Philosophy

IF 0.1 4区 历史学 0 CLASSICS GREECE & ROME Pub Date : 2021-04-01 DOI:10.1017/S0017383520000339
J. Bryan
{"title":"Philosophy","authors":"J. Bryan","doi":"10.1017/S0017383520000339","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Sara Brill's new book develops her argument for understanding ‘shared life’ as central to Aristotle's ethics and politics. By focusing on this notion of shared life, she seeks to establish the connection between Aristotle's ethical, political, and zoological works in order to ground her emphasis on the essential animality of human society in Aristotle's conception. Her argument turns on a distinction between bios, a ‘way of life’ that we can choose or reject, and zoē, ‘life itself’ (3), and she is committed to establishing the generally unrecognized significance of the latter in Aristotle's ethical thought. The volume is divided into three parts. The first (‘Shared Life in Aristotle's Ethics and Politics’) concentrates on developing an account of Aristotle's concept of ‘shared life’ in the ethical and political works in such a way as to establish the importance of the zoological perspective. Here, Brill argues that shared life is at the heart of many of the central concerns of the Nicomachean Ethics, including his account of friendship. This is not simply sharing of goods or communal living: ‘Because living in its authoritative sense is perceiving and thinking, sharing one's life is sharing in perception and sharing in thinking’ (52). Brill finds a similar focus on shared zoē in the Eudemian Ethics, and the suggestion that our self-awareness and self-concern depend on the presence of others. She further develops her central claim: for all that Aristotle makes repeated assertions of human exceptionality, he also adopts a zoological framework of analysis that locates human friendship within the category of ‘animal attachment’, albeit as a special case. Human society is distinguished from animal society, but primarily as an intensification of the animal, rather than as a rejection of it. As Brill notes, setting up some of the critical analysis found in the third part of the book, her emphasis on community helps to highlight both its fragility and the consequences of exclusion. This is an idea she explains further in her analysis of shared life in the Politics: ‘if Aristotle's ethics show us the most vivid form of shared life, his Politics shows us the conditions of its destruction’ (92). Brill considers two extremes of shared life to be found in the Politics. Aristotle rejects communism for the sake of the philia that lies at the heart of a true community. His account of tyranny, meanwhile, can be understood as an analysis of a polis lacking a meaningful presence of shared life or the common good. The second part of the book concentrates on fleshing out the detail of the zoological perspective at the heart of Brill's argument by focusing on the zoological works in particular. She makes the sensible point that, while Aristotle's zoological works may be inaccurate in biological detail, they nevertheless help us to understand his own thinking about the nature and relationship of intelligence and life. Beginning with the History of Animals, Brill looks for the political in Aristotle's biological, and argues that he conceives of animal sociality in terms of its various manifestations of the political bond of a common task. It is within this context that we should situate even shared human life. This is not to say that humans are not to be distinguished from animals: what marks humans out is the fact that they can choose their way of life (bios). But this choice does not liberate them from the fact of their animality. For this reason, analysis of Aristotle's politics, and of the polis itself, should be informed by an awareness of his zoological sensibility. At times in the detail of Brill's own analysis, this zoological emphasis seems to fade into the background, but her central claim remains that human politics is an intensification of animal sociality, rather than a rejection of it. The third and final part presents an intriguing exploration of intersections between Brill's account of Aristotle's zoē-politics and modern critical theory (her volume is published in the interdisciplinary series Classics in Theory). She first addresses the connection between Aristotle's commitment to private ownership and his eugenics legislation, noting the double mean of tokos as both ‘interest’ and ‘child’. She is particularly interesting on Aristotle's concern with the threat of uncontrolled or excessive reproduction. She then turns to an analysis of Aristotle's account of – and ambivalence towards – the maternal bond as central to his understanding of human communities and, especially, friendship. The two chapters of Part III are particularly compelling; I look forward to seeing further approaches to Aristotle, and ancient philosophy in general, along these lines.","PeriodicalId":44977,"journal":{"name":"GREECE & ROME","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1000,"publicationDate":"2021-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0017383520000339","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"GREECE & ROME","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0017383520000339","RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"CLASSICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Sara Brill's new book develops her argument for understanding ‘shared life’ as central to Aristotle's ethics and politics. By focusing on this notion of shared life, she seeks to establish the connection between Aristotle's ethical, political, and zoological works in order to ground her emphasis on the essential animality of human society in Aristotle's conception. Her argument turns on a distinction between bios, a ‘way of life’ that we can choose or reject, and zoē, ‘life itself’ (3), and she is committed to establishing the generally unrecognized significance of the latter in Aristotle's ethical thought. The volume is divided into three parts. The first (‘Shared Life in Aristotle's Ethics and Politics’) concentrates on developing an account of Aristotle's concept of ‘shared life’ in the ethical and political works in such a way as to establish the importance of the zoological perspective. Here, Brill argues that shared life is at the heart of many of the central concerns of the Nicomachean Ethics, including his account of friendship. This is not simply sharing of goods or communal living: ‘Because living in its authoritative sense is perceiving and thinking, sharing one's life is sharing in perception and sharing in thinking’ (52). Brill finds a similar focus on shared zoē in the Eudemian Ethics, and the suggestion that our self-awareness and self-concern depend on the presence of others. She further develops her central claim: for all that Aristotle makes repeated assertions of human exceptionality, he also adopts a zoological framework of analysis that locates human friendship within the category of ‘animal attachment’, albeit as a special case. Human society is distinguished from animal society, but primarily as an intensification of the animal, rather than as a rejection of it. As Brill notes, setting up some of the critical analysis found in the third part of the book, her emphasis on community helps to highlight both its fragility and the consequences of exclusion. This is an idea she explains further in her analysis of shared life in the Politics: ‘if Aristotle's ethics show us the most vivid form of shared life, his Politics shows us the conditions of its destruction’ (92). Brill considers two extremes of shared life to be found in the Politics. Aristotle rejects communism for the sake of the philia that lies at the heart of a true community. His account of tyranny, meanwhile, can be understood as an analysis of a polis lacking a meaningful presence of shared life or the common good. The second part of the book concentrates on fleshing out the detail of the zoological perspective at the heart of Brill's argument by focusing on the zoological works in particular. She makes the sensible point that, while Aristotle's zoological works may be inaccurate in biological detail, they nevertheless help us to understand his own thinking about the nature and relationship of intelligence and life. Beginning with the History of Animals, Brill looks for the political in Aristotle's biological, and argues that he conceives of animal sociality in terms of its various manifestations of the political bond of a common task. It is within this context that we should situate even shared human life. This is not to say that humans are not to be distinguished from animals: what marks humans out is the fact that they can choose their way of life (bios). But this choice does not liberate them from the fact of their animality. For this reason, analysis of Aristotle's politics, and of the polis itself, should be informed by an awareness of his zoological sensibility. At times in the detail of Brill's own analysis, this zoological emphasis seems to fade into the background, but her central claim remains that human politics is an intensification of animal sociality, rather than a rejection of it. The third and final part presents an intriguing exploration of intersections between Brill's account of Aristotle's zoē-politics and modern critical theory (her volume is published in the interdisciplinary series Classics in Theory). She first addresses the connection between Aristotle's commitment to private ownership and his eugenics legislation, noting the double mean of tokos as both ‘interest’ and ‘child’. She is particularly interesting on Aristotle's concern with the threat of uncontrolled or excessive reproduction. She then turns to an analysis of Aristotle's account of – and ambivalence towards – the maternal bond as central to his understanding of human communities and, especially, friendship. The two chapters of Part III are particularly compelling; I look forward to seeing further approaches to Aristotle, and ancient philosophy in general, along these lines.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
哲学
萨拉·布里尔的新书进一步阐述了她的观点,即把“共同生活”理解为亚里士多德伦理学和政治学的核心。通过关注共同生活的概念,她试图在亚里士多德的伦理、政治和动物学著作之间建立联系,以便将她的重点放在亚里士多德概念中人类社会的本质动物性上。她的论点围绕着对bios(我们可以选择或拒绝的“生活方式”)和zou(“生活本身”)的区分展开,她致力于确立后者在亚里士多德伦理思想中普遍未被认识到的重要性。全书分为三部分。第一篇(《亚里士多德的伦理学和政治学中的共同生活》)着重于发展亚里士多德在伦理学和政治学著作中的“共同生活”概念,以确立动物学观点的重要性。在这里,布里尔认为,共享生活是《尼各马可伦理学》许多核心问题的核心,包括他对友谊的描述。这不仅仅是分享物品或共同生活:“因为生活在权威意义上是感知和思考,分享一个人的生活就是分享感知和分享思考”(52)。布里尔在《尤德米安伦理学》中也发现了类似的观点,即我们的自我意识和自我关注依赖于他人的存在。她进一步发展了她的核心主张:尽管亚里士多德一再断言人类是例外的,但他也采用了一种动物学的分析框架,将人类友谊置于“动物依恋”的范畴内,尽管这是一种特殊情况。人类社会不同于动物社会,但主要是作为动物的强化,而不是作为对动物的排斥。正如布里尔所指出的,在书的第三部分中,她建立了一些批判性的分析,她对社区的强调有助于强调社区的脆弱性和排斥的后果。她在《政治学》中对共同生活的分析中进一步解释了这一观点:“如果亚里士多德的伦理学向我们展示了共同生活最生动的形式,那么他的《政治学》则向我们展示了共同生活毁灭的条件”(92)。布里尔认为在政治中可以找到共同生活的两个极端。亚里斯多德拒绝共产主义,是因为真正共同体的核心是非利亚。与此同时,他对暴政的描述可以被理解为对一个缺乏共享生活或共同利益的有意义存在的城邦的分析。书的第二部分集中于充实动物视角的细节,这是布里尔论证的核心,特别关注动物著作。她提出了一个明智的观点,即尽管亚里士多德的动物学著作在生物学细节上可能不准确,但它们仍有助于我们理解他自己对智力与生命的本质和关系的思考。从《动物史》开始,布里尔在亚里士多德的生物学中寻找政治,并认为他从共同任务的政治纽带的各种表现形式来构想动物的社会性。我们甚至应该把人类共同的生活置于这样的背景之下。这并不是说人类与动物没有区别:人类的区别在于他们可以选择自己的生活方式(bios)。但是这种选择并不能使他们从他们的兽性中解脱出来。由于这个原因,分析亚里士多德的政治,以及城邦本身,应该了解他的动物感性。有时,在布里尔自己的分析细节中,这种对动物学的强调似乎逐渐消失在背景中,但她的核心主张仍然是,人类政治是动物社会性的强化,而不是对它的拒绝。第三部分,也是最后一部分,对布里尔对亚里士多德zoē-politics和现代批判理论的描述之间的交叉点进行了有趣的探索(她的卷出版在跨学科系列理论经典中)。她首先阐述了亚里士多德对私有制的承诺和他的优生学立法之间的联系,注意到tokos既是“利益”又是“孩子”的双重含义。她对亚里士多德对不受控制或过度繁殖的威胁的关注特别感兴趣。然后,她转而分析了亚里士多德对母性纽带的描述——以及对母性纽带的矛盾心理——这是他对人类社会,尤其是友谊的理解的核心。第三部分的两章特别引人注目;我期待看到进一步的方法来研究亚里士多德,以及一般的古代哲学,沿着这些思路。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
GREECE & ROME
GREECE & ROME CLASSICS-
CiteScore
0.30
自引率
0.00%
发文量
35
期刊介绍: Published with the wider audience in mind, Greece & Rome features informative and lucid articles on ancient history, art, archaeology, religion, philosophy, and the classical tradition. Although its content is of interest to professional scholars, undergraduates and general readers who wish to be kept informed of what scholars are currently thinking will find it engaging and accessible. All Greek and Latin quotations are translated. A subscription to Greece & Rome includes a supplement of New Surveys in the Classics. These supplements have covered a broad range of topics, from key figures like Homer and Virgil, to subjects such as Greek tragedy, thought and science, women, slavery, and Roman religion. The 2007 New Survey will be Comedy by Nick Lowe.
期刊最新文献
Latin literature CHRISTIANITY AND CONSTANTINE'S IMPERIAL WOMEN Greek history A TE IN CATULLUS POEM 50: A PUN CURIOSITAS AND PSYCHE'S GROWTH IN APULEIUS' METAMORPHOSES
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1