:Infectious Liberty: Biopolitics between Romanticism and Liberalism

IF 0.4 2区 文学 0 LANGUAGE & LINGUISTICS MODERN PHILOLOGY Pub Date : 2023-02-01 DOI:10.1086/722228
Colin Jager
{"title":":<i>Infectious Liberty: Biopolitics between Romanticism and Liberalism</i>","authors":"Colin Jager","doi":"10.1086/722228","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Previous articleNext article FreeBook ReviewInfectious Liberty: Biopolitics between Romanticism and Liberalism. Robert Mitchell. New York: Fordham University Press, 2021. Pp. x+322.Colin JagerColin JagerRutgers University Search for more articles by this author PDFPDF PLUSFull Text Add to favoritesDownload CitationTrack CitationsPermissionsReprints Share onFacebookTwitterLinked InRedditEmailQR Code SectionsMoreLeft-identified intellectuals have enjoyed beating up on liberalism for some time. Liberalism’s omnipresence, not to mention its association with individual liberty, private property, and (especially) a market economy, have made it an irresistible counter in the academic parlor game of demonstrating that those who seem to be our friends are in fact our enemies. In his excellent book, Robert Mitchell writes that, having absorbed the critique of liberalism in graduate school, its primary theorists seemed to him “cramped, provincial, and reactionary” compared to the excitements of continental theory (vii). I imagine this bit of intellectual autobiography will resonate with Mitchell’s readers; it certainly did with me. I too learned in graduate school that novels inculcated liberal norms (individualism, agency, freedom) and that liberalism was pernicious—or, as Mitchell puts it in more measured terms, that literature was “a technology of normativity” (2). Was I supposed to hate novels, then?Infectious Liberty guides its readers beyond this intellectual cul-de-sac. Mitchell writes that when he read Michel Foucault’s lectures on biopolitics, and Roberto Esposito’s development of Foucault’s ideas, he came to see the liberal tradition as concerned with groupings, averages, and collective experiments, not simply with individual agency and private property. Liberalism, in short, was a mode of biopolitics: it was a way of seeing the world in terms of populations, regularities, collective bodies, and the overall processes of life and death (illness, production, birth, etc.). Like Foucault and Esposito, Mitchell is not interested in condemning biopolitics or getting rid of it, “whatever that might mean” (x). Rather, he follows Esposito by parsing it: on the one hand, into the death-dealing “thanatopolitics” that emerge in the work of Agamben and others, focused on security and survival; on the other, into an “affirmative biopolitics” focused on openness and transformation. One name for that affirmative biopolitics, Mitchell argues, is Romanticism.Infectious Liberty is divided into six chapters. The first three are organized by way of concepts familiar to literary scholars: genius, difference, character, and free indirect discourse. Chapters 4 through 6 take up more general concepts in critical sociology: flow, experiment, and self-regulation. All the chapters are characterized by an admirably dialectical impulse toward complication and nuance. Mitchell seems interested in clarity rather than academic point scoring, and so I fear my summary below will scarcely do justice to his arguments. This is particularly ironic because Mitchell himself is a marvelous summarizer of complicated material; I particularly admired the economy and clarity of his accounts of John Guillory (41–42), Franco Moretti (68–73), Ulrich Beck (173–78), and Bruno Latour (220–26), which are almost worth the price of admission on their own.The first chapter considers the relationship between genius and population. Some eighteenth-century commentators thought that the matter was arithmetical: a larger population would increase the number of geniuses. Others thought that genius might be related to particular social environments. A more complex possibility was that there were plenty of geniuses around, but that they were in danger of being overlooked or forgotten. Those latter possibilities, of course, are associated with literary texts: Gray’s Elegy, in the first instance, and Wordsworth’s 1800 Preface to the Lyrical Ballads, in the second. In a move that will be characteristic of the book as a whole, Mitchell argues that these literary texts deepen a reader’s ability to grasp the “complex internal dynamics” of populations (47). In this way Romantic literature makes the question of genius a biopolitical one, not in the blunt sense of increase and decrease (a paradigm associated with thanatopolitics) but rather by “approach[ing] populations as entities that have capacities for creating new norms” (49).The idea that literary writing complicates a given discourse in the direction of transformation rather than security carries over into chapter 2, on “imagining the population” (50). Here Mitchel revisits the Godwin-Malthus controversy, observing that despite their real disagreements both men regarded differences within populations as largely irrelevant; they thought in terms of the mass, not the individual. Mitchell contrasts this with Frankenstein, a novel that endeavors to train its readers to see and imagine multiple kinds of populations—including a population of creatures in South America, a possibility famously destroyed by the Malthusian Victor.In chapter 3, Mitchell expands the claim that “population” names not only a homogenized group but a collection of mappable differences. The novelistic development of character systems and of free indirect discourse makes this clear: “characters” include not just humans but nonhuman agents, and free indirect discourse registers not only thoughts in human minds but “nondiscursive forces that bear upon collective biological existence” (79), like the structural logic of assumptions that underlie particular experiences. Free indirect discourse, in other words, is the place where consciousness intersects population dynamics; in Zola’s The Human Beast, for example, a character’s “pathological relationship to women” is linked to “the vast transportation network and administrative bureaucracy created by the train system” (101). Appealing to systems theory and Latour rather than to models of ideology or disciplinarity, Mitchell argues that free indirect discourse maps intersections between “biological forces and social relations at which pressure can be exerted” in a more liberatory direction (101).Chapter 4 investigates how Romantic-era writers thought “globally” (113)—how, that is, they came to understand phenomena like weather or population as intrinsically global. Mitchell turns to texts by Erasmus Darwin and P. B. Shelley that reflect on human transformations of their global environment by means of terraforming and improving the weather. What Shelley and Darwin grasped, he proposes, is the concept of flow: since we are on a globe, any movement in a particular direction will ultimately come back around to its point of origin. This is true for physics, meteorology, and political economy. Mitchell argues that this Romantic tradition has much to offer our age of climate change, for while most theories of the Anthropocene are focused on security and mere survival, the Romantic emphasis on flow is oriented toward joyful repair.Wordsworth and Coleridge famously described the Lyrical Ballads as an experiment, and Burke called the French Revolution a “dangerous experiment.” In chapter 5, Mitchell argues that not only was the Romantic era one of collective experimentation, but the notion of collective experiment was more important to the development of liberalism than individual liberty. The chapter thus proposes a counterhistory of liberal biopolitics itself as a series of variations on the notion of collective experiment, from early eighteenth-century smallpox inoculation through the institutional foci of Burke and Mill to two latter-day developments: the neoliberalism of Hayek and the neo-Romantic “risk society” of Ulrich Beck. Echoing the transformative aspects of Romantic experimentation, Beck makes it possible to articulate normative projects that depart from the mechanisms of security and survival that dominate neoliberal theory. The “liberal schema of survival is contested,” Mitchell writes, “whenever a community refuses to accept expert risk thresholds” (182); for Beck, at stake in such refusals is an implicit normative claim of the form this is how we want to live. As Mitchell is all too aware, it becomes impossible not to think of contemporary vaccine hesitancy and climate change discourse as exemplifying such neo-Romantic collective experiments—for better and for worse.Does regulation come from a sovereign who establishes a rule, or from a more mysterious quality of self-regulation? The first may be exemplified in the institutions of standard weights and measures, the second by monetary policy, where the “natural” rate of interest is determined by a series of inspired guesses by actors who possess neither sovereign authority nor all the facts. The oscillation between sovereign regulation and self-regulation is the subject of Mitchell’s sixth and final chapter. Admirably in my view, Mitchell wants to wean humanities scholars from the tendency to read “self-regulation” entirely through the lenses of governmentality, as if it is necessarily a normalizing project. Inspired again by Esposito’s affirmative biopolitics, Mitchell traces the possibilities of transformation in Kant’s “regulative ideal” of reason and Hannah Arendt’s Kant-inspired “common world.” In this tradition, thinking is inherently social, done in the presence of others and undertaken always from a particular position. Such self-regulation may of course lead to the neoliberal assertion of the market as the “natural” model of all relations; but it may also lead, Mitchell argues, to those practices of collective resource management that we know as the Commons.Methodologically, two points stand out in this consistently enlightening study. The first is how little of its argument hangs on readings of literary texts. To be sure, imaginative works by Thomas Gray, Erasmus Darwin, Mary Shelley, and Percy Shelley do appear, alongside prominent works of Romantic-era prose by Burke and especially Malthus. Still, the only chapter that really gestures toward an interpretive reading is chapter 2, where Frankenstein is posed against Godwin and Malthus as a representative of literary “difference.” Even here, the claim for literature is a comparatively weak one: that Frankenstein “enabled readers to think through the implications of multiple models of population” (68). The second point, very much related to the first, is Mitchell’s studious distance from symptomatic reading. Aside from a couple of measured paragraphs critiquing the “general literary-critical tendency to understand biopolitics as something that should be opposed at all costs” (12), this is not a polemical book. Mitchell simply remarks from time to time that he has little interest in viewing liberalism, biopolitics, Romanticism, or indeed literature itself, as engaged in projects that need to be either exposed or celebrated. Here he follows the lead of the late Foucault, Roberto Esposito, and Bruno Latour. Of course, Romanticism and liberalism are entwined in all sorts of complicated ways; but Mitchell’s goal “is not, fundamentally, to critique Romanticism as a mode of liberal ideology, but rather to understand Romanticism as an attempt to steer the biopolitical critique of liberalism toward more liberatory shores” (9). These two methodological points are related, I think, because by definition symptomatic reading presupposes the importance of its target—why else expend so much interpretive energy on it? By sticking to the entirely correct observation that there are good and bad kinds of biopolitics, just as there are more and less desirable forms of liberalism, Mitchell also lowers the moral and ideological weight assigned to any given text or its interpretation. Rather than proffer ideal solutions to material problems, he says, literary texts propose “a multitude of different models and norms” for grasping the social whole of which they are a part (5). One inevitable result is that Romanticism as a literary movement remains mostly offstage. What we see instead is a Romanticism that helps to orient an affirmative biopolitics—that is to say, one with self-transformation rather than self-preservation as its goal. Readers interested in moving beyond the historical-contextual paradigm that has dominated so much literary study will find much to think about—and to celebrate—here. Previous articleNext article DetailsFiguresReferencesCited by Modern Philology Volume 120, Number 3February 2023 Article DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1086/722228 Views: 114Total views on this site HistoryPublished online November 09, 2022 For permission to reuse, please contact [email protected]PDF download Crossref reports no articles citing this article.","PeriodicalId":45201,"journal":{"name":"MODERN PHILOLOGY","volume":"3 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4000,"publicationDate":"2023-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"MODERN PHILOLOGY","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1086/722228","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"LANGUAGE & LINGUISTICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Previous articleNext article FreeBook ReviewInfectious Liberty: Biopolitics between Romanticism and Liberalism. Robert Mitchell. New York: Fordham University Press, 2021. Pp. x+322.Colin JagerColin JagerRutgers University Search for more articles by this author PDFPDF PLUSFull Text Add to favoritesDownload CitationTrack CitationsPermissionsReprints Share onFacebookTwitterLinked InRedditEmailQR Code SectionsMoreLeft-identified intellectuals have enjoyed beating up on liberalism for some time. Liberalism’s omnipresence, not to mention its association with individual liberty, private property, and (especially) a market economy, have made it an irresistible counter in the academic parlor game of demonstrating that those who seem to be our friends are in fact our enemies. In his excellent book, Robert Mitchell writes that, having absorbed the critique of liberalism in graduate school, its primary theorists seemed to him “cramped, provincial, and reactionary” compared to the excitements of continental theory (vii). I imagine this bit of intellectual autobiography will resonate with Mitchell’s readers; it certainly did with me. I too learned in graduate school that novels inculcated liberal norms (individualism, agency, freedom) and that liberalism was pernicious—or, as Mitchell puts it in more measured terms, that literature was “a technology of normativity” (2). Was I supposed to hate novels, then?Infectious Liberty guides its readers beyond this intellectual cul-de-sac. Mitchell writes that when he read Michel Foucault’s lectures on biopolitics, and Roberto Esposito’s development of Foucault’s ideas, he came to see the liberal tradition as concerned with groupings, averages, and collective experiments, not simply with individual agency and private property. Liberalism, in short, was a mode of biopolitics: it was a way of seeing the world in terms of populations, regularities, collective bodies, and the overall processes of life and death (illness, production, birth, etc.). Like Foucault and Esposito, Mitchell is not interested in condemning biopolitics or getting rid of it, “whatever that might mean” (x). Rather, he follows Esposito by parsing it: on the one hand, into the death-dealing “thanatopolitics” that emerge in the work of Agamben and others, focused on security and survival; on the other, into an “affirmative biopolitics” focused on openness and transformation. One name for that affirmative biopolitics, Mitchell argues, is Romanticism.Infectious Liberty is divided into six chapters. The first three are organized by way of concepts familiar to literary scholars: genius, difference, character, and free indirect discourse. Chapters 4 through 6 take up more general concepts in critical sociology: flow, experiment, and self-regulation. All the chapters are characterized by an admirably dialectical impulse toward complication and nuance. Mitchell seems interested in clarity rather than academic point scoring, and so I fear my summary below will scarcely do justice to his arguments. This is particularly ironic because Mitchell himself is a marvelous summarizer of complicated material; I particularly admired the economy and clarity of his accounts of John Guillory (41–42), Franco Moretti (68–73), Ulrich Beck (173–78), and Bruno Latour (220–26), which are almost worth the price of admission on their own.The first chapter considers the relationship between genius and population. Some eighteenth-century commentators thought that the matter was arithmetical: a larger population would increase the number of geniuses. Others thought that genius might be related to particular social environments. A more complex possibility was that there were plenty of geniuses around, but that they were in danger of being overlooked or forgotten. Those latter possibilities, of course, are associated with literary texts: Gray’s Elegy, in the first instance, and Wordsworth’s 1800 Preface to the Lyrical Ballads, in the second. In a move that will be characteristic of the book as a whole, Mitchell argues that these literary texts deepen a reader’s ability to grasp the “complex internal dynamics” of populations (47). In this way Romantic literature makes the question of genius a biopolitical one, not in the blunt sense of increase and decrease (a paradigm associated with thanatopolitics) but rather by “approach[ing] populations as entities that have capacities for creating new norms” (49).The idea that literary writing complicates a given discourse in the direction of transformation rather than security carries over into chapter 2, on “imagining the population” (50). Here Mitchel revisits the Godwin-Malthus controversy, observing that despite their real disagreements both men regarded differences within populations as largely irrelevant; they thought in terms of the mass, not the individual. Mitchell contrasts this with Frankenstein, a novel that endeavors to train its readers to see and imagine multiple kinds of populations—including a population of creatures in South America, a possibility famously destroyed by the Malthusian Victor.In chapter 3, Mitchell expands the claim that “population” names not only a homogenized group but a collection of mappable differences. The novelistic development of character systems and of free indirect discourse makes this clear: “characters” include not just humans but nonhuman agents, and free indirect discourse registers not only thoughts in human minds but “nondiscursive forces that bear upon collective biological existence” (79), like the structural logic of assumptions that underlie particular experiences. Free indirect discourse, in other words, is the place where consciousness intersects population dynamics; in Zola’s The Human Beast, for example, a character’s “pathological relationship to women” is linked to “the vast transportation network and administrative bureaucracy created by the train system” (101). Appealing to systems theory and Latour rather than to models of ideology or disciplinarity, Mitchell argues that free indirect discourse maps intersections between “biological forces and social relations at which pressure can be exerted” in a more liberatory direction (101).Chapter 4 investigates how Romantic-era writers thought “globally” (113)—how, that is, they came to understand phenomena like weather or population as intrinsically global. Mitchell turns to texts by Erasmus Darwin and P. B. Shelley that reflect on human transformations of their global environment by means of terraforming and improving the weather. What Shelley and Darwin grasped, he proposes, is the concept of flow: since we are on a globe, any movement in a particular direction will ultimately come back around to its point of origin. This is true for physics, meteorology, and political economy. Mitchell argues that this Romantic tradition has much to offer our age of climate change, for while most theories of the Anthropocene are focused on security and mere survival, the Romantic emphasis on flow is oriented toward joyful repair.Wordsworth and Coleridge famously described the Lyrical Ballads as an experiment, and Burke called the French Revolution a “dangerous experiment.” In chapter 5, Mitchell argues that not only was the Romantic era one of collective experimentation, but the notion of collective experiment was more important to the development of liberalism than individual liberty. The chapter thus proposes a counterhistory of liberal biopolitics itself as a series of variations on the notion of collective experiment, from early eighteenth-century smallpox inoculation through the institutional foci of Burke and Mill to two latter-day developments: the neoliberalism of Hayek and the neo-Romantic “risk society” of Ulrich Beck. Echoing the transformative aspects of Romantic experimentation, Beck makes it possible to articulate normative projects that depart from the mechanisms of security and survival that dominate neoliberal theory. The “liberal schema of survival is contested,” Mitchell writes, “whenever a community refuses to accept expert risk thresholds” (182); for Beck, at stake in such refusals is an implicit normative claim of the form this is how we want to live. As Mitchell is all too aware, it becomes impossible not to think of contemporary vaccine hesitancy and climate change discourse as exemplifying such neo-Romantic collective experiments—for better and for worse.Does regulation come from a sovereign who establishes a rule, or from a more mysterious quality of self-regulation? The first may be exemplified in the institutions of standard weights and measures, the second by monetary policy, where the “natural” rate of interest is determined by a series of inspired guesses by actors who possess neither sovereign authority nor all the facts. The oscillation between sovereign regulation and self-regulation is the subject of Mitchell’s sixth and final chapter. Admirably in my view, Mitchell wants to wean humanities scholars from the tendency to read “self-regulation” entirely through the lenses of governmentality, as if it is necessarily a normalizing project. Inspired again by Esposito’s affirmative biopolitics, Mitchell traces the possibilities of transformation in Kant’s “regulative ideal” of reason and Hannah Arendt’s Kant-inspired “common world.” In this tradition, thinking is inherently social, done in the presence of others and undertaken always from a particular position. Such self-regulation may of course lead to the neoliberal assertion of the market as the “natural” model of all relations; but it may also lead, Mitchell argues, to those practices of collective resource management that we know as the Commons.Methodologically, two points stand out in this consistently enlightening study. The first is how little of its argument hangs on readings of literary texts. To be sure, imaginative works by Thomas Gray, Erasmus Darwin, Mary Shelley, and Percy Shelley do appear, alongside prominent works of Romantic-era prose by Burke and especially Malthus. Still, the only chapter that really gestures toward an interpretive reading is chapter 2, where Frankenstein is posed against Godwin and Malthus as a representative of literary “difference.” Even here, the claim for literature is a comparatively weak one: that Frankenstein “enabled readers to think through the implications of multiple models of population” (68). The second point, very much related to the first, is Mitchell’s studious distance from symptomatic reading. Aside from a couple of measured paragraphs critiquing the “general literary-critical tendency to understand biopolitics as something that should be opposed at all costs” (12), this is not a polemical book. Mitchell simply remarks from time to time that he has little interest in viewing liberalism, biopolitics, Romanticism, or indeed literature itself, as engaged in projects that need to be either exposed or celebrated. Here he follows the lead of the late Foucault, Roberto Esposito, and Bruno Latour. Of course, Romanticism and liberalism are entwined in all sorts of complicated ways; but Mitchell’s goal “is not, fundamentally, to critique Romanticism as a mode of liberal ideology, but rather to understand Romanticism as an attempt to steer the biopolitical critique of liberalism toward more liberatory shores” (9). These two methodological points are related, I think, because by definition symptomatic reading presupposes the importance of its target—why else expend so much interpretive energy on it? By sticking to the entirely correct observation that there are good and bad kinds of biopolitics, just as there are more and less desirable forms of liberalism, Mitchell also lowers the moral and ideological weight assigned to any given text or its interpretation. Rather than proffer ideal solutions to material problems, he says, literary texts propose “a multitude of different models and norms” for grasping the social whole of which they are a part (5). One inevitable result is that Romanticism as a literary movement remains mostly offstage. What we see instead is a Romanticism that helps to orient an affirmative biopolitics—that is to say, one with self-transformation rather than self-preservation as its goal. Readers interested in moving beyond the historical-contextual paradigm that has dominated so much literary study will find much to think about—and to celebrate—here. Previous articleNext article DetailsFiguresReferencesCited by Modern Philology Volume 120, Number 3February 2023 Article DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1086/722228 Views: 114Total views on this site HistoryPublished online November 09, 2022 For permission to reuse, please contact [email protected]PDF download Crossref reports no articles citing this article.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
感染性自由:浪漫主义与自由主义之间的生命政治
《有效的自由:浪漫主义与自由主义之间的生命政治》。罗伯特·米切尔。纽约:福特汉姆大学出版社,2021。Pp. x + 322。Colin JagerColin JagerRutgers University搜索本文作者的更多文章PDFPDF +全文添加到收藏列表下载CitationTrack citationspermissions转载分享在facebook twitter上链接在redditemailqr Code章节一段时间以来,以自由主义为身份的知识分子一直享受着痛击自由主义的乐趣。自由主义的无所不在,更不用说它与个人自由、私有财产和(特别是)市场经济的联系,使它成为学术室内游戏中不可抗拒的反击,证明那些看似我们的朋友实际上是我们的敌人。罗伯特·米切尔(Robert Mitchell)在他出色的著作中写道,在研究生院吸收了对自由主义的批判后,与大陆理论的兴奋相比,他认为自由主义的主要理论家似乎“狭隘、偏狭、反动”(vii)。我想这一点知识分子的自传将与米切尔的读者产生共鸣;对我来说确实如此。我在研究生院也了解到,小说灌输了自由主义规范(个人主义、能动性、自由),而自由主义是有害的——或者,正如米切尔更慎重地说的那样,文学是“一种规范的技术”(2)。那么,我应该讨厌小说吗?《感染性自由》引导读者走出这个知识分子的死胡同。米切尔写道,当他阅读米歇尔·福柯关于生命政治的讲座,以及罗伯托·埃斯波西托对福柯思想的发展时,他开始看到自由主义传统关注的是群体、平均和集体实验,而不仅仅是个人代理和私有财产。简而言之,自由主义是一种生命政治模式:它是一种从人口、规律、集体和生与死(疾病、生产、出生等)的整体过程来看世界的方式。像福柯和埃斯波西托一样,米切尔对谴责或摆脱生命政治并不感兴趣,“不管这可能意味着什么”(x)。相反,他遵循埃斯波西托的分析方式:一方面,进入阿甘本和其他人的作品中出现的与死亡有关的“死亡政治”,专注于安全和生存;另一方面,转变为注重开放和转型的“平权生命政治”。米切尔认为,这种平权生命政治的一个名字是浪漫主义。《感染性自由》分为六章。前三篇是用文学学者熟悉的概念来组织的:天才、差异、性格和自由间接话语。第4章至第6章讨论了批判社会学中更一般的概念:心流、实验和自我调节。所有章节的特点是令人钦佩的辩证冲动的复杂性和细微差别。米切尔似乎更感兴趣的是清晰度,而不是学术得分,所以我担心我下面的总结很难公正地对待他的论点。这尤其具有讽刺意味,因为米切尔本人就是一个对复杂材料进行出色总结的人;我特别欣赏他对约翰·吉洛里(41-42)、佛朗哥·莫雷蒂(68-73)、乌尔里希·贝克(173-78)和布鲁诺·拉图尔(220-26)的叙述简洁明了,这些书本身就值回票价。第一章探讨天才与人口的关系。一些18世纪的评论家认为这是一个算术问题:人口越多,天才的数量就越多。其他人则认为天才可能与特定的社会环境有关。一种更复杂的可能性是,周围有很多天才,但他们有被忽视或被遗忘的危险。当然,后一种可能性与文学作品有关:第一种是格雷的《挽歌》,第二种是华兹华斯1800年的《抒情歌谣序》。米切尔认为,这些文学文本加深了读者掌握人口“复杂的内部动态”的能力,这将是本书整体的特点。通过这种方式,浪漫主义文学将天才问题变成了一个生命政治问题,不是在生硬的增加和减少的意义上(与死亡政治相关的范式),而是通过“将人口视为具有创造新规范能力的实体”(49)。文学写作使一个给定的话语在转变的方向上变得复杂,而不是在安全的方向上,这种观点延续到了第二章,关于“想象人口”(50)。在这里,米切尔重新审视了戈德温-马尔萨斯的争论,他观察到,尽管他们存在真正的分歧,但他们都认为人口内部的差异在很大程度上是无关紧要的;他们考虑的是整体,而不是个体。 首先,它的论点很少依赖于对文学文本的阅读。可以肯定的是,托马斯·格雷、伊拉斯谟·达尔文、玛丽·雪莱和珀西·雪莱的富有想象力的作品确实出现过,还有伯克,尤其是马尔萨斯的浪漫主义时代散文的杰出作品。然而,唯一真正倾向于解释性阅读的章节是第二章,弗兰肯斯坦被摆在戈德温和马尔萨斯的对立面,作为文学“差异”的代表。即使在这里,对文学的主张也相对薄弱:弗兰肯斯坦“使读者能够思考多种人口模型的含义”(68)。第二点,与第一点密切相关,就是米切尔刻意与症状性阅读保持距离。除了几段有条理的段落批评“将生命政治理解为应该不惜一切代价反对的一般文学批评倾向”(12)之外,这不是一本争论性的书。米切尔只是时不时地说,他对自由主义、生命政治、浪漫主义,甚至文学本身都不感兴趣,因为这些作品要么需要曝光,要么需要庆祝。在这里,他追随了已故的福柯、罗伯托·埃斯波西托和布鲁诺·拉图尔的领导。当然,浪漫主义和自由主义以各种复杂的方式纠缠在一起;但米切尔的目标“从根本上说,不是批判作为自由意识形态模式的浪漫主义,而是将浪漫主义理解为一种试图将自由主义的生命政治批判引向更自由的彼岸”(9)。我认为,这两个方法论观点是相关的,因为根据定义,症状性阅读预设了其目标的重要性——否则为什么要在它上面花费如此多的解释精力呢?通过坚持完全正确的观察,即生命政治有好有坏,就像自由主义有多有少一样,米切尔也降低了赋予任何给定文本或其解释的道德和意识形态权重。他说,文学作品并没有为物质问题提供理想的解决方案,而是提出了“大量不同的模式和规范”来把握它们所处的社会整体(5)。一个不可避免的结果是,浪漫主义作为一种文学运动,大部分时间都处于幕后。相反,我们看到的是一种浪漫主义,它有助于确定一种积极的生命政治——也就是说,一种以自我转变而不是自我保护为目标的生命政治。有兴趣超越主导文学研究的历史-语境范式的读者会在这里发现很多值得思考和庆祝的东西。上一篇文章下一篇文章详细信息图表参考文献被现代语言学引用第120卷,第3期2023年2月文章DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1086/722228浏览次数:114本网站总浏览量历史在线发布2022年11月09日如需重复使用,请联系[email protected]PDF下载Crossref报告没有引用本文的文章。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
MODERN PHILOLOGY
MODERN PHILOLOGY Multiple-
CiteScore
0.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
64
期刊介绍: Founded in 1903, Modern Philology sets the standard for literary scholarship, history, and criticism. In addition to innovative and scholarly articles (in English) on literature in all modern world languages, MP also publishes insightful book reviews of recent books as well as review articles and research on archival documents. Editor Richard Strier is happy to announce that we now welcome contributions on literature in non-European languages and contributions that productively compare texts or traditions from European and non-European literatures. In general, we expect contributions to be written in (or translated into) English, and we expect quotations from non-English languages to be translated into English as well as reproduced in the original.
期刊最新文献
:Black Shakespeare: Reading and Misreading Race :Pain, Penance, and Protest: Peine Forte et Dure in Medieval England :The Politics of Speech in Later Twentieth-Century Poetry: Local Tongues in Heaney, Brooks, Harrison, and Clifton :Melville, Beauty, and American Literary Studies: An Aesthetics in All Things :Heroic Awe: The Sublime and the Remaking of Renaissance Epic
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1