A Theory of Differential Punishment

IF 2.4 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Vanderbilt Law Review Pub Date : 2017-10-07 DOI:10.2139/ssrn.2910719
John A. Boeglin, Zachary B. Shapiro
{"title":"A Theory of Differential Punishment","authors":"John A. Boeglin, Zachary B. Shapiro","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.2910719","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"INTRODUCTIONIn 2009, three roommates at Purdue University in Indiana were drinking in their living room on a Saturday night when one of them, Landon Siela, headed to the bathroom. The other two roommates, William Calderon and Cory Lynch, each decided to \"prank\" Siela by pulling an unloaded gun on him and pretending to shoot when he returned to the living room. Tragically, Lynch's gun, unbeknownst to him, still had a live bullet lodged in the chamber, which struck and killed Siela when Lynch pulled the trigger. As a result, Calderon and Lynch were both convicted of criminal offenses. But while Calderon was convicted only of the Class A misdemeanor of \"pointing a firearm,\" punishable by no more than a year in prison,1 Lynch was convicted of reckless manslaughter, a Class C felony that carries a maximum sentence of eight years.2It is clear that the fact that Lynch's reckless actions caused Siela's death exposed him to much harsher legal penalties than those faced by Calderon. It is less clear, however, what justifies this discrepancy in severity, given that Lynch does not seem to have behaved any more culpably than Calderon. This dilemma, a close cousin of the philosophical problem of \"moral luck,\" has long stood as an intractable puzzle in the theory of criminal law.3The majority position among scholars on this topic, exemplified by Stephen J. Schulhofer in his influential 1974 article Harm and Punishment, is that differentiating punishment based on its results cannot be justified as a matter of practice.4 However, some theorists have dissented from this view. A few proponents of retributive punishment, most prominently philosopher Michael Moore,5 have attempted to resolve the dilemma of \"differential punishment\" by claiming that the consequences of one?s actions weigh directly on one?s ?moral desert,? and thus that an action that causes greater harm merits greater punishment.6 Other commentators, such as Judge Richard Posner, have advanced utilitarian rationales for more severely punishing those offenders who cause greater harm, arguing, inter alia, that this approach more effectively and efficiently deters future harmful conduct.7 However, as of yet, no theorist has succeeded in producing a widely accepted justification for this feature of the criminal law.In this Article, we propose a general theory of differential punishment-that is, the practice of differentiating an offender?s punishment based on whether her actions bring about a statutory harm. In so defining differential punishment, we borrow Schulhofer?s definition of statutory harm as ?[a]ny consequence of conduct . . . [that] is a necessary element of a given offense.?8 As Schulhofer explains, the concept of statutory harm is not coextensive with what might ordinarily be thought of as the ?harms? caused by a criminal offense, or with the ultimate harm or consequence that the criminal offense seeks to prevent.9 For example, if a married man is murdered, his wife might be ?harmed? in that she mourns his death and misses his company. But the wife?s psychological distress is not a statutory harm for the crime of murder, because-unlike her husband?s death-it is not a necessary element of the crime. Conversely, because the crime of burglary requires ?unauthorized entry into a building with intent to commit a felony therein,? one might reasonably think that the intended felony, and not the unlawful entry, is the ultimate harm the crime of burglary seeks to prevent.10 However, because ?unauthorized entry into a building? is a consequence of the offender?s conduct that is a necessary element of the crime of burglary, it is a statutory harm. Moreover, it is important to note that not all crimes have a statutory harm-for instance, inchoate crimes, such as attempts, prohibit certain types of conduct even if such conduct does not lead to any statutorily prohibited consequences.While a myriad of factors go into determining what specific sentence a judge will impose in any given case (such as an offender? …","PeriodicalId":47503,"journal":{"name":"Vanderbilt Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.4000,"publicationDate":"2017-10-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"3","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Vanderbilt Law Review","FirstCategoryId":"90","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2910719","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"LAW","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3

Abstract

INTRODUCTIONIn 2009, three roommates at Purdue University in Indiana were drinking in their living room on a Saturday night when one of them, Landon Siela, headed to the bathroom. The other two roommates, William Calderon and Cory Lynch, each decided to "prank" Siela by pulling an unloaded gun on him and pretending to shoot when he returned to the living room. Tragically, Lynch's gun, unbeknownst to him, still had a live bullet lodged in the chamber, which struck and killed Siela when Lynch pulled the trigger. As a result, Calderon and Lynch were both convicted of criminal offenses. But while Calderon was convicted only of the Class A misdemeanor of "pointing a firearm," punishable by no more than a year in prison,1 Lynch was convicted of reckless manslaughter, a Class C felony that carries a maximum sentence of eight years.2It is clear that the fact that Lynch's reckless actions caused Siela's death exposed him to much harsher legal penalties than those faced by Calderon. It is less clear, however, what justifies this discrepancy in severity, given that Lynch does not seem to have behaved any more culpably than Calderon. This dilemma, a close cousin of the philosophical problem of "moral luck," has long stood as an intractable puzzle in the theory of criminal law.3The majority position among scholars on this topic, exemplified by Stephen J. Schulhofer in his influential 1974 article Harm and Punishment, is that differentiating punishment based on its results cannot be justified as a matter of practice.4 However, some theorists have dissented from this view. A few proponents of retributive punishment, most prominently philosopher Michael Moore,5 have attempted to resolve the dilemma of "differential punishment" by claiming that the consequences of one?s actions weigh directly on one?s ?moral desert,? and thus that an action that causes greater harm merits greater punishment.6 Other commentators, such as Judge Richard Posner, have advanced utilitarian rationales for more severely punishing those offenders who cause greater harm, arguing, inter alia, that this approach more effectively and efficiently deters future harmful conduct.7 However, as of yet, no theorist has succeeded in producing a widely accepted justification for this feature of the criminal law.In this Article, we propose a general theory of differential punishment-that is, the practice of differentiating an offender?s punishment based on whether her actions bring about a statutory harm. In so defining differential punishment, we borrow Schulhofer?s definition of statutory harm as ?[a]ny consequence of conduct . . . [that] is a necessary element of a given offense.?8 As Schulhofer explains, the concept of statutory harm is not coextensive with what might ordinarily be thought of as the ?harms? caused by a criminal offense, or with the ultimate harm or consequence that the criminal offense seeks to prevent.9 For example, if a married man is murdered, his wife might be ?harmed? in that she mourns his death and misses his company. But the wife?s psychological distress is not a statutory harm for the crime of murder, because-unlike her husband?s death-it is not a necessary element of the crime. Conversely, because the crime of burglary requires ?unauthorized entry into a building with intent to commit a felony therein,? one might reasonably think that the intended felony, and not the unlawful entry, is the ultimate harm the crime of burglary seeks to prevent.10 However, because ?unauthorized entry into a building? is a consequence of the offender?s conduct that is a necessary element of the crime of burglary, it is a statutory harm. Moreover, it is important to note that not all crimes have a statutory harm-for instance, inchoate crimes, such as attempts, prohibit certain types of conduct even if such conduct does not lead to any statutorily prohibited consequences.While a myriad of factors go into determining what specific sentence a judge will impose in any given case (such as an offender? …
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
差别处罚理论
2009年,一个周六的晚上,印第安纳州普渡大学(Purdue University)的三个室友在客厅喝酒,其中一个名叫兰登·西拉(Landon Siela)的室友去了洗手间。另外两个室友,威廉·卡尔德隆和科里·林奇,每个人都决定“恶作剧”西拉,他们拿出一把没上膛的枪指着他,假装在他回到客厅时开枪。可悲的是,林奇不知道的是,他的枪里还有一颗子弹,当林奇扣动扳机时,这颗子弹击中了西拉,杀死了他。结果,卡尔德隆和林奇都被判犯有刑事罪。但卡尔德隆只被判犯有A级轻罪,即“拿枪指着人”,最多可判处一年监禁,而林奇则被判犯有过失杀人罪,这是C级重罪,最高可判处8年监禁。很明显,林奇鲁莽的行为导致了塞拉的死亡,这一事实使他面临比卡尔德隆更严厉的法律惩罚。然而,考虑到林奇的行为似乎并不比卡尔德隆更有罪,是什么证明了这种严重程度上的差异是合理的,目前还不太清楚。这一困境是“道德运气”哲学问题的近亲,长期以来一直是刑法理论中难以解决的难题。学者们在这个问题上的大多数立场,以斯蒂芬·j·舒尔霍夫1974年发表的有影响力的文章《伤害与惩罚》为例,认为根据惩罚的结果来区分惩罚在实践中是不合理的然而,一些理论家不同意这种观点。报应性惩罚的一些支持者,最著名的是哲学家迈克尔·摩尔(Michael Moore) 5,试图解决“差别惩罚”的困境,声称一种惩罚的后果是什么?美国的行为直接影响到一个国家?道德应得,?因此,造成更大伤害的行为应该受到更大的惩罚其他评论家,如理查德·波斯纳法官,提出了功利主义的理由,更严厉地惩罚那些造成更大伤害的罪犯,他们认为,除其他外,这种方法更有效地阻止了未来的有害行为然而,到目前为止,还没有一个理论家成功地为刑法的这一特征提出一个被广泛接受的理由。在本文中,我们提出了区别处罚的一般理论-即区分罪犯的实践?根据她的行为是否造成法定损害来处罚她。在定义差别惩罚时,我们借用了舒尔霍夫?法定损害的定义是?行为的任何后果……这是构成犯罪的必要因素。正如舒尔霍弗所解释的那样,法定损害的概念与通常被认为是“损害”的概念并不广泛。由刑事犯罪引起的,或具有刑事犯罪试图防止的最终伤害或后果的例如,如果一个已婚男子被谋杀,他的妻子可能会受到伤害。因为她哀悼他的死,想念他的陪伴。但是妻子呢?S的心理困扰不是谋杀罪的法定伤害,因为——不像她的丈夫?这并不是犯罪的必要因素。相反,由于入室行窃罪要求未经授权进入建筑物并意图在其中犯下重罪,人们可能会合理地认为,入室行窃罪试图防止的最终危害是故意的重罪,而不是非法进入但是,因为,擅自进入大楼?是违法者的后果吗?这种行为认为是入室行窃罪的必要要件,是一种法定损害。此外,必须指出,并非所有罪行都具有法定损害,例如,早期犯罪,例如企图,禁止某些类型的行为,即使这种行为不会导致任何法定禁止的后果。虽然有无数的因素决定了法官在任何特定案件(如罪犯?...
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
2.30
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊介绍: Vanderbilt Law Review En Banc is an online forum designed to advance scholarly discussion. En Banc offers professors, practitioners, students, and others an opportunity to respond to articles printed in the Vanderbilt Law Review. En Banc permits extended discussion of our articles in a way that maintains academic integrity and provides authors with a quicker approach to publication. When reexamining a case “en banc” an appellate court operates at its highest level, with all judges present and participating “on the bench.” We chose the name “En Banc” to capture this spirit of focused review and provide a forum for further dialogue where all can be present and participate.
期刊最新文献
Beyond Wickedness: Managing Complex Systems and Climate Change Formal Justice and Judicial Precedent Rights, Wrongs, and Recourse in the Law of Torts Discovery Cost Allocation, Due Process, and the Constitution's Role in Civil Litigation Judging Law in Election Cases
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1