In Defense of Clutter

IF 0.5 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Ergo-An Open Access Journal of Philosophy Pub Date : 2022-12-28 DOI:10.3998/ergo.2257
Brendan Balcerak Jackson, D. Didomenico, Kenji Lota
{"title":"In Defense of Clutter","authors":"Brendan Balcerak Jackson, D. Didomenico, Kenji Lota","doi":"10.3998/ergo.2257","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Gilbert Harman’s famous principle of Clutter Avoidance commands that “one should not clutter one’s mind with trivialities” (1986: 12). Harman appeals to this principle in the course of his well-known argument against logical closure, the view that one ought to believe all the logical consequences of one’s beliefs. Harman’s rationale for the principle is that one’s cognitive resources are limited, and ought to be used wisely; one ought not waste them by forming and maintaining beliefs that are in some sense trivial. Many epistemologists have been inclined to accept Harman’s principle, or something like it.1 This is significant, because the principle appears to have significant implications for our overall picture of epistemic normativity. Jane Friedman has recently argued that one potential implication is that there are no genuine purely evidential norms on belief revision—that “evidence alone doesn’t demand belief, and it can’t even, on its own, permit or justify belief” (2018: 576). Rather, genuine norms of belief revision must “combine considerations about one’s interests with more traditional epistemic sorts of considerations in issuing normative verdicts” (2018: 576).2 Even if we insist on keeping purely evidential norms, Friedman argues, the need to avoid clutter forces us to acknowledge that the verdicts of such norms can be overridden by consideration of our interests: even if one’s evidence requires (or permits) one to believe that p in a certain situation, it might still be the case that one is in fact not permitted to believe that p because doing so would violate the clutter avoidance principle. Either way, Friedman argues, accepting the principle leads to a picture of epistemic normativity that is highly “interest-driven,” a picture according to which our practical interests have a significant role to play.","PeriodicalId":51882,"journal":{"name":"Ergo-An Open Access Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5000,"publicationDate":"2022-12-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"1","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Ergo-An Open Access Journal of Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.2257","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1

Abstract

Gilbert Harman’s famous principle of Clutter Avoidance commands that “one should not clutter one’s mind with trivialities” (1986: 12). Harman appeals to this principle in the course of his well-known argument against logical closure, the view that one ought to believe all the logical consequences of one’s beliefs. Harman’s rationale for the principle is that one’s cognitive resources are limited, and ought to be used wisely; one ought not waste them by forming and maintaining beliefs that are in some sense trivial. Many epistemologists have been inclined to accept Harman’s principle, or something like it.1 This is significant, because the principle appears to have significant implications for our overall picture of epistemic normativity. Jane Friedman has recently argued that one potential implication is that there are no genuine purely evidential norms on belief revision—that “evidence alone doesn’t demand belief, and it can’t even, on its own, permit or justify belief” (2018: 576). Rather, genuine norms of belief revision must “combine considerations about one’s interests with more traditional epistemic sorts of considerations in issuing normative verdicts” (2018: 576).2 Even if we insist on keeping purely evidential norms, Friedman argues, the need to avoid clutter forces us to acknowledge that the verdicts of such norms can be overridden by consideration of our interests: even if one’s evidence requires (or permits) one to believe that p in a certain situation, it might still be the case that one is in fact not permitted to believe that p because doing so would violate the clutter avoidance principle. Either way, Friedman argues, accepting the principle leads to a picture of epistemic normativity that is highly “interest-driven,” a picture according to which our practical interests have a significant role to play.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
为杂乱辩护
吉尔伯特·哈曼(Gilbert Harman)著名的“避免混乱”原则要求“一个人不应该让琐碎的事情使自己的头脑混乱”(1986:12)。哈曼在他著名的反对逻辑闭合的论证中诉诸了这个原则,他认为一个人应该相信自己信仰的所有逻辑结果。哈曼对这一原则的基本原理是,一个人的认知资源是有限的,应该明智地使用;一个人不应该把时间浪费在形成和维持某种意义上微不足道的信念上。许多认识论家都倾向于接受哈曼的原理,或类似的原理这是很重要的,因为这个原则似乎对我们认知规范性的整体图景有重要的影响。简·弗里德曼(Jane Friedman)最近认为,一个潜在的含义是,在信念修正方面,不存在真正的纯证据规范——“证据本身并不要求信仰,它甚至不能单独允许或证明信仰”(2018:576)。相反,信仰修正的真正规范必须“在发布规范性裁决时,将对个人利益的考虑与更传统的认知类型的考虑结合起来”(2018:576)弗里德曼认为,即使我们坚持保持纯粹的证据规范,避免混乱的需要也会迫使我们承认,这些规范的结论可以被考虑到我们的利益所推翻:即使一个人的证据要求(或允许)一个人在某种情况下相信p,但实际上仍然可能不允许一个人相信p,因为这样做会违反混乱避免原则。弗里德曼认为,无论哪种方式,接受这一原则都会导致一幅高度“利益驱动”的认知规范性图景,在这幅图景中,我们的实际利益扮演着重要的角色。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
审稿时长
26 weeks
期刊最新文献
The Vagaries of References Advice for Analytic Naturalists Against Purity Hypocrisy in Politics Nature, Consciousness, and Metaphysics in Merleau-Ponty’s Early Thought
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1