Reviewability and the 'Law of Rules': An Essay in Honor of Justice Scalia

IF 1 3区 社会学 Q2 LAW Notre Dame Law Review Pub Date : 2017-07-17 DOI:10.2139/SSRN.3004071
Adrian Vermeule
{"title":"Reviewability and the 'Law of Rules': An Essay in Honor of Justice Scalia","authors":"Adrian Vermeule","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3004071","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"INTRODUCTION In Washington v. Trump, (1) the Ninth Circuit decision on the Administration's executive order on immigration, (2) a critical moment occurred when the panel had to explain why the order was reviewable at all. Precedents like Kleindienst v. Mandel (3) had said that \"when the Executive exercises [immigration authority] on the basis of a facially legitimate and bona fide reason, the courts will [not] look behind the exercise of that discretion.\" (4) The panel's response was to invoke an important distinction between the reviewability of general rules, on the one hand, and the reviewability of specific applications, on the other: [T]he Mandel standard applies to lawsuits challenging an executive branch official's decision to issue or deny an individual visa based on the application of a congressionally enumerated standard to the particular facts presented by that visa application. The present case, by contrast, is not about the application of a specifically enumerated congressional policy to the particular facts presented in an individual visa application. Rather, the States are challenging the President's promulgation of sweeping immigration policy. Such exercises of policymaking authority at the highest levels of the political branches are plainly not subject to the Mandel standard. (5) As we will see, this conception of reviewability (6)--keyed to a distinction between general policies or rules and specific applications, with the former subject to review even if the latter would not be--is one that Justice Scalia wrestled with throughout his reviewability jurisprudence. Yet it is more or less directly the opposite of Justice Scalia's own conception. Justice Scalia developed a consistent approach to questions of reviewability: roughly, the idea that \"general programs\" and \"general policies\" are to be excluded from judicial review, and even general and legally binding agency rules may or may not be reviewable before enforcement. On this approach, the proper business of courts is to review specific applications of agency rules to particular parties. Notice that there are actually three possible subjects of review in play here: nonbinding policies and rules (such as \"interpretive\" rules); binding general rules (\"legislative rules\"); and applications. More on this shortly. For now, the focus is on the distinction between review of general and specific agency action, whether that action is embodied in a legally binding rule or in a nonbinding policy. The approach featured in Washington v. Trump, by contrast, was propounded in several opinions by Justice John Paul Stevens. On that view, agencies should be more afforded more, not less, discretion to apply policies or rules in particular cases, whereas the proper business of the judiciary is to review the general legality of overall programs, policies, and rules. The Scalia view and the Stevens view obviously differ on the proper role of courts in an overall system of administrative law. For Justice Stevens, the role of courts is to say what the general rules of law are, leaving agencies (reasonable) discretion in application. For Justice Scalia, the role of courts is to decide cases, reviewing the legality of rules only insofar as necessary to that function--as a byproduct of deciding cases. Furthermore, the two approaches differ as to the relationship between reviewability and the idea--perhaps Justice Scalia's most famous contribution to legal theory--that the rule of law is best understood as \"a law of rules.\" (7) On the Stevens view, reviewability should attempt to ensure that courts review the overall legality of programs and policies to keep the administrative state within the broad bounds of the rule of law. (8) On that view, the \"rule of law\" is a \"law of rules\" in the sense that judicial power to say what the law is entails a power to examine the legality of general rules. On the Scalia view, by contrast, the rule of law is a law of rules in a quite different sense. …","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0000,"publicationDate":"2017-07-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Notre Dame Law Review","FirstCategoryId":"90","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3004071","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q2","JCRName":"LAW","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

INTRODUCTION In Washington v. Trump, (1) the Ninth Circuit decision on the Administration's executive order on immigration, (2) a critical moment occurred when the panel had to explain why the order was reviewable at all. Precedents like Kleindienst v. Mandel (3) had said that "when the Executive exercises [immigration authority] on the basis of a facially legitimate and bona fide reason, the courts will [not] look behind the exercise of that discretion." (4) The panel's response was to invoke an important distinction between the reviewability of general rules, on the one hand, and the reviewability of specific applications, on the other: [T]he Mandel standard applies to lawsuits challenging an executive branch official's decision to issue or deny an individual visa based on the application of a congressionally enumerated standard to the particular facts presented by that visa application. The present case, by contrast, is not about the application of a specifically enumerated congressional policy to the particular facts presented in an individual visa application. Rather, the States are challenging the President's promulgation of sweeping immigration policy. Such exercises of policymaking authority at the highest levels of the political branches are plainly not subject to the Mandel standard. (5) As we will see, this conception of reviewability (6)--keyed to a distinction between general policies or rules and specific applications, with the former subject to review even if the latter would not be--is one that Justice Scalia wrestled with throughout his reviewability jurisprudence. Yet it is more or less directly the opposite of Justice Scalia's own conception. Justice Scalia developed a consistent approach to questions of reviewability: roughly, the idea that "general programs" and "general policies" are to be excluded from judicial review, and even general and legally binding agency rules may or may not be reviewable before enforcement. On this approach, the proper business of courts is to review specific applications of agency rules to particular parties. Notice that there are actually three possible subjects of review in play here: nonbinding policies and rules (such as "interpretive" rules); binding general rules ("legislative rules"); and applications. More on this shortly. For now, the focus is on the distinction between review of general and specific agency action, whether that action is embodied in a legally binding rule or in a nonbinding policy. The approach featured in Washington v. Trump, by contrast, was propounded in several opinions by Justice John Paul Stevens. On that view, agencies should be more afforded more, not less, discretion to apply policies or rules in particular cases, whereas the proper business of the judiciary is to review the general legality of overall programs, policies, and rules. The Scalia view and the Stevens view obviously differ on the proper role of courts in an overall system of administrative law. For Justice Stevens, the role of courts is to say what the general rules of law are, leaving agencies (reasonable) discretion in application. For Justice Scalia, the role of courts is to decide cases, reviewing the legality of rules only insofar as necessary to that function--as a byproduct of deciding cases. Furthermore, the two approaches differ as to the relationship between reviewability and the idea--perhaps Justice Scalia's most famous contribution to legal theory--that the rule of law is best understood as "a law of rules." (7) On the Stevens view, reviewability should attempt to ensure that courts review the overall legality of programs and policies to keep the administrative state within the broad bounds of the rule of law. (8) On that view, the "rule of law" is a "law of rules" in the sense that judicial power to say what the law is entails a power to examine the legality of general rules. On the Scalia view, by contrast, the rule of law is a law of rules in a quite different sense. …
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
可复审性与“规则之法”:一篇向斯卡利亚大法官致敬的文章
在华盛顿诉特朗普案中,(1)第九巡回法院对政府移民行政命令的裁决,(2)当小组必须解释为什么该命令是可审查的时候,出现了一个关键时刻。克莱因登斯特诉曼德尔案(Kleindienst v. Mandel)等先例曾说过,“当行政部门基于表面上合法和善意的理由行使[移民权力]时,法院将[不]追究这种自由裁量权的行使。”(4)专家组的回应是援引一般规则的可审查性与具体申请的可审查性之间的重要区别:曼德尔标准适用于挑战行政部门官员根据国会列举的标准对该签证申请所提出的特定事实签发或拒绝个人签证的决定的诉讼。相比之下,本案的问题不是将具体列举的国会政策适用于个别签证申请中提出的具体事实。相反,各州正在挑战总统颁布的全面移民政策。在政治部门的最高层行使决策权显然不受曼德尔标准的约束。(5)正如我们将看到的,可复审性的概念(6)——关键在于一般政策或规则与具体应用之间的区别,即使后者不受审查,前者也要接受审查——是斯卡利亚大法官在其可复审性法理学中一直在努力解决的问题。然而,这或多或少与斯卡利亚大法官自己的观点完全相反。斯卡利亚大法官对可审查性问题提出了一种一致的方法:粗略地说,“一般项目”和“一般政策”应排除在司法审查之外,甚至一般和具有法律约束力的机构规则在执行前可能可审查,也可能不可审查。根据这种方法,法院的适当工作是审查机构规则对特定当事人的具体适用。请注意,这里实际上有三种可能的审查主题:非约束性策略和规则(例如“解释性”规则);有约束力的一般规则(“立法规则”);和应用程序。稍后会详细介绍。目前,重点是区分对一般和具体机构行动的审查,无论这种行动是体现在具有法律约束力的规则中还是体现在不具有法律约束力的政策中。相比之下,在华盛顿诉特朗普案中,大法官约翰·保罗·史蒂文斯(John Paul Stevens)在几份意见中提出了这种做法。根据这一观点,各机构应该被赋予更多而不是更少的自由裁量权,以便在特定情况下适用政策或规则,而司法机构的正当业务是审查总体计划、政策和规则的一般合法性。斯卡利亚的观点和史蒂文斯的观点在法院在整个行政法体系中的适当作用问题上明显不同。对于史蒂文斯大法官来说,法院的作用是说明一般法律规则是什么,让机构(合理的)自由裁量权在应用中。对斯卡利亚大法官来说,法院的作用是裁决案件,只有在对这一职能有必要的情况下才审查规则的合法性——这是裁决案件的副产品。此外,这两种方法在可复审性与“法治最好被理解为一种规则的法律”这一观点(也许是斯卡利亚大法官对法律理论最著名的贡献)之间的关系上存在差异。(7)根据史蒂文斯的观点,可审查性应试图确保法院审查项目和政策的整体合法性,以使行政国家保持在法治的广泛范围内。(8)根据这种观点,“法治”是一种“规则之法”,在这个意义上说,说什么是法律的司法权意味着审查一般规则合法性的权力。相反,在斯卡利亚看来,法治是一种完全不同意义上的规则之法。...
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
1.20
自引率
11.10%
发文量
0
期刊介绍: In 1925, a group of eager and idealistic students founded the Notre Dame Lawyer. Its name was changed in 1982 to the Notre Dame Law Review, but all generations have remained committed to the original founders’ vision of a law review “synonymous with respect for law, and jealous of any unjust attacks upon it.” Today, the Law Review maintains its tradition of excellence, and its membership includes some of the most able and distinguished judges, professors, and practitioners in the country. Entirely student edited, the Law Review offers its members an invaluable occasion for training in precise analysis of legal problems and in clear and cogent presentation of legal issues.
期刊最新文献
Préface Does Docket Size Matter? Revisiting Empirical Accounts of the Supreme Court's Incredibly Shrinking Docket Prior Art in the District Court Acknowledgments The Juggler of Notre Dame and the Medievalizing of Modernity. Volume 6: War and Peace, Sex and Violence
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1