Obligation as Weakest Permission: a strongly Complete Axiomatization
F. Putte
求助PDF
{"title":"Obligation as Weakest Permission: a strongly Complete Axiomatization","authors":"F. Putte","doi":"10.1017/S1755020316000034","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"In (Anglberger et al., 2015, Section 4.1), a deontic logic is proposed which explicates the idea that a formula φ is obligatory if and only if it is (semantically speaking) the weakest permission. We give a sound and strongly complete, Hilbert style axiomatization for this logic. As a corollary, it is compact, contradicting earlier claims from Anglberger et al. (2015). In addition, we prove that our axiomatization is equivalent to Anglberger et al.’s infinitary proof system, and show that our results are robust w.r.t. certain changes in the underlying semantics. §1. Intro. In Roy et al. (2014, 2012) and Anglberger et al. (2015), a logic is developed for “obligation as weakest permission”.1 The semantics proposed in Anglberger et al. (2015) is meant to capture the deontic aspects of reasoning in strategic games, where we speak about properties of the best actions available to a given agent. Whereas usually in formal models of such games, actions and/or agents are modeled explicitly at the object level, the present logic only speaks about action tokens (which correspond to states in a Kripke-model) and action types (sets of action tokens). Let us explain this briefly—we refer to the cited works for a more elaborate discussion. Consider a situation in which an agent can choose from a number of distinct action tokens, where at least some of these are optimal. Whereas the agent is permitted to perform one of those optimal action tokens, his sole obligation (if there is one at all – mind this important caveat) is to perform one of the optimal action tokens. This means that the deontic operators O and P can be read as follows, where φ refers to an arbitrary action type: Oφ: “φ is the (only) action type that is obligatory”, or more elaborately: “an action token is optimal if and only if it is of type φ” Pφ: “if an action is of type φ, then it is optimal” Anglberger et al. moreover introduce an alethic modality , which they interpret as a universal modality. φ thus means that all available action tokens are of type φ. They then propose what they call a “minimal logic” 5HD for these three operators. However, as they argue, 5HD only captures one half of the notion of “obligation as weakest permission”. That is, if φ is obligatory, then the logic stipulates that φ is the weakest permitted action type. The converse does not hold: something can be the weakest permitted action type without being obligatory. Received: September 30, 2015. 1 In more recent work Dong and Roy (2015); Van De Putte (2015), the logic is compared to other constructions in deontic logic. c © Association for Symbolic Logic, 2016 370 doi:10.1017/S1755020316000034 OBLIGATION AS WEAKEST PERMISSION 371 In the fourth section of Anglberger et al. (2015), a brief discussion of this converse direction is given, and it is shown how this translates to the semantics of 5HD. Let us call the resulting logic 5HD∗; it will be defined in Section 2. It is argued in Anglberger et al. (2015) that 5HD∗ is not compact, and a proof system with an infinitary rule (R-Conv) is shown to be (weakly) sound and complete w.r.t. 5HD∗. The main aim of the present paper is to give a sound and strongly complete, Hilbert-style axiomatization for 5HD∗ (Section 3). As a corollary, this consequence relation is compact, contradicting the claims mentioned in the previous paragraph. We prove in addition that the proof system proposed by Anglberger et al. is equivalent to 5HD∗ (Section 4). Finally, we show that these results can be generalized to other, similar logics for “obligation as weakest permission” (Section 5). §2. Definitions. This section is meant to fix notation; it contains no new material. See Anglberger et al. (2015) for the original definitions and notation. We work with a modal propositional language, obtained by closing the set of propositional letters S = {p1, p2, . . .} and ⊥, under boolean connectives ¬,∨,∧,⊃,≡ and the unary operators , O, P . Call the resulting set of formulas W . We treat only ¬,∨,⊥, O, P, as primitive; ∧,⊃,≡ are defined in the usual way. In the remainder, let the metavariables φ,ψ, . . . range over arbitrary members of W and , , . . . over arbitrary subsets of W . DEFINITION 2.1. A strict deontic frame F is a quadruple 〈W, R , n P , nO〉, where W is a non-empty set (the domain of F), R = W × W , and n P : W → ℘(℘(W )) and nO : W → ℘(℘(W )) satisfy the following conditions (OR) If X ∪ Y ∈ n P (w), then X ∈ n P (w) and Y ∈ n P (w) (WP) If X ∈ nO(w) and Y ∈ n P (w), then Y ⊆ X (OP) If X ∈ nO(w) then X ∈ n P (w) (OC) If X ∈ nO(w), then X = ∅ (Conv) If X ∈ n P (w) and for all Y ∈ n P (w), Y ⊆ X, then X ∈ nO(w) If a frame obeys all the above conditions except (possibly) (Conv), it is just a deontic frame. A (strict) deontic model is a (strict) deontic frame F together with a valuation v that maps every propositional atom to a subset of the domain of F. DEFINITION 2.2. Let M = 〈W, R , nO , n P , v〉 be a (strict) deontic model and w ∈ W . M, w | ⊥ M, w | p iff w ∈ v(p) M, w | ¬φ iff M, w | φ M, w | φ ∨ ψ iff M, w | φ or M, w | ψ M, w | φ iff M, w′ | φ for all w′ ∈ R (w) M, w | Oφ iff ‖φ‖M ∈ nO(w) M, w | Pφ iff ‖φ‖M ∈ n P (w), where ‖φ‖M = {u ∈ W | M, u | φ}. DEFINITION 2.3. 5HD∗ φ iff for all strict deontic models M: if M, w | ψ for all ψ ∈ , then M, w | φ. 372 FREDERIK VAN DE PUTTE §3. Axiomatization of 5HD∗. DEFINITION 3.1. The set of 5HD∗-theorems is the closure of the set of all instances of the following axiom schemas (CL) All tautologies of classical propositional logic (S5 ) S5 for (EQO) (φ ≡ ψ) ⊃ (Oφ ≡ Oψ) (EQP ) (φ ≡ ψ) ⊃ (Pφ ≡ Pψ) (FCP) P(ψ ∨ φ) ⊃ (Pψ ∧ Pφ) (Ought-Perm) Oφ ⊃ Pφ (Ought-Can) Oφ ⊃ φ (Weakest-Perm) Oφ ⊃ (Pψ ⊃ (ψ ⊃ φ)) (Taut-Perm) P ⊃ O under the following rules:","PeriodicalId":49628,"journal":{"name":"Review of Symbolic Logic","volume":"520 1","pages":"370-379"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9000,"publicationDate":"2016-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Review of Symbolic Logic","FirstCategoryId":"100","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S1755020316000034","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"LOGIC","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
引用
批量引用
Abstract
In (Anglberger et al., 2015, Section 4.1), a deontic logic is proposed which explicates the idea that a formula φ is obligatory if and only if it is (semantically speaking) the weakest permission. We give a sound and strongly complete, Hilbert style axiomatization for this logic. As a corollary, it is compact, contradicting earlier claims from Anglberger et al. (2015). In addition, we prove that our axiomatization is equivalent to Anglberger et al.’s infinitary proof system, and show that our results are robust w.r.t. certain changes in the underlying semantics. §1. Intro. In Roy et al. (2014, 2012) and Anglberger et al. (2015), a logic is developed for “obligation as weakest permission”.1 The semantics proposed in Anglberger et al. (2015) is meant to capture the deontic aspects of reasoning in strategic games, where we speak about properties of the best actions available to a given agent. Whereas usually in formal models of such games, actions and/or agents are modeled explicitly at the object level, the present logic only speaks about action tokens (which correspond to states in a Kripke-model) and action types (sets of action tokens). Let us explain this briefly—we refer to the cited works for a more elaborate discussion. Consider a situation in which an agent can choose from a number of distinct action tokens, where at least some of these are optimal. Whereas the agent is permitted to perform one of those optimal action tokens, his sole obligation (if there is one at all – mind this important caveat) is to perform one of the optimal action tokens. This means that the deontic operators O and P can be read as follows, where φ refers to an arbitrary action type: Oφ: “φ is the (only) action type that is obligatory”, or more elaborately: “an action token is optimal if and only if it is of type φ” Pφ: “if an action is of type φ, then it is optimal” Anglberger et al. moreover introduce an alethic modality , which they interpret as a universal modality. φ thus means that all available action tokens are of type φ. They then propose what they call a “minimal logic” 5HD for these three operators. However, as they argue, 5HD only captures one half of the notion of “obligation as weakest permission”. That is, if φ is obligatory, then the logic stipulates that φ is the weakest permitted action type. The converse does not hold: something can be the weakest permitted action type without being obligatory. Received: September 30, 2015. 1 In more recent work Dong and Roy (2015); Van De Putte (2015), the logic is compared to other constructions in deontic logic. c © Association for Symbolic Logic, 2016 370 doi:10.1017/S1755020316000034 OBLIGATION AS WEAKEST PERMISSION 371 In the fourth section of Anglberger et al. (2015), a brief discussion of this converse direction is given, and it is shown how this translates to the semantics of 5HD. Let us call the resulting logic 5HD∗; it will be defined in Section 2. It is argued in Anglberger et al. (2015) that 5HD∗ is not compact, and a proof system with an infinitary rule (R-Conv) is shown to be (weakly) sound and complete w.r.t. 5HD∗. The main aim of the present paper is to give a sound and strongly complete, Hilbert-style axiomatization for 5HD∗ (Section 3). As a corollary, this consequence relation is compact, contradicting the claims mentioned in the previous paragraph. We prove in addition that the proof system proposed by Anglberger et al. is equivalent to 5HD∗ (Section 4). Finally, we show that these results can be generalized to other, similar logics for “obligation as weakest permission” (Section 5). §2. Definitions. This section is meant to fix notation; it contains no new material. See Anglberger et al. (2015) for the original definitions and notation. We work with a modal propositional language, obtained by closing the set of propositional letters S = {p1, p2, . . .} and ⊥, under boolean connectives ¬,∨,∧,⊃,≡ and the unary operators , O, P . Call the resulting set of formulas W . We treat only ¬,∨,⊥, O, P, as primitive; ∧,⊃,≡ are defined in the usual way. In the remainder, let the metavariables φ,ψ, . . . range over arbitrary members of W and , , . . . over arbitrary subsets of W . DEFINITION 2.1. A strict deontic frame F is a quadruple 〈W, R , n P , nO〉, where W is a non-empty set (the domain of F), R = W × W , and n P : W → ℘(℘(W )) and nO : W → ℘(℘(W )) satisfy the following conditions (OR) If X ∪ Y ∈ n P (w), then X ∈ n P (w) and Y ∈ n P (w) (WP) If X ∈ nO(w) and Y ∈ n P (w), then Y ⊆ X (OP) If X ∈ nO(w) then X ∈ n P (w) (OC) If X ∈ nO(w), then X = ∅ (Conv) If X ∈ n P (w) and for all Y ∈ n P (w), Y ⊆ X, then X ∈ nO(w) If a frame obeys all the above conditions except (possibly) (Conv), it is just a deontic frame. A (strict) deontic model is a (strict) deontic frame F together with a valuation v that maps every propositional atom to a subset of the domain of F. DEFINITION 2.2. Let M = 〈W, R , nO , n P , v〉 be a (strict) deontic model and w ∈ W . M, w | ⊥ M, w | p iff w ∈ v(p) M, w | ¬φ iff M, w | φ M, w | φ ∨ ψ iff M, w | φ or M, w | ψ M, w | φ iff M, w′ | φ for all w′ ∈ R (w) M, w | Oφ iff ‖φ‖M ∈ nO(w) M, w | Pφ iff ‖φ‖M ∈ n P (w), where ‖φ‖M = {u ∈ W | M, u | φ}. DEFINITION 2.3. 5HD∗ φ iff for all strict deontic models M: if M, w | ψ for all ψ ∈ , then M, w | φ. 372 FREDERIK VAN DE PUTTE §3. Axiomatization of 5HD∗. DEFINITION 3.1. The set of 5HD∗-theorems is the closure of the set of all instances of the following axiom schemas (CL) All tautologies of classical propositional logic (S5 ) S5 for (EQO) (φ ≡ ψ) ⊃ (Oφ ≡ Oψ) (EQP ) (φ ≡ ψ) ⊃ (Pφ ≡ Pψ) (FCP) P(ψ ∨ φ) ⊃ (Pψ ∧ Pφ) (Ought-Perm) Oφ ⊃ Pφ (Ought-Can) Oφ ⊃ φ (Weakest-Perm) Oφ ⊃ (Pψ ⊃ (ψ ⊃ φ)) (Taut-Perm) P ⊃ O under the following rules:
义务作为最弱许可:一个强完全公理化
在(Anglberger et al., 2015, Section 4.1)中,提出了一个道义逻辑,它解释了公式φ是强制性的,当且仅当它(从语义上讲)是最弱的许可。对于这个逻辑,我们给出了一个健全的、强完备的、希尔伯特式的公理化。作为推论,它是紧凑的,与Anglberger等人(2015)的早期主张相矛盾。此外,我们证明了我们的公理化等价于Anglberger等人的无限证明系统,并证明了我们的结果在底层语义的某些变化下是鲁棒的。§1。介绍。在Roy等人(2014,2012)和Anglberger等人(2015)中,开发了“义务作为最弱许可”的逻辑Anglberger等人(2015)提出的语义旨在捕捉战略博弈中推理的道义方面,我们在其中谈论给定代理可用的最佳行为的属性。尽管在这类游戏的正式模型中,行动和/或代理通常是在对象层面上明确建模的,但目前的逻辑只涉及行动标记(对应于kripke模型中的状态)和行动类型(行动标记集)。让我们简要地解释一下——我们参考引用的作品进行更详细的讨论。考虑这样一种情况:代理可以从许多不同的操作令牌中进行选择,其中至少有一些是最优的。尽管代理被允许执行其中一个最优动作令牌,但他唯一的义务(如果有的话——记住这个重要的警告)是执行其中一个最优动作令牌。这意味着义务算子O和P可以这样解读,其中φ指的是任意的动作类型:Oφ:“φ是(唯一)强制性的动作类型”,或者更详细地说:“一个动作标记当且仅当它是φ类型时是最优的”Pφ:“如果一个动作是φ类型,那么它是最优的”Anglberger等人进一步引入了一个真性模态,他们将其解释为一个普遍模态。因此φ意味着所有可用的动作令牌都是φ类型的。然后,他们为这三家运营商提出了他们所谓的“最小逻辑”5HD。然而,正如他们所言,5HD只体现了“义务即最弱许可”概念的一半。也就是说,如果φ是强制性的,那么逻辑规定φ是允许的最弱动作类型。反过来不持有:可以允许的最低动作类型没有必修课。收稿日期:2015年9月30日。1在最近的研究中,Dong和Roy (2015);Van De Putte(2015),将逻辑与道义逻辑中的其他结构进行了比较。c©Association for Symbolic Logic, 2016 370 doi:10.1017/S1755020316000034 OBLIGATION AS weak PERMISSION 371在Anglberger等人(2015)的第四部分中,给出了对这个反向方向的简要讨论,并展示了如何将其转化为5HD的语义。让我们调用生成的逻辑5 hd∗;它将在第2节中定义。Anglberger等人(2015)认为5HD∗不是紧致的,并且具有无限规则(R-Conv)的证明系统被证明是(弱)健全和完备的。本文的主要目的是给出5HD *的一个健全且强完备的希尔伯特式公理化(第3节)。作为一个推论,这个推论关系是紧凑的,与前一段中提到的主张相矛盾。此外,我们证明Anglberger等人提出的证明系统等价于5HD *(第4节)。最后,我们证明这些结果可以推广到其他类似的“义务作为最弱许可”的逻辑(第5节)。§2。定义。本节的目的是修复符号;它不含新材料。看到Anglberger et al。(2015)的原始定义和符号。我们使用一个模态命题语言,它是通过闭合命题字母S = {p1, p2,…}和⊥的集合,在布尔连接¬,∨,∧,、≡和一元算子O, P下得到的。将生成的公式集称为W。我们对待¬,∨、⊥O, P,原始;∧,、,≡都是用通常的方式定义的。在剩余部分中,设元变量φ,ψ,…值域在W和,,…的任意成员上。W的任意子集。定义2.1。一个严格的约束性框架F是一个四元组< W, R, n P, nO >,其中W是一个非空集合(F的定义域),R = W × W, n P: W→P (P (W))和nO:W→℘(℘(W)具备下列条件(或)如果X∪Y∈n P (W),那么X∈n P (W)和Y∈n P (W) (WP)如果X∈(W)和Y∈n P (W),然后Y⊆X (OP)如果没有∈(W),那么X∈n P (W) (OC)如果X∈(W),那么X =∅(Conv)如果X∈n P (W)和Y∈n P (W), Y⊆X, X∈(W)如果一个框架遵循上述所有条件除了(可能)(Conv),它只是一个道义框架。(严格)道义模型是一个(严格)道义框架F和一个赋值v,该赋值v将每个命题原子映射到F的定义域的一个子集。设M = < W, R, nO, n P, v >是一个(严格)道义模型,且W∈W。 M, w |⊥M, w | p iff w∈v (p) M, w |¬φ敌我识别M, w |φM, w |φ∨ψ敌我识别M, w |φ或M, w |ψM, w |φ敌我识别M, w ' |φ为所有w '∈R (w) M, w | Oφ敌我识别为φ为M∈(w)米,w | pφ敌我识别为φ为M∈n p (w),在为φ为M = {u∈w | M u |φ}。定义2.3。5HD∗φ iff对于所有严格的义务模型M:如果M, w | ψ对于所有ψ∈,则M, w | φ。372弗雷德里克·范德普特§3。5HD *的公理化。定义3.1。5HD∗-定理的集合是下列公理模式的所有实例集合的闭包:经典命题逻辑(S5) S5对于(EQO) (φ≡ψ)、(EQP) (φ≡ψ)、(Pφ≡Pψ) (FCP) P(ψ∨φ)、(Pψ∧Pφ)(应该- perm) Oφ、Pφ(应该-可以)Oφ、φ(最弱- perm) Oφ、(Pψ、(ψ、φ)) (tautperm) P、O、O、O、O、O、(Pψ、φ)的所有重言式:
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。