The consequentialist problem with prepunishment

IF 0.7 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Thought-A Journal of Philosophy Pub Date : 2021-05-11 DOI:10.1002/THT3.493
Preston Greene
{"title":"The consequentialist problem with prepunishment","authors":"Preston Greene","doi":"10.1002/THT3.493","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"This paper targets a nearly universal assumption in the philosophical literature: that prepunishment is unproblematic for consequentialists. Prepunishment threats do not deter, as deterrence is traditionally conceived. In fact, a pure prepunishment legal system would tend to increase the criminal disposition of the grudgingly compliant. This is a serious problem since, from many perspectives, but especially from a consequentialist one, a primary purpose of punishment is deterrence. I analyze the decision theory behind preand postpunishments, which helps clarify both what deterrence is and how it operates in consequentialist justifications of punishment. I end by sketching a road map for the future of prepunishment as artificial intelligence and other technological advances generate increasing possibilities for its use. If the police could know that a person will commit a crime tomorrow, then could they reasonably decide to “prepunish” the predicted offender today? This was the question first asked by Christopher New [1992], who argued that such a practice, if made feasible, would be morally permissible. The intuition against prepunishment, New claimed, results from “attaching improper moral significance to an insignificant temporal fact” [37]. Subsequently, many philosophers have disagreed with New on nonconsequentialist grounds. Consequentialists think that the practice of punishing should aim to produce good consequences. One of the primary ways the threat of punishment produces good consequences is by deterring crime. And the most obvious way that the threat of punishment deters crime is by making people fear that they would be punished in response to their criminal act. Virtually everyone assumes that prepunishment is unproblematic, or dramatically less problematic, for consequentialists. For those who think that prepunishment is problematic, this is viewed as a reason to doubt consequentialism. Underlying the belief that prepunishment is unproblematic for consequentialists is the assumption that the deterrent value of prepunishment is similar to the deterrent value of postpunishment. This starts with New (1992, 38): “In preas much as in postpunishment the penalty imposed may deter potential offenders, as also the actual offender, from committing other offences in the future.” In his influential reply, Smilansky (1994, 50) agrees with New at least to that extent. He writes, “We need not concern ourselves here with [consequentialist objections]. I allow prepunishment may be useful. . . . The crucial question is whether someone who believes in nonconsequentialist constraints of justice has the resources to reject [prepunishment].” Subsequent discussions of prepunishment have emphasized its supposed deterrent value. Statman (1997, 129) writes, “Utilitarian benefits that can be gained by punishing after crime (‘postpunishment’) can also be gained by prepunishment, e.g., deterring other potential criminals. . . . It is a puzzle mainly for retributivists.” Petersen (2014, 140) writes: 1A separate but rich line of inquiry concerns the relationship between prepunishment and free will. This debate started with Smilansky (2007) and has also proven popular.","PeriodicalId":44963,"journal":{"name":"Thought-A Journal of Philosophy","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2021-05-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1002/THT3.493","citationCount":"1","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Thought-A Journal of Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1002/THT3.493","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"Arts and Humanities","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1

Abstract

This paper targets a nearly universal assumption in the philosophical literature: that prepunishment is unproblematic for consequentialists. Prepunishment threats do not deter, as deterrence is traditionally conceived. In fact, a pure prepunishment legal system would tend to increase the criminal disposition of the grudgingly compliant. This is a serious problem since, from many perspectives, but especially from a consequentialist one, a primary purpose of punishment is deterrence. I analyze the decision theory behind preand postpunishments, which helps clarify both what deterrence is and how it operates in consequentialist justifications of punishment. I end by sketching a road map for the future of prepunishment as artificial intelligence and other technological advances generate increasing possibilities for its use. If the police could know that a person will commit a crime tomorrow, then could they reasonably decide to “prepunish” the predicted offender today? This was the question first asked by Christopher New [1992], who argued that such a practice, if made feasible, would be morally permissible. The intuition against prepunishment, New claimed, results from “attaching improper moral significance to an insignificant temporal fact” [37]. Subsequently, many philosophers have disagreed with New on nonconsequentialist grounds. Consequentialists think that the practice of punishing should aim to produce good consequences. One of the primary ways the threat of punishment produces good consequences is by deterring crime. And the most obvious way that the threat of punishment deters crime is by making people fear that they would be punished in response to their criminal act. Virtually everyone assumes that prepunishment is unproblematic, or dramatically less problematic, for consequentialists. For those who think that prepunishment is problematic, this is viewed as a reason to doubt consequentialism. Underlying the belief that prepunishment is unproblematic for consequentialists is the assumption that the deterrent value of prepunishment is similar to the deterrent value of postpunishment. This starts with New (1992, 38): “In preas much as in postpunishment the penalty imposed may deter potential offenders, as also the actual offender, from committing other offences in the future.” In his influential reply, Smilansky (1994, 50) agrees with New at least to that extent. He writes, “We need not concern ourselves here with [consequentialist objections]. I allow prepunishment may be useful. . . . The crucial question is whether someone who believes in nonconsequentialist constraints of justice has the resources to reject [prepunishment].” Subsequent discussions of prepunishment have emphasized its supposed deterrent value. Statman (1997, 129) writes, “Utilitarian benefits that can be gained by punishing after crime (‘postpunishment’) can also be gained by prepunishment, e.g., deterring other potential criminals. . . . It is a puzzle mainly for retributivists.” Petersen (2014, 140) writes: 1A separate but rich line of inquiry concerns the relationship between prepunishment and free will. This debate started with Smilansky (2007) and has also proven popular.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
预备役的后果主义问题
本文针对哲学文献中一个几乎普遍的假设:对后果主义者来说,准备是没有问题的。预备性威胁并不能起到威慑作用,因为传统上认为威慑作用。事实上,一个纯粹的准备惩罚的法律体系往往会增加那些勉强顺从的人的犯罪倾向。这是一个严重的问题,因为从许多角度,特别是从后果主义角度来看,惩罚的主要目的是威慑。我分析了惩罚前后的决策理论,这有助于澄清什么是威慑,以及它如何在惩罚的后果性正当性中发挥作用。最后,随着人工智能和其他技术进步为其使用带来越来越多的可能性,我为未来的准备工作绘制了一张路线图。如果警方能知道一个人明天会犯罪,那么他们今天能合理地决定“为”预测的罪犯“做准备”吗?这是Christopher New【1992】首次提出的问题,他认为这种做法如果可行,在道德上是允许的。New声称,反对准备的直觉源于“将不恰当的道德意义附加到一个微不足道的时间事实上”[37]。随后,许多哲学家以非序论的理由与新产生了分歧。后果主义者认为惩罚的目的应该是产生好的后果。惩罚威胁产生良好后果的主要方式之一是威慑犯罪。惩罚威胁威慑犯罪的最明显方式是让人们担心自己的犯罪行为会受到惩罚。事实上,每个人都认为,对后果主义者来说,准备是没有问题的,或者问题大大减少。对于那些认为预科有问题的人来说,这被视为怀疑后果主义的理由。对于后果主义者来说,惩罚前是没有问题的,这一信念的基础是假设惩罚前的威慑价值与惩罚后的威慑价值相似。这始于New(1992,38):“在刑罚前和刑罚后,施加的惩罚可能会阻止潜在的罪犯,也可能阻止实际的罪犯,在未来犯下其他罪行。”Smilansky(1994,50)在他颇具影响力的答复中至少在这一程度上同意New的观点。他写道,“我们在这里不必担心[后果主义的反对意见]。我认为赦免可能是有用的……关键的问题是,相信非后果主义司法约束的人是否有资源拒绝[赦免]。”随后对赦免的讨论强调了其所谓的威慑价值。Statman(1997129)写道:“犯罪后惩罚(‘后惩罚’)可以获得的功利利益也可以通过惩罚来获得,例如,威慑其他潜在的罪犯……这主要是报复主义者的难题。”Petersen(2014140)写道:1独立但丰富的调查线涉及惩罚和自由意志之间的关系。这场争论始于斯迈兰斯基(2007),也被证明很受欢迎。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
5
期刊介绍: Thought: A Journal of Philosophy is dedicated to the publication of short (of less than 4500 words), original, philosophical papers in the following areas: Logic, Philosophy of Maths, Philosophy of Mind, Epistemology, Philosophy of Language, Metaphysics, and Value Theory. All published papers will be analytic in style. We intend that readers of Thought will be exposed to the most central and significant issues and positions in contemporary philosophy that fall under its remit. We will publish only papers that exemplify the highest standard of clarity. Thought aims to give a response to all authors within eight weeks of submission. Thought employs a triple-blind review system: the author''s identity is not revealed to the editors and referees, and the referee''s identity is not revealed to the author. Every submitted paper is appraised by the Subject Editor of the relevant subject area. Papers that pass to the editors are read by at least two experts in the relevant subject area.
期刊最新文献
Subset Realization and the Entailment Problem in advance The Co-Intension Problem in advance Removing Realizers in advance Editorial Note Measurement and desert: Why grades cannot be deserved
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1