{"title":"The consequentialist problem with prepunishment","authors":"Preston Greene","doi":"10.1002/THT3.493","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"This paper targets a nearly universal assumption in the philosophical literature: that prepunishment is unproblematic for consequentialists. Prepunishment threats do not deter, as deterrence is traditionally conceived. In fact, a pure prepunishment legal system would tend to increase the criminal disposition of the grudgingly compliant. This is a serious problem since, from many perspectives, but especially from a consequentialist one, a primary purpose of punishment is deterrence. I analyze the decision theory behind preand postpunishments, which helps clarify both what deterrence is and how it operates in consequentialist justifications of punishment. I end by sketching a road map for the future of prepunishment as artificial intelligence and other technological advances generate increasing possibilities for its use. If the police could know that a person will commit a crime tomorrow, then could they reasonably decide to “prepunish” the predicted offender today? This was the question first asked by Christopher New [1992], who argued that such a practice, if made feasible, would be morally permissible. The intuition against prepunishment, New claimed, results from “attaching improper moral significance to an insignificant temporal fact” [37]. Subsequently, many philosophers have disagreed with New on nonconsequentialist grounds. Consequentialists think that the practice of punishing should aim to produce good consequences. One of the primary ways the threat of punishment produces good consequences is by deterring crime. And the most obvious way that the threat of punishment deters crime is by making people fear that they would be punished in response to their criminal act. Virtually everyone assumes that prepunishment is unproblematic, or dramatically less problematic, for consequentialists. For those who think that prepunishment is problematic, this is viewed as a reason to doubt consequentialism. Underlying the belief that prepunishment is unproblematic for consequentialists is the assumption that the deterrent value of prepunishment is similar to the deterrent value of postpunishment. This starts with New (1992, 38): “In preas much as in postpunishment the penalty imposed may deter potential offenders, as also the actual offender, from committing other offences in the future.” In his influential reply, Smilansky (1994, 50) agrees with New at least to that extent. He writes, “We need not concern ourselves here with [consequentialist objections]. I allow prepunishment may be useful. . . . The crucial question is whether someone who believes in nonconsequentialist constraints of justice has the resources to reject [prepunishment].” Subsequent discussions of prepunishment have emphasized its supposed deterrent value. Statman (1997, 129) writes, “Utilitarian benefits that can be gained by punishing after crime (‘postpunishment’) can also be gained by prepunishment, e.g., deterring other potential criminals. . . . It is a puzzle mainly for retributivists.” Petersen (2014, 140) writes: 1A separate but rich line of inquiry concerns the relationship between prepunishment and free will. This debate started with Smilansky (2007) and has also proven popular.","PeriodicalId":44963,"journal":{"name":"Thought-A Journal of Philosophy","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2021-05-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1002/THT3.493","citationCount":"1","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Thought-A Journal of Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1002/THT3.493","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"Arts and Humanities","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Abstract
This paper targets a nearly universal assumption in the philosophical literature: that prepunishment is unproblematic for consequentialists. Prepunishment threats do not deter, as deterrence is traditionally conceived. In fact, a pure prepunishment legal system would tend to increase the criminal disposition of the grudgingly compliant. This is a serious problem since, from many perspectives, but especially from a consequentialist one, a primary purpose of punishment is deterrence. I analyze the decision theory behind preand postpunishments, which helps clarify both what deterrence is and how it operates in consequentialist justifications of punishment. I end by sketching a road map for the future of prepunishment as artificial intelligence and other technological advances generate increasing possibilities for its use. If the police could know that a person will commit a crime tomorrow, then could they reasonably decide to “prepunish” the predicted offender today? This was the question first asked by Christopher New [1992], who argued that such a practice, if made feasible, would be morally permissible. The intuition against prepunishment, New claimed, results from “attaching improper moral significance to an insignificant temporal fact” [37]. Subsequently, many philosophers have disagreed with New on nonconsequentialist grounds. Consequentialists think that the practice of punishing should aim to produce good consequences. One of the primary ways the threat of punishment produces good consequences is by deterring crime. And the most obvious way that the threat of punishment deters crime is by making people fear that they would be punished in response to their criminal act. Virtually everyone assumes that prepunishment is unproblematic, or dramatically less problematic, for consequentialists. For those who think that prepunishment is problematic, this is viewed as a reason to doubt consequentialism. Underlying the belief that prepunishment is unproblematic for consequentialists is the assumption that the deterrent value of prepunishment is similar to the deterrent value of postpunishment. This starts with New (1992, 38): “In preas much as in postpunishment the penalty imposed may deter potential offenders, as also the actual offender, from committing other offences in the future.” In his influential reply, Smilansky (1994, 50) agrees with New at least to that extent. He writes, “We need not concern ourselves here with [consequentialist objections]. I allow prepunishment may be useful. . . . The crucial question is whether someone who believes in nonconsequentialist constraints of justice has the resources to reject [prepunishment].” Subsequent discussions of prepunishment have emphasized its supposed deterrent value. Statman (1997, 129) writes, “Utilitarian benefits that can be gained by punishing after crime (‘postpunishment’) can also be gained by prepunishment, e.g., deterring other potential criminals. . . . It is a puzzle mainly for retributivists.” Petersen (2014, 140) writes: 1A separate but rich line of inquiry concerns the relationship between prepunishment and free will. This debate started with Smilansky (2007) and has also proven popular.
期刊介绍:
Thought: A Journal of Philosophy is dedicated to the publication of short (of less than 4500 words), original, philosophical papers in the following areas: Logic, Philosophy of Maths, Philosophy of Mind, Epistemology, Philosophy of Language, Metaphysics, and Value Theory. All published papers will be analytic in style. We intend that readers of Thought will be exposed to the most central and significant issues and positions in contemporary philosophy that fall under its remit. We will publish only papers that exemplify the highest standard of clarity. Thought aims to give a response to all authors within eight weeks of submission. Thought employs a triple-blind review system: the author''s identity is not revealed to the editors and referees, and the referee''s identity is not revealed to the author. Every submitted paper is appraised by the Subject Editor of the relevant subject area. Papers that pass to the editors are read by at least two experts in the relevant subject area.