a range of philosophical contexts, see Eric Voegelin, “Reason: The Classic Experience,” in The Eric Voegelin Reader: Politics, History, Consciousness, ed. Charles R. Embry and Glenn Hughes (Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press, 2017).19 Eric Voegelin, Order and History, Volume 4: The Ecumenic Age, ed. Michael Franz, The Collected Works of Eric Voegelin, Vol. 17, (Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press, 2000), 56.20 Voegelin, Plato and Aristotle, 167.21 Plato, The Symposium, trans. M. C. Howatson, ed. M. C. Howatson and Frisbee C. C. Sheffield (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), 38–9 (202d–e).22 Plato, 37–8 (202a–b).23 Plato, 39 (203a).24 Voegelin, “Reason: The Classic Experience,” 232–3.25 Eric Voegelin, Anamnesis: On the Theory of History and Politics, trans. Gerhart Niemeyer, ed. David Walsh, The Collected Works of Eric Voegelin, Vol. 6, (Columbia, MO: University of Columbia Press, 2002), 352.26 Voegelin, 324–5.27 Voegelin, 325.28 Plato, Five Dialogues, 117–8 (79a–c).29 Plato, 118 (80b).30 Voegelin highlights that the dialogue begins with the words “war and battle,” a foreshadowing of the failure of Socrates's efforts to establish some sort of meaningful communication with his interlocutors. Voegelin, Plato and Aristotle, 83.31 Plato, Gorgias, trans. Chris Emlyn-Jones (New York: Penguin, 2004), 65 (481d).32 Plato, 65 (481d).33 Voegelin, Plato and Aristotle, 83.34 “Discussion between you and me is an absurd affair; all the time we have been talking we have never ceased to revolve in an endless circle of mutual misunderstanding” Plato, Gorgias, 123 (517c).35 As Voegelin points out, the possibility that one's love will be misdirected away from the good and toward evil becomes a key them in the later books of the Republic. Voegelin, Plato and Aristotle, 83.36 Voegelin, Plato and Aristotle, 90.37 Voegelin, 90.38 Eric Voegelin, “Science, Politics and Gnosticism,” in Modernity Without Restraint: The Political Religions, The New Science of Politics, and Science, Politics, and Gnosticism, ed. Thomas A. Hollweck, The Collected Works of Eric Voegelin, Vol. 5 (Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press, 2000), 259.39 This chapter is deeply indebted to the analysis found in John John von Heyking, The Form of Politics: Aristotle and Plato on Friendship (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2016), Ch. 4. It should be noted that there has been much debate over the status of Plato's aims and conclusions in this dialogue subtle and problematic dialogue. These debates turn on the various senses in which φίλοζ (philos) might have been understood in Attic Greek. Interestingly, Robinson sees the dialogue as an expression of the real problem Plato faced when confronting the dissonance between the self-sufficient philosopher who has knowledge of the good and one's need for friends. Of course, this is apposite to the present question on the philosopher's return to the cave. See David B. Robinson, “Plato’s ‘Lysis’: The Structural Problem,” Illinois Classical Studies 11, no. 1 (1986): 72; David K. Glidden, “The Lysis on Loving One’s Own,” The Classical Quarterly 31, no. 1 (1981): 58; A.W. Price, Love and Friendship in Plato and Aristotle (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), Ch. 1.40 Robinson, “Plato’s ‘Lysis’: The Structural Problem,” 72.41 Plato, Plato’s Lysis, trans. Terry Penner and Christopher Rowe (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 4–9 (204c–06c).42 Plato, Plato’s Lysis, 4 (204b).43 Paul Friedländer, Plato: An Introduction (Princeton, NJ: Princeton Legacy Library, 1969), 50.44 Friedländer, 51.45 Francisco J. Gonzalez, “How to read a Platonic prologue: Lysis 203a–207d,” in Plato as Author: The Rhetoric of Philosophy, ed. Ann N. Michelini (Leiden, Netherlands: Brill, 2003), 25.46 Christopher Planeaux, “Socrates, an Unreliable Narrator? The Dramatic Setting of the ‘Lysis’,” Classical Philology 96, no. 1 (2001): 7. Quoted in John von Heyking, The Form of Politics: Aristotle and Plato on Friendship, 106.47 Plato, Plato’s Lysis, 330 (207c); 350 (223a).48 John von Heyking, The Form of Politics: Aristotle and Plato on Friendship, 106.49 Here I am generally drawing on von Heyking’s discussion of the Hymn in von Heyking, The Form of Politics: Aristotle and Plato on Friendship, 116–8.50 Hesiod, The Homeric Hymns, ed. G. P. Goold, trans. Hugh G. Evelyn-White, The Loeb Classical Library, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1914), 393.51 Hesiod, 395.52 Hesiod, The Homeric Hymns, 395.53 John von Heyking, The Form of Politics: Aristotle and Plato on Friendship, 116.54 Jenny Strauss Clay, The Politics of Olympus: Form and Meaning in the Homeric Hymns (London: Bristol Classical Press, 2006), 102.55 F. G. Welcker, Griechische Götterlehre (Göttingen, 1857), I:343. As quoted in Clay, The Politics of Olympus: Form and Meaning in the Homeric Hymns, 102.56 Clay, The Politics of Olympus: Form and Meaning in the Homeric Hymns, 102.57 Plato, Gorgias, 507a.58 Plato, Gorgias, 505e–06b.59 I submit that the very fact that Socrates engages in philosophical discussion to the very last moment of his life is significant in this regard. Plato, Five Dialogues, 104 (67c).60 Eric Voegelin, Order and History, Volume 2: The World of the Polis, ed. Athanasios Moulakis, The Collected Works of Eric Voegelin, Vol. 15, (Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press, 2000), 311. See also Leo Strauss, “What is Poltical Philosophy?,” The Journal of Politics 19, no. 3 (1957): 343.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
《回到洞穴:菲利亚、厄洛斯和哲学生活的情色封闭结构》
沃格林强调,对话以“战争和战斗”开始,这预示着苏格拉底试图与对话者建立某种有意义的沟通的努力失败了。沃格林,柏拉图与亚里士多德,83.31柏拉图,高尔吉亚,译。克里斯·埃姆林-琼斯(纽约:企鹅出版社,2004),65 (481d).32柏拉图,65 (481d)Voegelin,柏拉图和亚里士多德,83.34 "你我之间的讨论是荒谬的;在我们交谈的所有时间里,我们从来没有停止过在相互误解的无休止的循环中旋转。”柏拉图,戈尔吉亚,123 (517c)正如沃格林所指出的,一个人的爱会被误导,远离善而走向恶的可能性,成为《理想国》后几本书的关键。沃格林,柏拉图和亚里士多德,83.36沃格林,柏拉图和亚里士多德,90.37沃格林,90.38埃里克沃格林,“科学,政治和诺斯替主义”,《无约束的现代性:政治宗教,政治新科学,科学,政治和诺斯替主义》,托马斯A.霍尔韦克主编,埃里克沃格林文集,卷5(哥伦比亚,密苏里州:密苏里大学出版社,2000),259.39本章非常感谢约翰·约翰·冯·海金,《政治的形式》中的分析。《亚里士多德与柏拉图论友谊》(蒙特利尔:麦吉尔-皇后大学出版社,2016),第4章。值得注意的是,关于柏拉图的目的和结论在这段微妙而有问题的对话中的地位,有很多争论。这些争论转向了在阿提卡希腊语中φ末梢λο (philos)可能被理解的各种意义。有趣的是,罗宾逊认为这段对话表达了柏拉图所面临的真正问题,即自给自足的哲学家与对朋友的需求之间的不和谐。当然,这与现在哲学家回到洞穴的问题是相反的。参见David B. Robinson,“柏拉图的‘裂解’:结构问题”,《伊利诺伊古典研究》第11期。1 (1986): 72;大卫·k·格利登,“爱自己的酵解”,《古典季刊》第31期,第2期。1 (1981): 58;A.W.普赖斯,《柏拉图与亚里士多德的爱情与友谊》(牛津:克拉伦登出版社,1989),第1.40章。罗宾逊,“柏拉图的‘分解’:结构问题”,72.41柏拉图,《柏拉图的分解》,译。特里·彭纳和克里斯托弗·罗(剑桥:剑桥大学出版社,2005),4-9 (204 - 06).4243 .柏拉图,《柏拉图的解》,4 (204b)保罗Friedländer,柏拉图:一个介绍(普林斯顿,新泽西州:普林斯顿遗产图书馆,1969年),50.44 Friedländer, 51.45弗朗西斯科·j·冈萨雷斯,“如何阅读柏拉图的序言:分析203a-207d,”柏拉图作为作者:哲学修辞学,安·米歇里尼编辑(莱顿,荷兰:布瑞尔,2003年),25.46克里斯托弗·普莱诺,“苏格拉底,一个不可靠的叙述者?“酵解”的戏剧性背景”,《古典文字学》96期。1(2001): 7。引自约翰·冯·海金,《政治的形式:亚里士多德和柏拉图谈友谊》,106.47柏拉图,《柏拉图的解》,330 (207c);350(223年)的相关性约翰·冯·海金,《政治的形式:亚里士多德和柏拉图论友谊》,第6章第49节,这里我主要引用了冯·海金在《政治的形式:亚里士多德和柏拉图论友谊》第116-8.50节中对《赞美诗》的讨论。休·g·伊夫林-怀特,勒布古典图书馆,(剑桥,马萨诸塞州:哈佛大学出版社,1914),393.51赫西奥德,395.52赫西奥德,荷马赞美诗,395.53约翰·冯·海金,政治的形式:亚里士多德和柏拉图的友谊,116.54珍妮·施特劳斯克莱,奥林匹斯的政治:荷马赞美诗的形式和意义(伦敦:布里斯托尔古典出版社,2006),102.55 F。王志强,王志强,王志强,等。研究进展Götterlehre (Göttingen, 1857), 31(3):343。克莱,《奥林匹斯山的政治:荷马赞美诗中的形式和意义》,102.56克莱,《奥林匹斯山的政治:荷马赞美诗中的形式和意义》,102.57柏拉图,戈尔吉亚,507a.58柏拉图,戈尔吉亚,505e-06b.59我认为,苏格拉底直到生命的最后一刻都在进行哲学讨论,这一事实在这方面是很重要的。柏拉图,《五对话》,104 (67c).60埃里克·沃格林,《秩序与历史》,第二卷:城邦的世界,Athanasios Moulakis主编,《埃里克·沃格林文集》,第15卷(密苏里州哥伦比亚:密苏里大学出版社,2000年),第311页。参见李奥·施特劳斯的《什么是政治哲学?》,《政治杂志》第19期,no。3(1957): 343。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
Perspectives on Political Science
Perspectives on Political Science Social Sciences-Political Science and International Relations
CiteScore
0.20
自引率
0.00%
发文量
24
期刊介绍: Whether discussing Montaigne"s case for tolerance or Nietzsche"s political critique of modern science, Perspectives on Political Science links contemporary politics and culture to the enduring questions posed by great thinkers from antiquity to the present. Ideas are the lifeblood of the journal, which comprises articles, symposia, and book reviews. Recent articles address the writings of Aristotle, Adam Smith, and Plutarch; the movies No Country for Old Men and 3:10 to Yuma; and the role of humility in modern political thought.
期刊最新文献
Paul & Empire Criticism: Why and How? Paul & Empire Criticism: Why and How? by Najeeb T. Haddad, Cascade Books, Publication Date: 2023 Conversation as Political Education Defending Socrates: Political Philosophy Before the Tribunal of Science Defending Socrates: Political Philosophy Before the Tribunal of Science , by Alex Priou, Macon, Georgia: Mercer University Press, 184 pp., ISBN 978-0-88146-914-1, Publication Date: 2023 The Politics of Suicide: Miasma and Katharmos in Plato’s Political Thought “Worse than Nothing: The Dangerous Fallacy of Originalism,” by Erwin Chemerinsky
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1