The criminal law's person By C. Lernestedt, M. Matravers (Eds.), Oxford: Hart. 2022. pp. 216. £85.00 (hbk). ISBN: 9781509923748

Q2 Social Sciences Howard Journal of Crime and Justice Pub Date : 2023-03-20 DOI:10.1111/hojo.12519
David Prendergast
{"title":"The criminal law's person By C. Lernestedt, M. Matravers (Eds.), Oxford: Hart. 2022. pp. 216. £85.00 (hbk). ISBN: 9781509923748","authors":"David Prendergast","doi":"10.1111/hojo.12519","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p><i>The criminal law's person</i> is a multifaceted exploration of how substantive criminal law takes humans – or makes them out – to be. As explained in the editors’ efficient and perspicacious introduction essay, the criminal law's person might be set by how people actually are, what they ought to be, or some purpose-driven fictional construct (p.8). The book's final essay, ‘Implicit bias, self-defence and the reasonable person’, by Jules Holroyd and Federico Picinali, unpacks ‘reasonable person’ belief-based exculpatory tests in defensive force law in England and Wales and the United States and evaluates them for their facilitation of morally problematic cognitive bias, which, the authors conclude, ‘cannot be avoided in the presence of racist social structures’ (p.167). The authors push past the ‘reasonable person’ as the empirically ordinary person (p.179) to the possessor of reasonably-based and non-culpably held beliefs. But there remains, I think, further scope for consideration of the ‘reasonable person’ as an optional heuristic for getting at the actual standard of reasonableness. At least one of the jurisdictions under consideration does not even use the phrase ‘reasonable person’ in statute, but uses ‘reasonable’.<sup>1</sup> The standard of ‘reasonable’ itself is never wrong, only its application can be wrong, and the authors’ points about implicit biases could be redeployed in regard to its application.</p><p>Holroyd and Picinali invoke a conduct rules and decision rules framing distinction for their evaluation. This dual evaluation is perhaps one reflection of what Claes Lernestedt (in his contribution, ‘Standard-setting versus tracking “profound” blameworthiness: what should be the role of the rules for ascription of responsibility’) identifies as criminal law's tension between forward-looking ambitions and its limiting constraints (p.56). Lernestedt calls for criminal law to seek ‘“profound” blameworthiness in the concrete person’ (p.73). This concrete person is the actual person, not the construct, and to appreciate them in criminal law we need more input from disciplines such as psychiatry and psychology (p.73). Broadly speaking, similar concern arises in the essays by Michael Thorburn (‘In search of the criminal law's person’), Alan Norrie (‘Victims who victimise: guilt in political theory and moral psychology’) and Craig Reeves (‘Responsibility beyond blame: unfree agency and the moral psychology of criminal law's persons’). These essays each develop critical reaction to the criminal law orthodoxy that assumes the would-be (non-insane) criminal defendant as a rational autonomous agent. They question the very possibility of the criminal law's authority. Thorburn is quite demanding about the level of political understanding needed on the part of the defendant for legitimate criminal liability imposition. It is difficult to go along with Norrie's styling of the recipient of structural social injustice as a ‘victim’ in the same sense as a victim of a crime. Reeves proceeds with more nuance and no hyperbole. Norrie and Reeves both weave masterfully and informatively through, among other things, psychological guilt literature, as Thorburn does with 20th-century criminal responsibility theory.</p><p>Kai Hamdorf, a judge of the German Federal Court of Justice, contributes ‘The criminal law's person and normative elements in the legal definition of excusing circumstances’. This is a concise and elucidating account of German criminal law's self-rationalisation that pays critical attention to how it sorts exculpating from non-exculpating human disordering. Hamdorf regrets that matters of practicality and policy determine the conceptualisation of the person. But the person is not necessarily reconceptualised by the rules under scrutiny, for example, the rule requiring that blood alcohol be 10% higher for severe crimes than for lower-level crimes in order for a defendant to avail of possible partial or full exculpation due to intoxication (p.48). Hamdorf notes the standard justification as ‘people generally have a psychological hindrance or barrier to kill other human beings’ and says it is ‘hard to imagine that any psychiatrist would say that 10 per cent more alcohol is needed for a loss of control in murder than in cases of bodily harm’ (pp.48–49). But such line-drawing rules are not attempting to precisely reflect physiological and neurological reality in the first place, they do not pass or fail rational evaluation solely by reference to psychiatry; they are meant to be arbitrary (within limits) and unmistakably policy-driven. As it happens, German criminal law is a comparative leading light at doing the thing – facilitating intoxication and mental disordering to be variously and non-bluntly reflected in criminal liability – which Hamdorf says falls short of German constitutional standards of responsibility and blameworthiness (p.50).</p><p>Matt Matravers, in ‘The criminal law's various persons’, uses an <i>ex ante</i> and <i>ex post</i> frame for surveying the criminal law's conceptualisations of the person. Matravers, like Hamdorf and several other contributors to <i>The criminal law's person</i>, in effect, urges the criminal law to get a more accurate picture of the actual person than currently the case. No one calls for the criminal law to double down on its fictions. Nonetheless, Robin Zheng (‘Attributability and accountability in the criminal law’) develops a rich analytical distinction that, among other things, could aid rationalisation of current criminal law. Responsibility as attributability is simply the appraisal of an action. Responsibility as accountability is the assigning of some consequence, such as a burden, for the action (p.78). For some theorists, attributability is a precondition to accountability. Zheng shows how attributability and accountability converge in explaining <i>criminal</i> responsibility: attributability reflects moral responsibility and accountability reflects the political question of the distribution of duties and burdens across the community via criminally enforced obligations and punishment (p.80). According to Zheng, justificatory accounts of criminal law may be classed as attributability-first or as accountability-first accounts (p.77). Attributability-first accounts are more concerned to respond to the criminal law's person as a moral agent; they have a metaphysical understanding of the person. Accountability-first theories, which are less prominent than attributability-first accounts, are concerned with the person taking their place in the community's network of duties; these theories have a political conception of the person. It would seem that accountability-first theories would be more comfortable with fictional constructs of the person than attributability-first theories. But not always. Thorburn's essay, for instance, could be read as an accountability-first theory that needs the criminal law's person to (really) be something they not always are. This being just one connecting thought prompted by this fascinating book of individually excellent criminal law theory essays which collectively amount to something even greater than their sum.</p>","PeriodicalId":37514,"journal":{"name":"Howard Journal of Crime and Justice","volume":"62 1","pages":"144-146"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2023-03-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/hojo.12519","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Howard Journal of Crime and Justice","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/hojo.12519","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q2","JCRName":"Social Sciences","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

The criminal law's person is a multifaceted exploration of how substantive criminal law takes humans – or makes them out – to be. As explained in the editors’ efficient and perspicacious introduction essay, the criminal law's person might be set by how people actually are, what they ought to be, or some purpose-driven fictional construct (p.8). The book's final essay, ‘Implicit bias, self-defence and the reasonable person’, by Jules Holroyd and Federico Picinali, unpacks ‘reasonable person’ belief-based exculpatory tests in defensive force law in England and Wales and the United States and evaluates them for their facilitation of morally problematic cognitive bias, which, the authors conclude, ‘cannot be avoided in the presence of racist social structures’ (p.167). The authors push past the ‘reasonable person’ as the empirically ordinary person (p.179) to the possessor of reasonably-based and non-culpably held beliefs. But there remains, I think, further scope for consideration of the ‘reasonable person’ as an optional heuristic for getting at the actual standard of reasonableness. At least one of the jurisdictions under consideration does not even use the phrase ‘reasonable person’ in statute, but uses ‘reasonable’.1 The standard of ‘reasonable’ itself is never wrong, only its application can be wrong, and the authors’ points about implicit biases could be redeployed in regard to its application.

Holroyd and Picinali invoke a conduct rules and decision rules framing distinction for their evaluation. This dual evaluation is perhaps one reflection of what Claes Lernestedt (in his contribution, ‘Standard-setting versus tracking “profound” blameworthiness: what should be the role of the rules for ascription of responsibility’) identifies as criminal law's tension between forward-looking ambitions and its limiting constraints (p.56). Lernestedt calls for criminal law to seek ‘“profound” blameworthiness in the concrete person’ (p.73). This concrete person is the actual person, not the construct, and to appreciate them in criminal law we need more input from disciplines such as psychiatry and psychology (p.73). Broadly speaking, similar concern arises in the essays by Michael Thorburn (‘In search of the criminal law's person’), Alan Norrie (‘Victims who victimise: guilt in political theory and moral psychology’) and Craig Reeves (‘Responsibility beyond blame: unfree agency and the moral psychology of criminal law's persons’). These essays each develop critical reaction to the criminal law orthodoxy that assumes the would-be (non-insane) criminal defendant as a rational autonomous agent. They question the very possibility of the criminal law's authority. Thorburn is quite demanding about the level of political understanding needed on the part of the defendant for legitimate criminal liability imposition. It is difficult to go along with Norrie's styling of the recipient of structural social injustice as a ‘victim’ in the same sense as a victim of a crime. Reeves proceeds with more nuance and no hyperbole. Norrie and Reeves both weave masterfully and informatively through, among other things, psychological guilt literature, as Thorburn does with 20th-century criminal responsibility theory.

Kai Hamdorf, a judge of the German Federal Court of Justice, contributes ‘The criminal law's person and normative elements in the legal definition of excusing circumstances’. This is a concise and elucidating account of German criminal law's self-rationalisation that pays critical attention to how it sorts exculpating from non-exculpating human disordering. Hamdorf regrets that matters of practicality and policy determine the conceptualisation of the person. But the person is not necessarily reconceptualised by the rules under scrutiny, for example, the rule requiring that blood alcohol be 10% higher for severe crimes than for lower-level crimes in order for a defendant to avail of possible partial or full exculpation due to intoxication (p.48). Hamdorf notes the standard justification as ‘people generally have a psychological hindrance or barrier to kill other human beings’ and says it is ‘hard to imagine that any psychiatrist would say that 10 per cent more alcohol is needed for a loss of control in murder than in cases of bodily harm’ (pp.48–49). But such line-drawing rules are not attempting to precisely reflect physiological and neurological reality in the first place, they do not pass or fail rational evaluation solely by reference to psychiatry; they are meant to be arbitrary (within limits) and unmistakably policy-driven. As it happens, German criminal law is a comparative leading light at doing the thing – facilitating intoxication and mental disordering to be variously and non-bluntly reflected in criminal liability – which Hamdorf says falls short of German constitutional standards of responsibility and blameworthiness (p.50).

Matt Matravers, in ‘The criminal law's various persons’, uses an ex ante and ex post frame for surveying the criminal law's conceptualisations of the person. Matravers, like Hamdorf and several other contributors to The criminal law's person, in effect, urges the criminal law to get a more accurate picture of the actual person than currently the case. No one calls for the criminal law to double down on its fictions. Nonetheless, Robin Zheng (‘Attributability and accountability in the criminal law’) develops a rich analytical distinction that, among other things, could aid rationalisation of current criminal law. Responsibility as attributability is simply the appraisal of an action. Responsibility as accountability is the assigning of some consequence, such as a burden, for the action (p.78). For some theorists, attributability is a precondition to accountability. Zheng shows how attributability and accountability converge in explaining criminal responsibility: attributability reflects moral responsibility and accountability reflects the political question of the distribution of duties and burdens across the community via criminally enforced obligations and punishment (p.80). According to Zheng, justificatory accounts of criminal law may be classed as attributability-first or as accountability-first accounts (p.77). Attributability-first accounts are more concerned to respond to the criminal law's person as a moral agent; they have a metaphysical understanding of the person. Accountability-first theories, which are less prominent than attributability-first accounts, are concerned with the person taking their place in the community's network of duties; these theories have a political conception of the person. It would seem that accountability-first theories would be more comfortable with fictional constructs of the person than attributability-first theories. But not always. Thorburn's essay, for instance, could be read as an accountability-first theory that needs the criminal law's person to (really) be something they not always are. This being just one connecting thought prompted by this fascinating book of individually excellent criminal law theory essays which collectively amount to something even greater than their sum.

查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
《刑法的人》C.Lernestedt, M.Matravers(编),牛津:Hart. 2022。216页。£85.00 (hbk)。ISBN: 9781509923748
马特·马特拉弗斯在《刑法的各种人》中,使用事前和事后的框架来考察刑法对人的概念。像Hamdorf和其他几位《刑法的人》的撰稿人一样,Matravers实际上敦促刑法比目前的案件更准确地描绘真实的人。没有人要求刑法加倍打击它的虚构。尽管如此,Robin Zheng(“刑法中的归因性和问责性”)提出了一个丰富的分析区分,除其他外,可以帮助当前刑法的合理化。作为归因的责任仅仅是对一个行为的评估。作为责任的责任是为行动指定某种后果,例如负担(临78)。对于一些理论家来说,归因性是问责制的先决条件。郑展示了归因性和问责性如何在解释刑事责任时趋于一致:归因性反映了道德责任,而问责性反映了通过刑事强制义务和惩罚在整个社会中分配责任和负担的政治问题(第80页)。根据郑的观点,刑法的正当性解释可以分为归因优先和问责优先两类(第77页)。归因优先说更关注回应刑法的人作为道德行为人;他们对人有一种形而上学的理解。问责优先理论,没有归因优先理论那么突出,它关注的是在社区责任网络中占据自己位置的人;这些理论都有关于人的政治概念。与归因优先理论相比,问责优先理论似乎更适合虚构的人物结构。但并非总是如此。例如,索伯恩的文章可以被解读为一种责任至上的理论,它需要刑法的人(真的)成为他们并不总是如此的东西。这仅仅是这本引人入胜的书所激发的一个联系的想法,这本书中包含了个别优秀的刑法理论论文,这些论文的总和甚至大于它们的总和。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
2.30
自引率
0.00%
发文量
41
期刊介绍: The Howard Journal of Crime and Justice is an international peer-reviewed journal committed to publishing high quality theory, research and debate on all aspects of the relationship between crime and justice across the globe. It is a leading forum for conversation between academic theory and research and the cultures, policies and practices of the range of institutions concerned with harm, security and justice.
期刊最新文献
Issue Information Colonialism and its aftermaths in prisons in Guyana: An introduction The Palgrave handbook of global rehabilitation in criminal justice By M. Vanstone, P. Priestley (Ed.), Cham, Switzerland: Palgrave Macmillan. 2022. pp. 722. £199.99 (hbk). £199.99 (pbk). ISBN: 9783031143748 Sex as work: Decriminalisation and the management of brothels in New Zealand By C. Weinhold, Cham, Switzerland: Palgrave Macmillan. 2022. pp. 275. £99.99 (hbk). £99.99 (pbk). ISBN: 9783031192593 Doing transdisciplinary research in Guyana's prisons
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1