Timescales of Rational Inattention

IF 3.1 1区 心理学 Q2 PSYCHOLOGY, DEVELOPMENTAL Developmental Science Pub Date : 2024-10-08 DOI:10.1111/desc.13571
Nivedita Mani
{"title":"Timescales of Rational Inattention","authors":"Nivedita Mani","doi":"10.1111/desc.13571","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>To reconcile previously reported differences in information-seeking behaviour displayed by neurodivergent children and their neurotypical peers, Jones et al. (<span>2024</span>) present a compelling new theory of rational information-seeking behaviour. The central premise of rational inattention is that optimal information-seeking behaviour may centre around learning to disengage from imprecise sources, that is, sources where information gain is expected to be low and imprecise. Thus, children with dyslexia may, over time, selectively disengage from further processing of text, which past experience has taught them provides minimal information gain. Neurotypical children who have experienced greater information gain from text sources, however, may persevere and attend to such sources proportionately in the future.</p><p>Rational inattention has critical bridges to previous rational accounts of curiosity, where the rational agent aims to maximise information gain by <i>attending</i> to sources that maximally increase the usefulness of their knowledge (e.g., Dubey and Griffiths <span>2020</span>). These links to previous accounts of curiosity are worth considering in greater detail towards a unified account of information-seeking behaviour. In particular, in reconciling these accounts, one question worth pursuing is the relationship between rational attention—as characterised by rational accounts of curiosity—and rational inattention. Is rational attention the flip side of rational inattention or are different factors likely to impact the sources children choose to attend to in the search for information gain and the sources children disengage from over time. My suspicion is that at least a partial answer to this question may lie in paying closer attention (pun unintended) to two timescales of rational inattention, in particular, the real-time and the developmental timescale of rational inattention (cf. McMurray <span>2016</span>).</p><p>Let us first consider the timescale of real-time processing in the proposed model. The model suggests that some reconstruction of the input is produced regardless of the precision of this reconstruction in the initial stages of processing (see Figure 1). Thus, even input that is later evaluated as imprecise is included in the early processing stages. The error between the input and the imprecise reconstruction is downweighted, retrospectively, based on the learner's experience with such stimuli (e.g., see Schütte, Mani, and Behne <span>2020</span>, for evidence of such retrospective selective learning in young children). This is where rational inattention comes in. Indeed, the early reconstruction of all input is the reason why a clamped model—without such retrospective downweighting—shows improved learning from even imprecise input. Here, rational attention and rational inattention may be seen as flip sides of the same coin with the input being retrospectively weighted in essentially the same way to allow attention to sources that ensure information gain and away from sources that are unlikely to minimise uncertainty. Such an interpretation would allow for a unified framework for information seeking, bringing together the benefits of rational accounts of curiosity—in terms of estimating the future usefulness of encountered information—and the neurodivergent perspective offered by rational inattention.</p><p>The scenario with regard to the developmental timescale is, however, less clear. In particular, minimising epistemic uncertainty requires some evaluation of the learner's current state of knowledge or abilities, that is, identifying the sources that are likely to be imprecise for specific learners. Jones et al. (<span>2024</span>) note that formal metacognitive awareness of the imprecision of specific sources for specific learners is not a prerequisite for the model's behaviour. Although this makes sense when considering rational (in)attention in young infants and children lacking such metacognitive awareness, how does rational inattention play out across development? On the one hand, this raises questions regarding the cognitive correlate of global error—the sum of the weighted error signals (MSE) between the input and the reconstruction from different sources—especially in young infants with limited metacognitive abilities. Moreover, how would growing metacognitive awareness in early childhood factor into rational models of information-seeking behaviour? Whilst research has long suggested that young children lack extensive metacognitive awareness of their knowledge gaps (Goupil and Kouider <span>2019</span>), more recent work suggests that even young infants display some form of metacognitive monitoring (Goupil and Kouider <span>2016</span>; Goupil, Romand-Monnier, and Kouider <span>2016</span>). Nevertheless, metacognitive abilities improve considerably across childhood, with the absolute accuracy of young children's metacognitive judgements and the impact of such judgements on information seeking being astonishingly low. For instance, in recent work, we showed that children's metacognitive judgements of their subjective uncertainty predicted information-seeking behaviour only in older but not in younger children (de Eccher, Mundry, and Mani <span>2024</span>). What would be the role of children's increasing metacognitive awareness of their knowledge gaps in the current model? Furthermore, what would be the relationship between such advanced metacognitive awareness and the global error in the model proposed? Would increasing metacognitive awareness of areas of subjective uncertainty require changes to the model structure proposed in Figure 1? For instance, one possible outcome could be that increased metacognitive awareness of difficulties, for example, in processing text, leads to children with dyslexia disengaging with text at the earliest stages of processing highlighted above. In other words, with growing explicit awareness of their difficulties in text processing, children with dyslexia may inhibit even production of a reconstruction of presented textual input. Metacognitive awareness may in this case act like a firewall, inhibiting not just retrospective inattention but even early processing of imprecise sources, whilst more reliable sources filter through to early processing. This could then, potentially, suggest different pathways for rational attention and inattention whilst also speaking to previously reported differences in the proposed causes of some neurodivergent profiles, for example, deficits in early auditory processing or later working memory. This is but one of many solutions to integrating metacognition with information seeking. Clearly, this compelling theory of rational information seeking offers many avenues for bringing together the thinking from diverse fields, in terms of reconciling differences in neurodivergent and neurotypical information seeking but also across development and, potentially, the causes of certain neurodivergent profiles.</p><p>The author declares no conflicts of interest.</p>","PeriodicalId":48392,"journal":{"name":"Developmental Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.1000,"publicationDate":"2024-10-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/desc.13571","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Developmental Science","FirstCategoryId":"102","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/desc.13571","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"心理学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q2","JCRName":"PSYCHOLOGY, DEVELOPMENTAL","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

To reconcile previously reported differences in information-seeking behaviour displayed by neurodivergent children and their neurotypical peers, Jones et al. (2024) present a compelling new theory of rational information-seeking behaviour. The central premise of rational inattention is that optimal information-seeking behaviour may centre around learning to disengage from imprecise sources, that is, sources where information gain is expected to be low and imprecise. Thus, children with dyslexia may, over time, selectively disengage from further processing of text, which past experience has taught them provides minimal information gain. Neurotypical children who have experienced greater information gain from text sources, however, may persevere and attend to such sources proportionately in the future.

Rational inattention has critical bridges to previous rational accounts of curiosity, where the rational agent aims to maximise information gain by attending to sources that maximally increase the usefulness of their knowledge (e.g., Dubey and Griffiths 2020). These links to previous accounts of curiosity are worth considering in greater detail towards a unified account of information-seeking behaviour. In particular, in reconciling these accounts, one question worth pursuing is the relationship between rational attention—as characterised by rational accounts of curiosity—and rational inattention. Is rational attention the flip side of rational inattention or are different factors likely to impact the sources children choose to attend to in the search for information gain and the sources children disengage from over time. My suspicion is that at least a partial answer to this question may lie in paying closer attention (pun unintended) to two timescales of rational inattention, in particular, the real-time and the developmental timescale of rational inattention (cf. McMurray 2016).

Let us first consider the timescale of real-time processing in the proposed model. The model suggests that some reconstruction of the input is produced regardless of the precision of this reconstruction in the initial stages of processing (see Figure 1). Thus, even input that is later evaluated as imprecise is included in the early processing stages. The error between the input and the imprecise reconstruction is downweighted, retrospectively, based on the learner's experience with such stimuli (e.g., see Schütte, Mani, and Behne 2020, for evidence of such retrospective selective learning in young children). This is where rational inattention comes in. Indeed, the early reconstruction of all input is the reason why a clamped model—without such retrospective downweighting—shows improved learning from even imprecise input. Here, rational attention and rational inattention may be seen as flip sides of the same coin with the input being retrospectively weighted in essentially the same way to allow attention to sources that ensure information gain and away from sources that are unlikely to minimise uncertainty. Such an interpretation would allow for a unified framework for information seeking, bringing together the benefits of rational accounts of curiosity—in terms of estimating the future usefulness of encountered information—and the neurodivergent perspective offered by rational inattention.

The scenario with regard to the developmental timescale is, however, less clear. In particular, minimising epistemic uncertainty requires some evaluation of the learner's current state of knowledge or abilities, that is, identifying the sources that are likely to be imprecise for specific learners. Jones et al. (2024) note that formal metacognitive awareness of the imprecision of specific sources for specific learners is not a prerequisite for the model's behaviour. Although this makes sense when considering rational (in)attention in young infants and children lacking such metacognitive awareness, how does rational inattention play out across development? On the one hand, this raises questions regarding the cognitive correlate of global error—the sum of the weighted error signals (MSE) between the input and the reconstruction from different sources—especially in young infants with limited metacognitive abilities. Moreover, how would growing metacognitive awareness in early childhood factor into rational models of information-seeking behaviour? Whilst research has long suggested that young children lack extensive metacognitive awareness of their knowledge gaps (Goupil and Kouider 2019), more recent work suggests that even young infants display some form of metacognitive monitoring (Goupil and Kouider 2016; Goupil, Romand-Monnier, and Kouider 2016). Nevertheless, metacognitive abilities improve considerably across childhood, with the absolute accuracy of young children's metacognitive judgements and the impact of such judgements on information seeking being astonishingly low. For instance, in recent work, we showed that children's metacognitive judgements of their subjective uncertainty predicted information-seeking behaviour only in older but not in younger children (de Eccher, Mundry, and Mani 2024). What would be the role of children's increasing metacognitive awareness of their knowledge gaps in the current model? Furthermore, what would be the relationship between such advanced metacognitive awareness and the global error in the model proposed? Would increasing metacognitive awareness of areas of subjective uncertainty require changes to the model structure proposed in Figure 1? For instance, one possible outcome could be that increased metacognitive awareness of difficulties, for example, in processing text, leads to children with dyslexia disengaging with text at the earliest stages of processing highlighted above. In other words, with growing explicit awareness of their difficulties in text processing, children with dyslexia may inhibit even production of a reconstruction of presented textual input. Metacognitive awareness may in this case act like a firewall, inhibiting not just retrospective inattention but even early processing of imprecise sources, whilst more reliable sources filter through to early processing. This could then, potentially, suggest different pathways for rational attention and inattention whilst also speaking to previously reported differences in the proposed causes of some neurodivergent profiles, for example, deficits in early auditory processing or later working memory. This is but one of many solutions to integrating metacognition with information seeking. Clearly, this compelling theory of rational information seeking offers many avenues for bringing together the thinking from diverse fields, in terms of reconciling differences in neurodivergent and neurotypical information seeking but also across development and, potentially, the causes of certain neurodivergent profiles.

The author declares no conflicts of interest.

查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
理性注意力不集中的时间尺度。
为了协调之前报道的神经发育迟缓儿童与神经正常儿童在信息搜寻行为上的差异,琼斯等人(2024 年)提出了一个令人信服的理性信息搜寻行为新理论。理性注意力不集中的核心前提是,最佳的信息搜寻行为可能以学习脱离不精确信息源为中心,即预期信息收益低且不精确的信息源。因此,随着时间的推移,有阅读障碍的儿童可能会选择性地放弃对文字的进一步处理,因为过去的经验告诉他们,这些文字所提供的信息量极少。理性不专心与以往关于好奇心的理性论述有着重要的联系,在后者中,理性主体的目标是通过关注那些能最大限度地提高其知识有用性的信息源来最大限度地获取信息(例如,Dubey 和 Griffiths,2020 年)。这些与以往关于好奇心的论述之间的联系值得更详细地加以考虑,以便对信息搜寻行为进行统一的论述。特别是,在协调这些论述时,一个值得探讨的问题是理性注意--即好奇心的理性论述所表征的--与理性不注意之间的关系。是理性注意是理性不注意的反面,还是不同的因素可能会影响儿童在寻找信息时选择关注的信息源,以及儿童随着时间的推移而不再关注的信息源。我猜想,这个问题的至少部分答案可能在于更密切地关注(双关语无意)理性不专心的两个时间尺度,特别是理性不专心的实时时间尺度和发展时间尺度(参见 McMurray 2016)。该模型表明,在处理的初始阶段,无论这种重构的精确度如何,都会对输入进行某种重构(见图 1)。因此,即使后来被评估为不精确的输入也会被纳入早期处理阶段。输入与不精确的重构之间的误差会根据学习者对此类刺激的经验进行回溯性减权(例如,参见 Schütte, Mani 和 Behne 2020,以了解幼儿这种回溯性选择学习的证据)。这就是理性注意力不集中的原因。事实上,对所有输入的早期重构正是箝位模型--没有这种回溯性减权--能更好地从不确定性输入中学习的原因。在这里,理性注意和理性不注意可以被看作是一枚硬币的两面,输入的回溯加权方式基本相同,都是为了让注意力集中在能够确保信息增益的来源上,而远离那些不太可能将不确定性降到最低的来源。这样的解释可以为信息搜寻提供一个统一的框架,将理性好奇心--估计所遇信息的未来有用性--和理性不注意所提供的神经发散视角--的益处结合起来。特别是,要最大限度地减少认识上的不确定性,就需要对学习者当前的知识或能力状况进行一些评估,也就是说,要确定对特定学习者来说可能不精确的信息来源。Jones 等人(2024 年)指出,对特定学习者而言,正式的元认知意识到特定来源的不精确性并不是该模型行为的先决条件。虽然在考虑缺乏这种元认知意识的幼儿和儿童的理性(不)注意时,这是有道理的,但理性不注意在整个发展过程中是如何表现的呢?一方面,这提出了有关全局误差的认知相关性--输入与来自不同来源的重构之间的加权误差信号之和(MSE)--的问题,特别是在元认知能力有限的幼儿中。此外,婴幼儿时期元认知意识的不断增强会如何影响信息搜寻行为的理性模型?长期以来的研究表明,幼儿对自己的知识差距缺乏广泛的元认知意识(Goupil 和 Kouider,2019 年),但最近的研究表明,即使是幼儿也会表现出某种形式的元认知监控(Goupil 和 Kouider,2016 年;Goupil、Romand-Monnier 和 Kouider,2016 年)。尽管如此,元认知能力在整个童年期都会得到显著提高,而幼儿元认知判断的绝对准确性以及这种判断对信息搜寻的影响却低得惊人。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
8.10
自引率
8.10%
发文量
132
期刊介绍: Developmental Science publishes cutting-edge theory and up-to-the-minute research on scientific developmental psychology from leading thinkers in the field. It is currently the only journal that specifically focuses on human developmental cognitive neuroscience. Coverage includes: - Clinical, computational and comparative approaches to development - Key advances in cognitive and social development - Developmental cognitive neuroscience - Functional neuroimaging of the developing brain
期刊最新文献
Bursty, Irregular Speech Input to Children Predicts Vocabulary Size RETRACTION: H. Schmidt, M. Daseking, C. Gawrilow, J. Karbach, and J. Kerner auch Koerner, “Self-Regulation in Preschool: Are Executive Function and Effortful Control Overlapping Constructs?,” Developmental Science 25, no. 6 (2022): e13272, https://doi.org/10.1111/desc.13272 Understanding a Third-Party Communicative Situation in Korean-Learning Infants How Culture Shapes the Early Development of Essentialist Beliefs Neural Markers of Attention at 6 Months Associate With Later Attentional Control Performance
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1