Appreciating the need for autonomy, or recognizing the truth of evidentialism?

Kevin McCain
{"title":"Appreciating the need for autonomy, or recognizing the truth of evidentialism?","authors":"Kevin McCain","doi":"10.1080/0020174x.2023.2261491","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTIn this article I raise two challenges for the primary argument of Adam Carter's Autonomous Knowledge. The first is that his argument for thinking that internalist theories of epistemic justification face problems from TrueTemp-style examples is unsound. The second is that the autonomy condition that Carter argues for is not new as it seems to be already implicit in Earl Conee and Richard Feldman's account of well-founded belief. Ultimately, I do not see these challenges as undermining the value of Carter's project. Rather, these challenges help illuminate that what Autonomous Knowledge does is provide a powerful argument for Evidentialism.KEYWORDS: autonomyAdam CarterEarl ConeeEvidentialismRichard FeldmanTrue-Temp Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 More precisely, the principle says: “for any version of a TrueTemp case, T, and any kind of epistemic justification condition, EJ, on knowledge that we might appeal to explain why Mr. TrueTemp fails to know in T, there will be a possible variation on T, T*, in which Mr. TrueTemp continues to fail to know and yet EJ is satisfied.”2 See, in particular, their Citation2004 collection of essays and their Citation2011 replies to critics. See also McCain (Citation2014) for development and defense of this sort of mentalist Evidentialism. Although there are externalist versions of Evidentialism (see Bergmann Citation2018 for helpful discussion), throughout this article I will use the term “Evidentialism” to refer to the internalist variety.3 There are various answers to what sorts of mental states in particular count as evidence. For example, as discussed below, Conee and Feldman (Citation2008) claim that experiences of various kinds are ultimate evidence, and beliefs justified by those experiences are intermediate evidence. McCain and Moretti (Citation2021) agree, though they offer a more precise take on which experiences count as ultimate evidence by insisting that only seemings/appearances are evidence.4 There are different views of what is required for a belief to be held on the basis of a given body of evidence. Some insist that one must have a meta-belief to the effect that the evidence sufficiently supports the belief (see for example, Lehrer Citation1971; Tolliver Citation1982; Foley Citation1987). Others insist that one’s evidence must cause the belief in the appropriate way (see, for example, Moser Citation1989; Pollock and Cruz Citation1999; McCain Citation2012). Still others suggest that one must simply satisfy one or the other of these conditions (see Korcz Citation2000; Mittag Citation2002 for criticism). Fortunately, we don’t have to settle the issue here because TrueTemp* doesn’t satisfy any of these conditions with respect to his belief that q.5 A number of Evidentialists are explicit in claiming that ultimate evidence is experiential, and beliefs are only intermediate evidence. In particular, they insist that the only time a belief is evidence is when that belief is itself justified. See, for example, Conee and Feldman (Citation2008), McCain (Citation2014), and McCain and Moretti (Citation2021).6 I am assuming that the reason that TrueTemp* has for believing that p isn’t undermined by other evidence he has and that he doesn’t have equally good reasons for believing ∼p. In other words, I’m granting in this case that, all things considered, the evidence TrueTemp* possesses actually provides propositional justification for believing that p.7 See McCain (Citation2012) for elaboration and defense of this account of the basing relation. Other causal accounts of the basing relation, such as Moser (Citation1989) and Pollock and Cruz (Citation1999), seem to deliver the same result that TrueTemp*’s belief is reasons-responsive. The sort of dispositional account of basing defended by Evans (Citation2013) appears to have this consequence as well.8 Other Evidentialists deny that the appreciation described by Conee and Feldman is required for evidence to support believing a proposition (see, for example, Smithies Citation2019; McCain and Moretti Citation2021). However, these Evidentialists allow that such appreciation is a necessary component of basing, which is required for doxastic justification. Hence, on these alternative Evidentialist pictures of evidential support bypassing or preempting beliefs would still fail to be well-founded.9 It’s worth noting that if we understand Conee and Feldman’s conditions for well-founded belief as an epistemic justification condition in the sense the term is used in the Iteration Principle, then we have additional reason to doubt that principle. After all, a belief that satisfies Conee and Feldman’s requirements for well-founded belief will also satisfy the conditions of Carter’s HSEEA***. Since satisfying HSEEA*** rules out being in a TrueTemp case, it won’t be possible for a TrueTemp character to satisfy Conee and Feldman’s conditions for well-founded belief and fail to have knowledge.10 Thanks to Jon Matheson and an anonymous reviewer for helpful comments on an earlier draft.","PeriodicalId":47504,"journal":{"name":"Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0000,"publicationDate":"2023-09-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174x.2023.2261491","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

ABSTRACTIn this article I raise two challenges for the primary argument of Adam Carter's Autonomous Knowledge. The first is that his argument for thinking that internalist theories of epistemic justification face problems from TrueTemp-style examples is unsound. The second is that the autonomy condition that Carter argues for is not new as it seems to be already implicit in Earl Conee and Richard Feldman's account of well-founded belief. Ultimately, I do not see these challenges as undermining the value of Carter's project. Rather, these challenges help illuminate that what Autonomous Knowledge does is provide a powerful argument for Evidentialism.KEYWORDS: autonomyAdam CarterEarl ConeeEvidentialismRichard FeldmanTrue-Temp Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 More precisely, the principle says: “for any version of a TrueTemp case, T, and any kind of epistemic justification condition, EJ, on knowledge that we might appeal to explain why Mr. TrueTemp fails to know in T, there will be a possible variation on T, T*, in which Mr. TrueTemp continues to fail to know and yet EJ is satisfied.”2 See, in particular, their Citation2004 collection of essays and their Citation2011 replies to critics. See also McCain (Citation2014) for development and defense of this sort of mentalist Evidentialism. Although there are externalist versions of Evidentialism (see Bergmann Citation2018 for helpful discussion), throughout this article I will use the term “Evidentialism” to refer to the internalist variety.3 There are various answers to what sorts of mental states in particular count as evidence. For example, as discussed below, Conee and Feldman (Citation2008) claim that experiences of various kinds are ultimate evidence, and beliefs justified by those experiences are intermediate evidence. McCain and Moretti (Citation2021) agree, though they offer a more precise take on which experiences count as ultimate evidence by insisting that only seemings/appearances are evidence.4 There are different views of what is required for a belief to be held on the basis of a given body of evidence. Some insist that one must have a meta-belief to the effect that the evidence sufficiently supports the belief (see for example, Lehrer Citation1971; Tolliver Citation1982; Foley Citation1987). Others insist that one’s evidence must cause the belief in the appropriate way (see, for example, Moser Citation1989; Pollock and Cruz Citation1999; McCain Citation2012). Still others suggest that one must simply satisfy one or the other of these conditions (see Korcz Citation2000; Mittag Citation2002 for criticism). Fortunately, we don’t have to settle the issue here because TrueTemp* doesn’t satisfy any of these conditions with respect to his belief that q.5 A number of Evidentialists are explicit in claiming that ultimate evidence is experiential, and beliefs are only intermediate evidence. In particular, they insist that the only time a belief is evidence is when that belief is itself justified. See, for example, Conee and Feldman (Citation2008), McCain (Citation2014), and McCain and Moretti (Citation2021).6 I am assuming that the reason that TrueTemp* has for believing that p isn’t undermined by other evidence he has and that he doesn’t have equally good reasons for believing ∼p. In other words, I’m granting in this case that, all things considered, the evidence TrueTemp* possesses actually provides propositional justification for believing that p.7 See McCain (Citation2012) for elaboration and defense of this account of the basing relation. Other causal accounts of the basing relation, such as Moser (Citation1989) and Pollock and Cruz (Citation1999), seem to deliver the same result that TrueTemp*’s belief is reasons-responsive. The sort of dispositional account of basing defended by Evans (Citation2013) appears to have this consequence as well.8 Other Evidentialists deny that the appreciation described by Conee and Feldman is required for evidence to support believing a proposition (see, for example, Smithies Citation2019; McCain and Moretti Citation2021). However, these Evidentialists allow that such appreciation is a necessary component of basing, which is required for doxastic justification. Hence, on these alternative Evidentialist pictures of evidential support bypassing or preempting beliefs would still fail to be well-founded.9 It’s worth noting that if we understand Conee and Feldman’s conditions for well-founded belief as an epistemic justification condition in the sense the term is used in the Iteration Principle, then we have additional reason to doubt that principle. After all, a belief that satisfies Conee and Feldman’s requirements for well-founded belief will also satisfy the conditions of Carter’s HSEEA***. Since satisfying HSEEA*** rules out being in a TrueTemp case, it won’t be possible for a TrueTemp character to satisfy Conee and Feldman’s conditions for well-founded belief and fail to have knowledge.10 Thanks to Jon Matheson and an anonymous reviewer for helpful comments on an earlier draft.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
欣赏自治的必要性,还是承认证据主义的真理?
摘要本文对亚当·卡特的自主知识理论的主要论点提出了两个挑战。首先,他认为内部主义的认识论辩护理论面临着来自truetemp式例子的问题,这种观点是站不住脚的。其次,卡特所主张的自治条件并不新鲜,因为它似乎已经隐含在厄尔·科尼和理查德·费尔德曼对有充分根据的信仰的描述中。最终,我不认为这些挑战会破坏卡特项目的价值。相反,这些挑战有助于阐明自主知识所做的是为证据主义提供有力的论据。关键词:自主adam CarterEarl coneeevidence - ism richard feldmanture - temp披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。注1更准确地说,这个原则说:“对于任何版本的TrueTemp情况T,以及任何类型的认知证明条件EJ,关于我们可能用来解释为什么TrueTemp先生在T中不知道的知识,会有一个可能的T变化T*,其中TrueTemp先生继续不知道,但EJ被满足。”2请特别参阅他们的Citation2004论文集和Citation2011对评论家的回复。参见麦凯恩(Citation2014)对这种唯心主义证据主义的发展和辩护。尽管证据主义有外部主义版本(参见Bergmann Citation2018以获得有益的讨论),但在本文中,我将使用术语“证据主义”来指代内部主义的变体对于什么样的精神状态可以算作证据,有各种各样的答案。例如,正如下面所讨论的,Conee和Feldman (Citation2008)声称,各种各样的经验是最终证据,而由这些经验证明的信念是中间证据。麦凯恩和莫雷蒂(Citation2021)对此表示同意,尽管他们通过坚持认为只有看似/表象才是证据,对经验算作最终证据的观点提出了更精确的看法对于在一定证据的基础上持有一种信念所需要的条件,人们有不同的看法。一些人坚持认为,一个人必须有一个元信念,大意是有足够的证据支持这个信念(例如,Lehrer Citation1971;Tolliver Citation1982;福利Citation1987)。另一些人坚持认为,一个人的证据必须以适当的方式引起信念(例如,参见Moser Citation1989;Pollock and Cruz citation; 1999;麦凯恩Citation2012)。还有一些人认为,一个人必须简单地满足这些条件中的一个或另一个(见Korcz Citation2000;Mittag Citation2002批评)。幸运的是,我们不必在这里解决这个问题,因为TrueTemp*不满足关于他的信念q.5的任何这些条件许多证据主义者明确地宣称终极证据是经验证据,而信仰只是中间证据。特别是,他们坚持认为,只有当信念本身被证明是正确的时候,信念才会成为证据。例如,参见Conee and Feldman (Citation2008), McCain (Citation2014),以及McCain and Moretti (Citation2021)我假设TrueTemp*相信p的理由没有被他所拥有的其他证据所破坏,而且他没有同样好的理由相信p。换句话说,在这种情况下,我同意,考虑到所有的事情,TrueTemp*拥有的证据实际上为相信p.7提供了命题论证参见麦凯恩(Citation2012)对这种基地关系的阐述和辩护。其他关于基础关系的因果解释,如Moser (Citation1989)和Pollock和Cruz (Citation1999),似乎也得出了同样的结果,即TrueTemp*的信念是理性响应的。埃文斯(Citation2013)捍卫的那种关于基地的性格描述似乎也有这种后果其他证据主义者否认Conee和Feldman所描述的欣赏是支持相信一个命题的证据所必需的(例如,参见Smithies Citation2019;麦凯恩和莫雷蒂引文(2021)。然而,这些证据主义者认为,这种欣赏是基础的必要组成部分,这是谬论辩护所必需的。因此,在这些替代的证据主义图片上,证据支持绕过或先发制人的信念仍然是没有充分根据的值得注意的是,如果我们把Conee和Feldman关于有充分根据的信念的条件理解为在迭代原则中使用的认识论证明条件,那么我们就有更多的理由怀疑该原则。毕竟,满足Conee和Feldman对有充分根据的信念的要求的信念也将满足Carter的HSEEA***的条件。 由于满足HSEEA***排除了在TrueTemp的情况下,TrueTemp的角色不可能满足Conee和Feldman的有充分根据的信念条件而不具备知识感谢Jon Matheson和一位匿名审稿人对早期草稿的有益评论。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
2.60
自引率
23.10%
发文量
144
期刊最新文献
Ordinal type theory What is priority monism? Reply to Kovacs Responses to critics A new concept of replication Precis of Amie L. Thomasson, norms and necessity
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1