The Status of the Phenomenal Appearance of the Sensory in Fourteenth-century Franciscan Thought after Duns Scotus (Peter Aureol to Adam of Wodeham)

Q4 Arts and Humanities Franciscan Studies Pub Date : 2018-11-16 DOI:10.1353/FRC.2018.0008
O. Bychkov
{"title":"The Status of the Phenomenal Appearance of the Sensory in Fourteenth-century Franciscan Thought after Duns Scotus (Peter Aureol to Adam of Wodeham)","authors":"O. Bychkov","doi":"10.1353/FRC.2018.0008","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Franciscan thought in the 1300’s, starting with Duns Scotus, is quite a revolution in terms of a shift to relying on sensory and phenomenal experience in the construction of cognitive theories.1 However, we do not yet understand the full extent of its convergence with modern and contemporary thought. In what follows, we intend to advance this understanding. The experiential tendency in early fourteenth-century thought is undermined by a Cartesian-style doubt about the reliability of sensory perception and phenomenal experience that stems from the 63rd proposition of the Condemnations of 1277, which rejects the thesis that “God cannot produce the effect of a secondary cause without the secondary cause itself ”:2 a position frequently repeated by the authors discussed below. The position implies that all of our sensory and phenomenal experiences at least in principle could exist without any real things standing behind them. The issue of the status of phenomenal appearances, or the results of sensory perception or operation of other mental faculties that project a picture of what is interpreted variously as “reality,” “external world,” etc., is not new. It is raised in the Hindu and Buddhist thought long before Greek thought. Descriptions of hallucinations, visual illusions, and altered mental states abound, such as a rope appearing as a snake or one’s phenomenal field being colored yellow or red from a diseased condition","PeriodicalId":53533,"journal":{"name":"Franciscan Studies","volume":"76 1","pages":"267 - 285"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2018-11-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1353/FRC.2018.0008","citationCount":"1","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Franciscan Studies","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1353/FRC.2018.0008","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q4","JCRName":"Arts and Humanities","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1

Abstract

Franciscan thought in the 1300’s, starting with Duns Scotus, is quite a revolution in terms of a shift to relying on sensory and phenomenal experience in the construction of cognitive theories.1 However, we do not yet understand the full extent of its convergence with modern and contemporary thought. In what follows, we intend to advance this understanding. The experiential tendency in early fourteenth-century thought is undermined by a Cartesian-style doubt about the reliability of sensory perception and phenomenal experience that stems from the 63rd proposition of the Condemnations of 1277, which rejects the thesis that “God cannot produce the effect of a secondary cause without the secondary cause itself ”:2 a position frequently repeated by the authors discussed below. The position implies that all of our sensory and phenomenal experiences at least in principle could exist without any real things standing behind them. The issue of the status of phenomenal appearances, or the results of sensory perception or operation of other mental faculties that project a picture of what is interpreted variously as “reality,” “external world,” etc., is not new. It is raised in the Hindu and Buddhist thought long before Greek thought. Descriptions of hallucinations, visual illusions, and altered mental states abound, such as a rope appearing as a snake or one’s phenomenal field being colored yellow or red from a diseased condition
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
邓斯·斯科特之后14世纪方济会思想中感官现象的地位(彼得·奥雷罗致亚当·沃德汉姆)
13世纪方济会的思想,从邓斯·司各脱开始,是一场相当大的革命,因为它转向依靠感官和现象经验来构建认知理论然而,我们还没有完全了解它与现当代思想的融合程度。在接下来的文章中,我们打算促进这种理解。14世纪早期的经验倾向被笛卡尔式的对感官知觉和现象经验的可靠性的怀疑所破坏,这种怀疑源于1277年谴责的第63个命题,它拒绝了“上帝不能在没有次要原因本身的情况下产生次要原因的结果”的论点:2下面讨论的作者经常重复这个立场。这一立场意味着,至少在原则上,我们所有的感官和现象体验都可以在没有任何真实事物支撑的情况下存在。现象表象的状态,或者感官知觉的结果,或者其他心理机能的运作,投射出一幅被不同地解释为“现实”、“外部世界”等的图景,这些问题并不新鲜。它早在希腊思想之前就在印度教和佛教思想中被提出。关于幻觉、视觉错觉和精神状态改变的描述比比皆是,比如一根绳子看起来像一条蛇,或者一个人的现象场因患病而被染成黄色或红色
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
Franciscan Studies
Franciscan Studies Arts and Humanities-Religious Studies
CiteScore
0.20
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
Guibert of Tournai's Letter to Lady Isabelle: An Introduction and English Translation John Punch's Hybrid Theory of Relations Editorial – A Word of Thanks Eric Doyle OFM: Hidden Architect of the Retrieval of the Franciscan Charism by Brenda Abbott (review) Communicating Conversion: Penitential Turn Transmission in the Early Franciscan Fraternity
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1