Was Spinoza a Pagan?

IF 0.2 4区 社会学 N/A HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms Pub Date : 2023-01-17 DOI:10.1080/10848770.2023.2164951
G. Havers
{"title":"Was Spinoza a Pagan?","authors":"G. Havers","doi":"10.1080/10848770.2023.2164951","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Spinoza once remarked in a letter to his friend Hugo Boxel: “To me the authority of Plato, Aristotle, and Socrates is not worth much.” The clarity of this statement has not deterred even experienced readers of Spinoza’s works from associating his philosophy with the philosophers of classical antiquity. Steven Nadler, in his latest study of Spinoza, cogently shows that the theme of freedom ties together Spinoza’s major works on metaphysics, ethics, and politics. He brings forth valuable insights that help readers comprehend and appreciate the unique contribution of Spinoza towards a metaphysical, moral, psychological, and political understanding of a truly free, happy, and rational existence, one that celebrates life over death. However, the core premise of Nadler’s argument, that Spinoza is indebted to pagan philosophy (especially Stoicism), seriously undermines the coherence of his study. Although Nadler is certain that “Spinoza fits well in this broad eudaimonistic tradition” represented by Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics, he provides no substantive evidence for this thesis (10). What Nadler’s insights sometimes demonstrate, despite his intent, is the utterly biblical foundation of Spinoza’s philosophy of freedom and life. Although Spinoza is typically read as a defender of a naturalistic determinism that disallows freedom, Nadler persuasively outlines the paradox that Spinoza’s articulation of this necessity does not contradict his robust conceptualization of freedom. Spinoza’s rejection of free will—the superstitious belief that the faculty of the will enables human beings to freely ignore the psychological causes (e.g., passions) that determine their actions—is not a repudiation of true freedom. Rather, the authentic practice of the free life requires the recognition of the necessary truth that one cannot be free unless one lives according to reason. A life dedicated to reason, in turn, does not and cannot willfully extinguish the existence of the passions. What a rational understanding of freedom can enable is active control of one’s passions, as opposed to a surrender to them. As Nadler explains through his analyses of both Spinoza’s Ethics and Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect, the free person “acts rather than reacts. He will certainly do what he wishes, but what he wishes—and thus his behavior—is guided from within, by knowledge rather than by imagination, sentiment, or feeling” (12; author’s emphasis).","PeriodicalId":55962,"journal":{"name":"European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-01-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/10848770.2023.2164951","RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"N/A","JCRName":"HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Spinoza once remarked in a letter to his friend Hugo Boxel: “To me the authority of Plato, Aristotle, and Socrates is not worth much.” The clarity of this statement has not deterred even experienced readers of Spinoza’s works from associating his philosophy with the philosophers of classical antiquity. Steven Nadler, in his latest study of Spinoza, cogently shows that the theme of freedom ties together Spinoza’s major works on metaphysics, ethics, and politics. He brings forth valuable insights that help readers comprehend and appreciate the unique contribution of Spinoza towards a metaphysical, moral, psychological, and political understanding of a truly free, happy, and rational existence, one that celebrates life over death. However, the core premise of Nadler’s argument, that Spinoza is indebted to pagan philosophy (especially Stoicism), seriously undermines the coherence of his study. Although Nadler is certain that “Spinoza fits well in this broad eudaimonistic tradition” represented by Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics, he provides no substantive evidence for this thesis (10). What Nadler’s insights sometimes demonstrate, despite his intent, is the utterly biblical foundation of Spinoza’s philosophy of freedom and life. Although Spinoza is typically read as a defender of a naturalistic determinism that disallows freedom, Nadler persuasively outlines the paradox that Spinoza’s articulation of this necessity does not contradict his robust conceptualization of freedom. Spinoza’s rejection of free will—the superstitious belief that the faculty of the will enables human beings to freely ignore the psychological causes (e.g., passions) that determine their actions—is not a repudiation of true freedom. Rather, the authentic practice of the free life requires the recognition of the necessary truth that one cannot be free unless one lives according to reason. A life dedicated to reason, in turn, does not and cannot willfully extinguish the existence of the passions. What a rational understanding of freedom can enable is active control of one’s passions, as opposed to a surrender to them. As Nadler explains through his analyses of both Spinoza’s Ethics and Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect, the free person “acts rather than reacts. He will certainly do what he wishes, but what he wishes—and thus his behavior—is guided from within, by knowledge rather than by imagination, sentiment, or feeling” (12; author’s emphasis).
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
斯宾诺莎是异教徒吗?
斯宾诺莎曾在给朋友雨果·波克塞尔的一封信中说:“对我来说,柏拉图、亚里士多德和苏格拉底的权威没有多大价值。”这句话的清晰并没有阻止斯宾诺莎作品的资深读者将他的哲学与古代哲学家联系起来。史蒂文·纳德勒在他对斯宾诺莎的最新研究中有力地表明,自由的主题将斯宾诺莎关于形而上学、伦理学和政治的主要作品联系在一起。他提出了有价值的见解,帮助读者理解和欣赏斯宾诺莎对形而上学、道德、心理和政治理解的独特贡献,即真正自由、快乐和理性的存在,一种庆祝生而非死的存在。然而,纳德勒论点的核心前提,即斯宾诺莎得益于异教徒哲学(尤其是斯多葛主义),严重破坏了他的研究的连贯性。尽管纳德勒确信“斯宾诺莎非常符合以苏格拉底、柏拉图、亚里士多德和斯多葛学派为代表的这种广泛的一元论传统”,但他并没有为这篇论文提供实质性的证据(10)。Nadler的见解有时表明,尽管他的意图是,斯宾诺莎的自由和生命哲学完全是圣经的基础。尽管斯宾诺莎通常被解读为不允许自由的自然主义决定论的捍卫者,但纳德勒令人信服地概述了一个悖论,即斯宾诺莎对这种必要性的阐述与他对自由的有力概念并不矛盾。斯宾诺莎拒绝自由意志——迷信意志的力量使人类能够自由地忽视决定其行为的心理原因(如激情)——并不是对真正自由的否定。相反,真正的自由生活实践需要承认一个必要的真理,即除非一个人按照理性生活,否则他就不可能自由。一个专注于理性的生活,反过来,不会也不可能故意熄灭激情的存在。对自由的理性理解所能实现的是积极控制自己的激情,而不是屈服于激情。正如纳德勒通过分析斯宾诺莎的《伦理学》和《知识分子复兴论》所解释的那样,自由人“行动而非反应。他肯定会做他希望做的事,但他希望做什么——以及他的行为——是由知识而非想象、情感或感觉从内部引导的”(12;作者的重点)。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms
European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms HUMANITIES, MULTIDISCIPLINARY-
CiteScore
0.30
自引率
0.00%
发文量
97
期刊最新文献
Meeting a Hero Grandmother Zofia’s Table Symphony as Event: The Significance of Political Philosophy On Aging: A Personal Account Joseph Brodsky and the Aesthetic Origins of Ethics
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1