C. Koster, B. Lust, G. Hermon, J. Kornfilt, Suzanne Flynn, S. Kapur, Barbier, K Boser, C. Foley, ZN delPrado, EJ Rubin, L Santelman, J. Toribio
{"title":"代词习得问题","authors":"C. Koster, B. Lust, G. Hermon, J. Kornfilt, Suzanne Flynn, S. Kapur, Barbier, K Boser, C. Foley, ZN delPrado, EJ Rubin, L Santelman, J. Toribio","doi":"10.4324/9781315789200-9","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Experimental studies have often shown that children have more problems with pronouns than was originally expected. One recent explanation of the discrepancy between empirical results and linguistic theory is that the Binding Theory is in need of reformulation to include only bound variable interpretations of pronominals as well as reflexives, with intended coreference relegated to the domain of pragmatics. The Dutch studies presented here explore children’s sensitivity to bound variable interpretations of reflexives and pronominals by investigating their understanding of VP-deletion sentences. The results show errors with pronominals that do not support the reformulated version of the Binding Theory as a better description of children’s acquisition problems. (DRAFT: non-final version!!) PROBLEMS WITH PRONOUN ACQUISITION 1. The traditional Binding Theory Knowledge of anaphora in relation to reflexives and pronominals is traditionally summed up in two of the principles of the Binding Theory (Chomsky, 1981): Principle A a bound anaphor, like the reflexive himself, must be bound in its governing category, and Principle B a free anaphor, like the pronominal him, must not be bound in its governing category. Based on the principles and parameters view of language acquisition, it has been proposed that the principles of the Binding Theory should have an innate basis, or be part of what is often called Universal Grammar. Children’s knowledge of the Binding Theory principles has been quite extensively investigated during the last decade, but the empirical evidence does not give as straightforward a picture as was originally expected. Children’s performance on anaphora tasks is more of a mixed success than had been predicted. Correct understanding of anaphoric reference with pronominals and reflexives is not instantaneously visible in very young children; but it does improve over time. Developmental patterns for sentences with reflexives and pronominals also do not necessarily run parallel. One of the more consistent results is that children relatively quickly and easily come to understand bound anaphors, such as reflexives. In the case of pronominals, development is usually (but not always) slow, often stagnating and problematic for many years, even up into middle childhood. In some experimental studies, children seem to be interpreting pronouns as if they were reflexives, and this is specifically the one error that they should not be making. To make the picture even more confusing, there are also situations in which children perform equally well on sentences with pronominals and reflexives, or even better on sentences with pronominals (Kaufman, 1992). If both Binding Theory principles are presumed to be part of innate linguistic knowledge, how is it possible that children often, but not always, seem to be able to start using one principle earlier and better than the other? Several proposals have been made as to what the problem is with the Binding Theory and the acquisition of anaphoric elements in general, or with Principle B and the acquisition of pronouns in particular (Grimshaw & Rosen, 1990, Koster, 1988). The main focus of this paper is the proposal that the traditional Binding Theory may be incorrectly stated and, specifically, that Principle B is in need of reformulation, separating grammatical binding from intended coreference interpretations. This separation would entail making a strict distinction between knowledge of a grammatical sort and knowledge of a pragmatic sort; the former presumed to be part of Universal Grammar and available from an early age onward, the latter presumed to be based on knowledge of the world which may be acquired only gradually, via experience. In the traditional version of the Binding Theory, reflexives are always given a bound variable interpretation, while pronominals are open to either a bound variable interpretation which is grammatically determined or to an intended coreference interpretation which is partially pragmatically determined. The fact that pragmatic rules are brought into play for pronominals and not for reflexives could result in an imbalance between children’s success with reflexives and pronouns. 2. The reformulated Binding Theory A recent attempt to reformulate the Binding Theory centers specifically on problems with pronouns: what must be explained grammatically and what can be explained pragmatically (Montalbetti & Wexler, 1985, Reinhart, 1983, 1986). The suggestion is that the core issue of a syntactic Binding Theory should be bound variable interpretation, and not intended coreference, of pronominals as well as reflexives. The reformulated Principle B, therefore, would also be limited to grammatical binding. Constraints on intended coreference of pronouns, in this view, should not be considered part of a theory of grammar, but limited to the domain of pragmatics. In Reinhart’s version of the reformulated Binding Theory, the anaphoric element must be syntactically bound, c-commanded by its antecedent, either within its governing category (for reflexives) or outside its governing category (for pronominals) in order to receive an interpretation. Reinhart’s (1983) definition of the reformulated Binding Theory is as follows: Binding Theory: Coindex a pronoun P with a c-commanding NP alpha (alpha not immediately dominated by COMP o r S’). Conditions: A if P is an R-pronoun alpha must be in its minimal governing category. B if P is a non-R-pronoun, alpha must be outside its minimal governing category (p. 71) For coreference, Reinhart (1983) describes a Speaker’s Strategy and a Hearer’s Strategy, which has been formulated as Rule I (Grodzinsky & Reinhart, to appear): Rule I (inference): A free NP, A, can be intended as coreferential with NP, B, in the same sentence, iff either a. it is impossible to replace A with a (distinct) anaphoric expression that can be bound by B or b. the coreference interpretation needs to be distinguished from the bound Recently, Chien and Wexler (1990) stated the reformulation of Principle B only in terms of the local domain: pronouns cannot have a bound variable reading with a c-commanding antecedent in the same local domain. The key to reformulating the Binding Theory, according to them, lies in the role of indices: anaphors must have the same index as the local c-commanding antecedent, while pronouns may not have the same index as the local c-commanding antecedent. The semantics and pragmatics must deal with how these indices are to be interpreted. In the case of Principle A, anaphors and their antecedents have the same index, and are intended to refer to the same entity; coindexation implies intended coreference here. Principle B rules out the possibility of a pronoun and a local c-commanding NP having the same index. The pronominal cannot be locally bound. The critical question for pronouns now is: when a pronoun has a different index from the local c-commanding NP, what does this noncoindexing imply? It can be demonstrated that it does not necessarily imply disjoint reference. Chien and Wexler give the following example to demonstrate that disjoint reference is not always the case: (1) Thati must be Johnj (2) a. *At least hei looks like himi b. At least hei looks like himj Coindexing in (2a) is ruled out because him is bound in its governing category. In (2b), where the pronoun is not bound and no binding principle is violated, noncoindexing does not necessarily demand disjointness: he and him can both refer to the same entity, the NP John. While two coindexed NPs must corefer, (2a), two noncoindexed NPs are simply free in reference, (2b). Chien and Wexler propose a Principle P (P=pragmatics), like Reinhart’s Rule I, to handle the pragmatic coreference cases like (2b) above, where he and him are not coindexed but nevertheless still can be coreferentially interpreted. The reformulated Principle B applies only to bound variable readings of pronouns and not to (2), which allowed a pragmatic, intended coreference interpretation of two noncoindexed NPs. In order for a pronoun to be interpreted as a bound variable, it must be coindexed with its antecedent and, as Principle B states, this must not occur in the local domain. Compare Reinhart’s example (1986, p 124) below with (2) above. (3) Each of the boysi brought hisi bear For all x (x is a boy), x brought x’s bear The pronoun his is coindexed with the quantified phrase Each of the boys, and is a variable bound by this antecedent. It does not have a fixed value here, since this value depends upon the choice of quantified antecedent. Quantified NPs have no reference. Now, look at an example of a quantified NP and an object pronoun c-commanded by that NP. Compare Chien and Wexler’s example (4) with (2) and (3) above: (4) Every womani looks like her*i/j","PeriodicalId":269579,"journal":{"name":"Binding, Dependencies, and Learnability","volume":"79 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2018-10-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"1","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Problems With Pronoun Acquisition\",\"authors\":\"C. Koster, B. Lust, G. Hermon, J. Kornfilt, Suzanne Flynn, S. Kapur, Barbier, K Boser, C. Foley, ZN delPrado, EJ Rubin, L Santelman, J. Toribio\",\"doi\":\"10.4324/9781315789200-9\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Experimental studies have often shown that children have more problems with pronouns than was originally expected. One recent explanation of the discrepancy between empirical results and linguistic theory is that the Binding Theory is in need of reformulation to include only bound variable interpretations of pronominals as well as reflexives, with intended coreference relegated to the domain of pragmatics. The Dutch studies presented here explore children’s sensitivity to bound variable interpretations of reflexives and pronominals by investigating their understanding of VP-deletion sentences. The results show errors with pronominals that do not support the reformulated version of the Binding Theory as a better description of children’s acquisition problems. (DRAFT: non-final version!!) PROBLEMS WITH PRONOUN ACQUISITION 1. The traditional Binding Theory Knowledge of anaphora in relation to reflexives and pronominals is traditionally summed up in two of the principles of the Binding Theory (Chomsky, 1981): Principle A a bound anaphor, like the reflexive himself, must be bound in its governing category, and Principle B a free anaphor, like the pronominal him, must not be bound in its governing category. Based on the principles and parameters view of language acquisition, it has been proposed that the principles of the Binding Theory should have an innate basis, or be part of what is often called Universal Grammar. Children’s knowledge of the Binding Theory principles has been quite extensively investigated during the last decade, but the empirical evidence does not give as straightforward a picture as was originally expected. Children’s performance on anaphora tasks is more of a mixed success than had been predicted. Correct understanding of anaphoric reference with pronominals and reflexives is not instantaneously visible in very young children; but it does improve over time. Developmental patterns for sentences with reflexives and pronominals also do not necessarily run parallel. One of the more consistent results is that children relatively quickly and easily come to understand bound anaphors, such as reflexives. In the case of pronominals, development is usually (but not always) slow, often stagnating and problematic for many years, even up into middle childhood. In some experimental studies, children seem to be interpreting pronouns as if they were reflexives, and this is specifically the one error that they should not be making. To make the picture even more confusing, there are also situations in which children perform equally well on sentences with pronominals and reflexives, or even better on sentences with pronominals (Kaufman, 1992). If both Binding Theory principles are presumed to be part of innate linguistic knowledge, how is it possible that children often, but not always, seem to be able to start using one principle earlier and better than the other? Several proposals have been made as to what the problem is with the Binding Theory and the acquisition of anaphoric elements in general, or with Principle B and the acquisition of pronouns in particular (Grimshaw & Rosen, 1990, Koster, 1988). The main focus of this paper is the proposal that the traditional Binding Theory may be incorrectly stated and, specifically, that Principle B is in need of reformulation, separating grammatical binding from intended coreference interpretations. This separation would entail making a strict distinction between knowledge of a grammatical sort and knowledge of a pragmatic sort; the former presumed to be part of Universal Grammar and available from an early age onward, the latter presumed to be based on knowledge of the world which may be acquired only gradually, via experience. In the traditional version of the Binding Theory, reflexives are always given a bound variable interpretation, while pronominals are open to either a bound variable interpretation which is grammatically determined or to an intended coreference interpretation which is partially pragmatically determined. The fact that pragmatic rules are brought into play for pronominals and not for reflexives could result in an imbalance between children’s success with reflexives and pronouns. 2. The reformulated Binding Theory A recent attempt to reformulate the Binding Theory centers specifically on problems with pronouns: what must be explained grammatically and what can be explained pragmatically (Montalbetti & Wexler, 1985, Reinhart, 1983, 1986). The suggestion is that the core issue of a syntactic Binding Theory should be bound variable interpretation, and not intended coreference, of pronominals as well as reflexives. The reformulated Principle B, therefore, would also be limited to grammatical binding. Constraints on intended coreference of pronouns, in this view, should not be considered part of a theory of grammar, but limited to the domain of pragmatics. In Reinhart’s version of the reformulated Binding Theory, the anaphoric element must be syntactically bound, c-commanded by its antecedent, either within its governing category (for reflexives) or outside its governing category (for pronominals) in order to receive an interpretation. Reinhart’s (1983) definition of the reformulated Binding Theory is as follows: Binding Theory: Coindex a pronoun P with a c-commanding NP alpha (alpha not immediately dominated by COMP o r S’). Conditions: A if P is an R-pronoun alpha must be in its minimal governing category. B if P is a non-R-pronoun, alpha must be outside its minimal governing category (p. 71) For coreference, Reinhart (1983) describes a Speaker’s Strategy and a Hearer’s Strategy, which has been formulated as Rule I (Grodzinsky & Reinhart, to appear): Rule I (inference): A free NP, A, can be intended as coreferential with NP, B, in the same sentence, iff either a. it is impossible to replace A with a (distinct) anaphoric expression that can be bound by B or b. the coreference interpretation needs to be distinguished from the bound Recently, Chien and Wexler (1990) stated the reformulation of Principle B only in terms of the local domain: pronouns cannot have a bound variable reading with a c-commanding antecedent in the same local domain. The key to reformulating the Binding Theory, according to them, lies in the role of indices: anaphors must have the same index as the local c-commanding antecedent, while pronouns may not have the same index as the local c-commanding antecedent. The semantics and pragmatics must deal with how these indices are to be interpreted. In the case of Principle A, anaphors and their antecedents have the same index, and are intended to refer to the same entity; coindexation implies intended coreference here. Principle B rules out the possibility of a pronoun and a local c-commanding NP having the same index. The pronominal cannot be locally bound. The critical question for pronouns now is: when a pronoun has a different index from the local c-commanding NP, what does this noncoindexing imply? It can be demonstrated that it does not necessarily imply disjoint reference. Chien and Wexler give the following example to demonstrate that disjoint reference is not always the case: (1) Thati must be Johnj (2) a. *At least hei looks like himi b. At least hei looks like himj Coindexing in (2a) is ruled out because him is bound in its governing category. In (2b), where the pronoun is not bound and no binding principle is violated, noncoindexing does not necessarily demand disjointness: he and him can both refer to the same entity, the NP John. While two coindexed NPs must corefer, (2a), two noncoindexed NPs are simply free in reference, (2b). Chien and Wexler propose a Principle P (P=pragmatics), like Reinhart’s Rule I, to handle the pragmatic coreference cases like (2b) above, where he and him are not coindexed but nevertheless still can be coreferentially interpreted. The reformulated Principle B applies only to bound variable readings of pronouns and not to (2), which allowed a pragmatic, intended coreference interpretation of two noncoindexed NPs. In order for a pronoun to be interpreted as a bound variable, it must be coindexed with its antecedent and, as Principle B states, this must not occur in the local domain. Compare Reinhart’s example (1986, p 124) below with (2) above. (3) Each of the boysi brought hisi bear For all x (x is a boy), x brought x’s bear The pronoun his is coindexed with the quantified phrase Each of the boys, and is a variable bound by this antecedent. It does not have a fixed value here, since this value depends upon the choice of quantified antecedent. Quantified NPs have no reference. Now, look at an example of a quantified NP and an object pronoun c-commanded by that NP. Compare Chien and Wexler’s example (4) with (2) and (3) above: (4) Every womani looks like her*i/j\",\"PeriodicalId\":269579,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Binding, Dependencies, and Learnability\",\"volume\":\"79 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2018-10-24\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"1\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Binding, Dependencies, and Learnability\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315789200-9\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Binding, Dependencies, and Learnability","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315789200-9","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
摘要
在莱因哈特重新制定的约束理论中,回指元素必须在句法上被约束,由先行词控制,要么在其支配范畴内(对于反身代词),要么在其支配范畴外(对于代词),才能得到解释。Reinhart(1983)对重新表述的绑定理论的定义如下:绑定理论:将代词P与命令c的NP α (α不立即被COMP o或S '支配)结合起来。条件:如果P是r的代名词,则A必须在其最小支配范畴内。B如果P是非r -代词,则alpha必须在其最小控制范畴之外(第71页)。为了共同参考,Reinhart(1983)描述了说话者的策略和听者的策略,并将其制定为规则I (Grodzinsky & Reinhart,将出现):规则I(推论):免费NP,可以作为互参的NP, B,在同一个句子,敌我识别答:它无法取代的(不同的)逐字表达式,可以受B或B指称相同解释需要区别绑定最近,简和Wexler(1990)所述原则B的再形成只有当地的领域:代词不能绑定变量阅读c-commanding先行词在同一地方域。他们认为,重新制定约束理论的关键在于索引的作用:指喻必须具有与局部命令型先行词相同的索引,而代词不一定具有与局部命令型先行词相同的索引。语义学和语用学必须处理如何解释这些索引。在原则A的情况下,指喻及其先行词具有相同的索引,并且旨在指同一实体;共同索引在这里意味着有意的共同引用。原则B排除了代词和局部c-命令NP具有相同索引的可能性。代词不能被局部约束。对于代词来说,现在的关键问题是:当一个代词的索引不同于局部命令c的NP时,这种不共同索引意味着什么?可以证明,它并不一定意味着不相交的参考。Chien和weexler给出了下面的例子来证明不相交的引用并不总是这样:(1)必须是Johnj (2) a. *至少hei看起来像他b.至少hei看起来像他j在(2a)中被排除了共标,因为他被限制在它的支配范畴中。在(2b)中,当代词不受约束且不违反约束原则时,非共标并不一定要求不相交:他和他都可以指代同一个实体,即NP John。两个协同索引的NPs必须相互引用(2a),而两个非协同索引的NPs在引用(2b)上是自由的。Chien和weexler提出了一个原则P (P=语用学),就像莱因哈特的规则I一样,来处理像上面(2b)这样的语用共指情况,在这种情况下,他和他没有被共指,但仍然可以被共指解释。重新制定的原则B仅适用于代词的绑定变量阅读,而不适用于(2),这允许对两个非协同索引的np进行语用,有意的共指解释。为了将代词解释为绑定变量,它必须与其先行词协同索引,并且正如原则B所述,这不能发生在局部域中。比较下面莱因哈特的例子(1986,第124页)和上面(2)。对于所有的x (x是一个男孩),x带来了x的熊。代词his与量词Each of the boys并列,是一个受这个先行词约束的变量。它在这里没有一个固定的值,因为这个值取决于量化先行词的选择。量化的NPs没有参考。现在,看一个量化NP和由该NP支配的宾语代词c的例子。将Chien和Wexler的例子(4)与上面的(2)和(3)进行比较:(4)每个女人看起来都像她的*i/j
Experimental studies have often shown that children have more problems with pronouns than was originally expected. One recent explanation of the discrepancy between empirical results and linguistic theory is that the Binding Theory is in need of reformulation to include only bound variable interpretations of pronominals as well as reflexives, with intended coreference relegated to the domain of pragmatics. The Dutch studies presented here explore children’s sensitivity to bound variable interpretations of reflexives and pronominals by investigating their understanding of VP-deletion sentences. The results show errors with pronominals that do not support the reformulated version of the Binding Theory as a better description of children’s acquisition problems. (DRAFT: non-final version!!) PROBLEMS WITH PRONOUN ACQUISITION 1. The traditional Binding Theory Knowledge of anaphora in relation to reflexives and pronominals is traditionally summed up in two of the principles of the Binding Theory (Chomsky, 1981): Principle A a bound anaphor, like the reflexive himself, must be bound in its governing category, and Principle B a free anaphor, like the pronominal him, must not be bound in its governing category. Based on the principles and parameters view of language acquisition, it has been proposed that the principles of the Binding Theory should have an innate basis, or be part of what is often called Universal Grammar. Children’s knowledge of the Binding Theory principles has been quite extensively investigated during the last decade, but the empirical evidence does not give as straightforward a picture as was originally expected. Children’s performance on anaphora tasks is more of a mixed success than had been predicted. Correct understanding of anaphoric reference with pronominals and reflexives is not instantaneously visible in very young children; but it does improve over time. Developmental patterns for sentences with reflexives and pronominals also do not necessarily run parallel. One of the more consistent results is that children relatively quickly and easily come to understand bound anaphors, such as reflexives. In the case of pronominals, development is usually (but not always) slow, often stagnating and problematic for many years, even up into middle childhood. In some experimental studies, children seem to be interpreting pronouns as if they were reflexives, and this is specifically the one error that they should not be making. To make the picture even more confusing, there are also situations in which children perform equally well on sentences with pronominals and reflexives, or even better on sentences with pronominals (Kaufman, 1992). If both Binding Theory principles are presumed to be part of innate linguistic knowledge, how is it possible that children often, but not always, seem to be able to start using one principle earlier and better than the other? Several proposals have been made as to what the problem is with the Binding Theory and the acquisition of anaphoric elements in general, or with Principle B and the acquisition of pronouns in particular (Grimshaw & Rosen, 1990, Koster, 1988). The main focus of this paper is the proposal that the traditional Binding Theory may be incorrectly stated and, specifically, that Principle B is in need of reformulation, separating grammatical binding from intended coreference interpretations. This separation would entail making a strict distinction between knowledge of a grammatical sort and knowledge of a pragmatic sort; the former presumed to be part of Universal Grammar and available from an early age onward, the latter presumed to be based on knowledge of the world which may be acquired only gradually, via experience. In the traditional version of the Binding Theory, reflexives are always given a bound variable interpretation, while pronominals are open to either a bound variable interpretation which is grammatically determined or to an intended coreference interpretation which is partially pragmatically determined. The fact that pragmatic rules are brought into play for pronominals and not for reflexives could result in an imbalance between children’s success with reflexives and pronouns. 2. The reformulated Binding Theory A recent attempt to reformulate the Binding Theory centers specifically on problems with pronouns: what must be explained grammatically and what can be explained pragmatically (Montalbetti & Wexler, 1985, Reinhart, 1983, 1986). The suggestion is that the core issue of a syntactic Binding Theory should be bound variable interpretation, and not intended coreference, of pronominals as well as reflexives. The reformulated Principle B, therefore, would also be limited to grammatical binding. Constraints on intended coreference of pronouns, in this view, should not be considered part of a theory of grammar, but limited to the domain of pragmatics. In Reinhart’s version of the reformulated Binding Theory, the anaphoric element must be syntactically bound, c-commanded by its antecedent, either within its governing category (for reflexives) or outside its governing category (for pronominals) in order to receive an interpretation. Reinhart’s (1983) definition of the reformulated Binding Theory is as follows: Binding Theory: Coindex a pronoun P with a c-commanding NP alpha (alpha not immediately dominated by COMP o r S’). Conditions: A if P is an R-pronoun alpha must be in its minimal governing category. B if P is a non-R-pronoun, alpha must be outside its minimal governing category (p. 71) For coreference, Reinhart (1983) describes a Speaker’s Strategy and a Hearer’s Strategy, which has been formulated as Rule I (Grodzinsky & Reinhart, to appear): Rule I (inference): A free NP, A, can be intended as coreferential with NP, B, in the same sentence, iff either a. it is impossible to replace A with a (distinct) anaphoric expression that can be bound by B or b. the coreference interpretation needs to be distinguished from the bound Recently, Chien and Wexler (1990) stated the reformulation of Principle B only in terms of the local domain: pronouns cannot have a bound variable reading with a c-commanding antecedent in the same local domain. The key to reformulating the Binding Theory, according to them, lies in the role of indices: anaphors must have the same index as the local c-commanding antecedent, while pronouns may not have the same index as the local c-commanding antecedent. The semantics and pragmatics must deal with how these indices are to be interpreted. In the case of Principle A, anaphors and their antecedents have the same index, and are intended to refer to the same entity; coindexation implies intended coreference here. Principle B rules out the possibility of a pronoun and a local c-commanding NP having the same index. The pronominal cannot be locally bound. The critical question for pronouns now is: when a pronoun has a different index from the local c-commanding NP, what does this noncoindexing imply? It can be demonstrated that it does not necessarily imply disjoint reference. Chien and Wexler give the following example to demonstrate that disjoint reference is not always the case: (1) Thati must be Johnj (2) a. *At least hei looks like himi b. At least hei looks like himj Coindexing in (2a) is ruled out because him is bound in its governing category. In (2b), where the pronoun is not bound and no binding principle is violated, noncoindexing does not necessarily demand disjointness: he and him can both refer to the same entity, the NP John. While two coindexed NPs must corefer, (2a), two noncoindexed NPs are simply free in reference, (2b). Chien and Wexler propose a Principle P (P=pragmatics), like Reinhart’s Rule I, to handle the pragmatic coreference cases like (2b) above, where he and him are not coindexed but nevertheless still can be coreferentially interpreted. The reformulated Principle B applies only to bound variable readings of pronouns and not to (2), which allowed a pragmatic, intended coreference interpretation of two noncoindexed NPs. In order for a pronoun to be interpreted as a bound variable, it must be coindexed with its antecedent and, as Principle B states, this must not occur in the local domain. Compare Reinhart’s example (1986, p 124) below with (2) above. (3) Each of the boysi brought hisi bear For all x (x is a boy), x brought x’s bear The pronoun his is coindexed with the quantified phrase Each of the boys, and is a variable bound by this antecedent. It does not have a fixed value here, since this value depends upon the choice of quantified antecedent. Quantified NPs have no reference. Now, look at an example of a quantified NP and an object pronoun c-commanded by that NP. Compare Chien and Wexler’s example (4) with (2) and (3) above: (4) Every womani looks like her*i/j