情报分析的统一理论

IF 0.8 3区 社会学 Q1 HISTORY Intelligence and National Security Pub Date : 2023-11-01 DOI:10.1080/02684527.2023.2272349
Carles Ortola
{"title":"情报分析的统一理论","authors":"Carles Ortola","doi":"10.1080/02684527.2023.2272349","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTCausation has traditionally been an under-theorized topic. Until Hendrickson’s work, very little effort had been devoted to creating a compelling theory of causation in intelligence analysis. In line with the recent attempts to integrate intelligence theory with philosophy, this article is intended to contribute to the philosophy of intelligence by defining a dedicated account of causation for it. The Unified Theory for Intelligence Analysis, as this account of causation is named, is intended to integrate into a single account Betts’ Normal and Exceptional Theories as well as Hendrickson’s target challenges. It is then proved that a pluralistic account of causation that combines both counterfactual and probabilistic accounts of causation is the most successful option. Finally, it is shown that Bayesian tools are the natural manifestation of this Unified Theory, and that Subjective Logic can help refute criticism against Bayesianism in intelligence analysis. Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Phythian, “Intelligence Analysis and Social Science Methods: Exploring the Potential for and Possible Limits of Mutual Learning,” 601.2. Marrin, Improving Intelligence Analysis: Bridging the Gap between Scholarship and Practice.3. Kaupi, “Counterterrorism Analysis 101,” 47.4. Phythian, “Intelligence Analysis and Social Science Methods: Exploring the Potential for and Possible Limits of Mutual Learning,” p. 605.5. Betts, Enemies of Intelligence: Knowledge and Power in American National Security, p. 57.6. Laplace’s demon is a hypothetical being that has perfect knowledge of the position and momentum of every particle in the universe. If such a being existed, it could use this knowledge to predict the future with certainty. Laplace and his contemporaries believed that the universe was deterministic, meaning that every event was caused by a previous event and could be predicted with perfect knowledge. However, later research showed that the universe is not deterministic at the quantum level, meaning that there is an element of randomness in nature. This led to the crisis of classical determinism and the development of probabilistic quantum mechanics, which is a more accurate description of the world.7. Minkel, “If the Universe Were a Computer”.8. Phythian, ‘Intelligence Analysis and Social Science Methods: Exploring the Potential for and Possible Limits of Mutual Learning’. P. 603.9. Hendrickson, Reasoning for Intelligence Analysts: A Multidimensional Approach of Traits, Techniques, and Targets.10. Heuer, “The Evolution of Structured Analytic Techniques,” p. 4.11. Hendrickson, Reasoning for Intelligence Analysts: A Multidimensional Approach of Traits, Techniques, and Targets.12. According to Hendrickson, there is an epistemic continuum from data collection to strategic advice, and it can be divided into four separate stages that can be added up depending on the kind of intelligence to be produced. In particular, he divides that continuum into: what is happening? Why is this happening? When and where might this change? And how can the client respond to it? In turn, each of Hendrickson’s four problems becomes the protagonist in one of these stages. Moreover, this classification is similar to Edward Waltz’s epistemic domains: prescriptive, descriptive, exploratory, and predictive-evaluative.13. Godson and Wirtz, “Strategic Denial and Deception,” 426.14. Betts, Enemies of Intelligence: Knowledge and Power in American National Security, p. 60.15. Betts, “Warning Dilemmas: Normal Theory vs. Exceptional Theory,” 829.16. Betts, Enemies of Intelligence: Knowledge and Power in American National Security, 6217. Ross, Prospects for Crisis Prediction: A South Pacific Case Study., p. 3118. Hendrickson, Reasoning for Intelligence Analysts: A Multidimensional Approach of Traits, Techniques, and Targets19. Hart and Simon, “Thinking Straight and Talking Straight: Problems of Intelligence Analysis,“ 41.20. Waltz, Quantitative Intelligence Analysis: Applied Analytic Models, Simulations, and Games.21. Gaspard and Pili, “Integrating Intelligence Theory with Philosophy: Introduction to the Special Issue,” 763.22. Ben-Haim, “Positivism and Its Limitations for Strategic Intelligence: A Non-Constructivist Info-Gap Critique,” 912.23. Knightian uncertainty, coined by economist Frank Knight, is a form of uncertainty that arises when faced with new or unfamiliar situations where probabilities cannot be assigned. Shackle-Popper indeterminism is the inherent unpredictability of human behavior and complex systems due to the numerous and interconnected variables at play.24. Danks, “The Psychology of Causal Perception and Reasoning,” 458.25. Loewer, “Determinism and Chance,” 612.26. Psillos, “Regularity Theories,” 132–13327. Berofsky and Mackie, “The Cement of the Universe: A Study of Causation,” 86.28. Lebow, Forbidden Fruit: Counterfactuals and International Relations, 259–28629. Nolan, “Why Historians (and Everyone Else) Should Care about Counterfactuals,” 333.30. Abel and Ofer, “Subjective Causality and Counterfactuals in the Social Sciences: Toward an Ethnographic Causality?,” 15.31. Lebow, “What’s so Different about a Counterfactual?,” 557.32. Menzies and Beebee, “Counterfactual Theories of Causation”.33. Lebow, “What’s so Different about a Counterfactual?,” 554–55534. Weber, “Counterfactuals, Past and Future,” 278.35. Lebow, Forbidden Fruit: Counterfactuals and International Relations, p. 3036. Lebow, “What’s so Different about a Counterfactual?,” 566.37. Kiser and Levi, Using Counterfactuals in Historical Analysis: Theories of Revolution., p. 18938. Kiser and Levi, Using Counterfactuals in Historical Analysis: Theories of Revolution., p. 19239. Lebow, “What’s so Different about a Counterfactual?,” 556.40. Lebow, “What’s so Different about a Counterfactual?,” 574.41. Harbecke, “Counterfactual Theories of Causation and the Problem of Large Causes,” 1652.42. Papineau, “Can We Reduce Causal Direction to Probabilities?,” 239–24043. Pearl, “Probabilities Of Causation: Three Counterfactual Interpretations And Their Identification,” 94.44. Hájek, “Probabilities of Counterfactuals and Counterfactual Probabilities,” 237.45. Longworth, “Causation, Pluralism and Responsibility,” 54.46. The Second Law of Thermodynamics is responsible for the future being uncertain. It basically describes why processes in the world are irreversible and defines why the Arrow of Time always goes forward and why the past is defined, but the future is not. In fact, this law is one of the most solid claims Science has ever made. In Einstein’s opinion, ‘the second law of thermodynamics is the only physical theory of universal content concerning which I am convinced that, within the framework of the applicability of its basic concepts, it will never be overthrown’.47. de Finetti, “Foresight: Its Logical Laws, Its Subjective Sources,” 139.48. Marrin and Torres, “Improving How to Think in Intelligence Analysis and Medicine,” 649.49. Zlotnick, ‘Bayes’ Theorem for Intelligence Analysis”.50. Marchio, “Overcoming the Inertia of ‘Old Ways of Producing Intelligence’ – the IC’s Development and Use of New Analytic Methods in the 1970s,” 990.51. Sloman, Causal Models: How People Think about the World and Its Alternatives., pp. 116–13152. Zlotnick, “A Theorem for Prediction,” 5.53. Martin and Popper, “Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach,” 276–27754. Lewis, “Postscripts to ‘Causation’,” 50.55. Jøsang, “A Logic for Uncertain Probabilities”; Jøsang, “Subjective Evidential Reasoning,” p. 282.56. Although Subjective Logic is a powerful tool, it requires considerable knowledge on Statistics and Logic. An introduction to Subjective’s Logic can be found at Subjective Logic: A Formalism for Reasoning Under Uncertainty. Subjective Logic is a solid and well-developed theory that permits complex operators in causal networks to be evaluated to determine nested causal chains, for example. Some simple calculators are available online at: https://folk.universitetetioslo.no/josang/sl/Op.html57. M. Isaksen and McNaught, “Towards a Better Framework for Estimative Intelligence – Addressing Quality through a Systematic Approach to Uncertainty Handling”.Additional informationNotes on contributorsCarles OrtolaCarles Ortola Associate Professor of Strategic Intelligence at Universitat de Barcelona and PhD Candidate at UNED (Universidad Nacional de Eduación a Distancia) in Spain.","PeriodicalId":47048,"journal":{"name":"Intelligence and National Security","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"A Unified Theory for Intelligence Analysis\",\"authors\":\"Carles Ortola\",\"doi\":\"10.1080/02684527.2023.2272349\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"ABSTRACTCausation has traditionally been an under-theorized topic. Until Hendrickson’s work, very little effort had been devoted to creating a compelling theory of causation in intelligence analysis. In line with the recent attempts to integrate intelligence theory with philosophy, this article is intended to contribute to the philosophy of intelligence by defining a dedicated account of causation for it. The Unified Theory for Intelligence Analysis, as this account of causation is named, is intended to integrate into a single account Betts’ Normal and Exceptional Theories as well as Hendrickson’s target challenges. It is then proved that a pluralistic account of causation that combines both counterfactual and probabilistic accounts of causation is the most successful option. Finally, it is shown that Bayesian tools are the natural manifestation of this Unified Theory, and that Subjective Logic can help refute criticism against Bayesianism in intelligence analysis. Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Phythian, “Intelligence Analysis and Social Science Methods: Exploring the Potential for and Possible Limits of Mutual Learning,” 601.2. Marrin, Improving Intelligence Analysis: Bridging the Gap between Scholarship and Practice.3. Kaupi, “Counterterrorism Analysis 101,” 47.4. Phythian, “Intelligence Analysis and Social Science Methods: Exploring the Potential for and Possible Limits of Mutual Learning,” p. 605.5. Betts, Enemies of Intelligence: Knowledge and Power in American National Security, p. 57.6. Laplace’s demon is a hypothetical being that has perfect knowledge of the position and momentum of every particle in the universe. If such a being existed, it could use this knowledge to predict the future with certainty. Laplace and his contemporaries believed that the universe was deterministic, meaning that every event was caused by a previous event and could be predicted with perfect knowledge. However, later research showed that the universe is not deterministic at the quantum level, meaning that there is an element of randomness in nature. This led to the crisis of classical determinism and the development of probabilistic quantum mechanics, which is a more accurate description of the world.7. Minkel, “If the Universe Were a Computer”.8. Phythian, ‘Intelligence Analysis and Social Science Methods: Exploring the Potential for and Possible Limits of Mutual Learning’. P. 603.9. Hendrickson, Reasoning for Intelligence Analysts: A Multidimensional Approach of Traits, Techniques, and Targets.10. Heuer, “The Evolution of Structured Analytic Techniques,” p. 4.11. Hendrickson, Reasoning for Intelligence Analysts: A Multidimensional Approach of Traits, Techniques, and Targets.12. According to Hendrickson, there is an epistemic continuum from data collection to strategic advice, and it can be divided into four separate stages that can be added up depending on the kind of intelligence to be produced. In particular, he divides that continuum into: what is happening? Why is this happening? When and where might this change? And how can the client respond to it? In turn, each of Hendrickson’s four problems becomes the protagonist in one of these stages. Moreover, this classification is similar to Edward Waltz’s epistemic domains: prescriptive, descriptive, exploratory, and predictive-evaluative.13. Godson and Wirtz, “Strategic Denial and Deception,” 426.14. Betts, Enemies of Intelligence: Knowledge and Power in American National Security, p. 60.15. Betts, “Warning Dilemmas: Normal Theory vs. Exceptional Theory,” 829.16. Betts, Enemies of Intelligence: Knowledge and Power in American National Security, 6217. Ross, Prospects for Crisis Prediction: A South Pacific Case Study., p. 3118. Hendrickson, Reasoning for Intelligence Analysts: A Multidimensional Approach of Traits, Techniques, and Targets19. Hart and Simon, “Thinking Straight and Talking Straight: Problems of Intelligence Analysis,“ 41.20. Waltz, Quantitative Intelligence Analysis: Applied Analytic Models, Simulations, and Games.21. Gaspard and Pili, “Integrating Intelligence Theory with Philosophy: Introduction to the Special Issue,” 763.22. Ben-Haim, “Positivism and Its Limitations for Strategic Intelligence: A Non-Constructivist Info-Gap Critique,” 912.23. Knightian uncertainty, coined by economist Frank Knight, is a form of uncertainty that arises when faced with new or unfamiliar situations where probabilities cannot be assigned. Shackle-Popper indeterminism is the inherent unpredictability of human behavior and complex systems due to the numerous and interconnected variables at play.24. Danks, “The Psychology of Causal Perception and Reasoning,” 458.25. Loewer, “Determinism and Chance,” 612.26. Psillos, “Regularity Theories,” 132–13327. Berofsky and Mackie, “The Cement of the Universe: A Study of Causation,” 86.28. Lebow, Forbidden Fruit: Counterfactuals and International Relations, 259–28629. Nolan, “Why Historians (and Everyone Else) Should Care about Counterfactuals,” 333.30. Abel and Ofer, “Subjective Causality and Counterfactuals in the Social Sciences: Toward an Ethnographic Causality?,” 15.31. Lebow, “What’s so Different about a Counterfactual?,” 557.32. Menzies and Beebee, “Counterfactual Theories of Causation”.33. Lebow, “What’s so Different about a Counterfactual?,” 554–55534. Weber, “Counterfactuals, Past and Future,” 278.35. Lebow, Forbidden Fruit: Counterfactuals and International Relations, p. 3036. Lebow, “What’s so Different about a Counterfactual?,” 566.37. Kiser and Levi, Using Counterfactuals in Historical Analysis: Theories of Revolution., p. 18938. Kiser and Levi, Using Counterfactuals in Historical Analysis: Theories of Revolution., p. 19239. Lebow, “What’s so Different about a Counterfactual?,” 556.40. Lebow, “What’s so Different about a Counterfactual?,” 574.41. Harbecke, “Counterfactual Theories of Causation and the Problem of Large Causes,” 1652.42. Papineau, “Can We Reduce Causal Direction to Probabilities?,” 239–24043. Pearl, “Probabilities Of Causation: Three Counterfactual Interpretations And Their Identification,” 94.44. Hájek, “Probabilities of Counterfactuals and Counterfactual Probabilities,” 237.45. Longworth, “Causation, Pluralism and Responsibility,” 54.46. The Second Law of Thermodynamics is responsible for the future being uncertain. It basically describes why processes in the world are irreversible and defines why the Arrow of Time always goes forward and why the past is defined, but the future is not. In fact, this law is one of the most solid claims Science has ever made. In Einstein’s opinion, ‘the second law of thermodynamics is the only physical theory of universal content concerning which I am convinced that, within the framework of the applicability of its basic concepts, it will never be overthrown’.47. de Finetti, “Foresight: Its Logical Laws, Its Subjective Sources,” 139.48. Marrin and Torres, “Improving How to Think in Intelligence Analysis and Medicine,” 649.49. Zlotnick, ‘Bayes’ Theorem for Intelligence Analysis”.50. Marchio, “Overcoming the Inertia of ‘Old Ways of Producing Intelligence’ – the IC’s Development and Use of New Analytic Methods in the 1970s,” 990.51. Sloman, Causal Models: How People Think about the World and Its Alternatives., pp. 116–13152. Zlotnick, “A Theorem for Prediction,” 5.53. Martin and Popper, “Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach,” 276–27754. Lewis, “Postscripts to ‘Causation’,” 50.55. Jøsang, “A Logic for Uncertain Probabilities”; Jøsang, “Subjective Evidential Reasoning,” p. 282.56. Although Subjective Logic is a powerful tool, it requires considerable knowledge on Statistics and Logic. An introduction to Subjective’s Logic can be found at Subjective Logic: A Formalism for Reasoning Under Uncertainty. Subjective Logic is a solid and well-developed theory that permits complex operators in causal networks to be evaluated to determine nested causal chains, for example. Some simple calculators are available online at: https://folk.universitetetioslo.no/josang/sl/Op.html57. M. Isaksen and McNaught, “Towards a Better Framework for Estimative Intelligence – Addressing Quality through a Systematic Approach to Uncertainty Handling”.Additional informationNotes on contributorsCarles OrtolaCarles Ortola Associate Professor of Strategic Intelligence at Universitat de Barcelona and PhD Candidate at UNED (Universidad Nacional de Eduación a Distancia) in Spain.\",\"PeriodicalId\":47048,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Intelligence and National Security\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.8000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-11-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Intelligence and National Security\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1080/02684527.2023.2272349\",\"RegionNum\":3,\"RegionCategory\":\"社会学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q1\",\"JCRName\":\"HISTORY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Intelligence and National Security","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02684527.2023.2272349","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"HISTORY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

摘要因果关系历来是一个理论化程度较低的话题。在亨德里克森的工作之前,很少有人致力于在情报分析中建立一个令人信服的因果关系理论。根据最近将智力理论与哲学相结合的尝试,本文旨在通过定义其因果关系的专门说明来为智力哲学做出贡献。这种对因果关系的解释被命名为“情报分析统一理论”,其目的是将贝茨的“正常理论”和“例外理论”以及亨德里克森的目标挑战整合到一个单一的解释中。然后证明,结合反事实和概率因果关系的多元因果关系是最成功的选择。最后,本文表明贝叶斯工具是这一统一理论的自然表现,主观逻辑可以帮助反驳对贝叶斯理论在智力分析中的批评。披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。智力分析和社会科学方法:探索相互学习的潜力和可能的限制,第601.2期。《提高智力分析:弥合学术与实践之间的差距》,第3期。考皮,《反恐分析101》,47.4页。Phythian,“智力分析和社会科学方法:探索相互学习的潜力和可能的限制”,第605.5页。贝茨,《情报的敌人:美国国家安全中的知识和权力》,第57.6页。拉普拉斯妖是一种假设的存在,它对宇宙中每一个粒子的位置和动量都有完美的了解。如果存在这样的生物,它可以利用这些知识来准确地预测未来。拉普拉斯和他的同时代人相信宇宙是决定论的,这意味着每一个事件都是由前一个事件引起的,可以用完美的知识来预测。然而,后来的研究表明,宇宙在量子层面上不是确定性的,这意味着自然界中存在随机性的因素。这导致了经典决定论的危机和概率量子力学的发展,后者是对世界的更准确的描述。8.《如果宇宙是一台计算机》Phythian,“智力分析和社会科学方法:探索相互学习的潜力和可能的限制”。p . 603.9。《情报分析家的推理:特征、技术和目标的多维方法》第10卷。Heuer,“结构化分析技术的演变”,第4.11页。《情报分析家的推理:特征、技术和目标的多维方法》12。亨德里克森认为,从数据收集到战略建议,这是一个认知连续体,它可以分为四个独立的阶段,根据要产生的情报类型,这些阶段可以叠加起来。特别地,他将这个连续体分为:正在发生什么?为什么会发生这种情况?这种变化可能在何时何地发生?客户会如何回应?亨德里克森的四个问题依次成为其中一个阶段的主角。此外,这种分类与爱德华·瓦尔兹的认知领域相似:规定性的、描述性的、探索性的和预测性的。Godson和Wirtz,“战略否认和欺骗”,426.14。贝茨,《情报的敌人:美国国家安全中的知识和权力》,第60.15页。警告困境:正常理论与例外理论>,829.16。情报的敌人:美国国家安全中的知识和权力,6217。危机预测的前景:南太平洋案例研究。, 3118页。亨德里克森,《情报分析的推理:特征、技术和目标的多维方法》19。Hart和Simon, <直想直说:智力分析的问题>,第41期第20页。《定量智能分析:应用分析模型、模拟和游戏》21。Gaspard and Pili, <整合智力理论与哲学:特刊导论>,763.22。张志明,“战略情报的实证主义及其局限性:一种非建构主义的信息鸿沟批判”,第12期。奈特不确定性(Knight uncertainty)是经济学家弗兰克·奈特(Frank Knight)提出的概念,指的是当面对新的或不熟悉的情况,无法确定概率时产生的一种不确定性。桎梏-波普尔不确定性是人类行为和复杂系统固有的不可预测性,这是由于众多相互关联的变量在起作用。《因果知觉与推理的心理学》,第458.25页。下层,“决定论与偶然性”,612.26。Psillos, "规律性理论",132-13327。Berofsky和Mackie,“宇宙的水泥:因果关系的研究”,86.28。《禁果:反事实和国际关系》,259-28629。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
A Unified Theory for Intelligence Analysis
ABSTRACTCausation has traditionally been an under-theorized topic. Until Hendrickson’s work, very little effort had been devoted to creating a compelling theory of causation in intelligence analysis. In line with the recent attempts to integrate intelligence theory with philosophy, this article is intended to contribute to the philosophy of intelligence by defining a dedicated account of causation for it. The Unified Theory for Intelligence Analysis, as this account of causation is named, is intended to integrate into a single account Betts’ Normal and Exceptional Theories as well as Hendrickson’s target challenges. It is then proved that a pluralistic account of causation that combines both counterfactual and probabilistic accounts of causation is the most successful option. Finally, it is shown that Bayesian tools are the natural manifestation of this Unified Theory, and that Subjective Logic can help refute criticism against Bayesianism in intelligence analysis. Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Phythian, “Intelligence Analysis and Social Science Methods: Exploring the Potential for and Possible Limits of Mutual Learning,” 601.2. Marrin, Improving Intelligence Analysis: Bridging the Gap between Scholarship and Practice.3. Kaupi, “Counterterrorism Analysis 101,” 47.4. Phythian, “Intelligence Analysis and Social Science Methods: Exploring the Potential for and Possible Limits of Mutual Learning,” p. 605.5. Betts, Enemies of Intelligence: Knowledge and Power in American National Security, p. 57.6. Laplace’s demon is a hypothetical being that has perfect knowledge of the position and momentum of every particle in the universe. If such a being existed, it could use this knowledge to predict the future with certainty. Laplace and his contemporaries believed that the universe was deterministic, meaning that every event was caused by a previous event and could be predicted with perfect knowledge. However, later research showed that the universe is not deterministic at the quantum level, meaning that there is an element of randomness in nature. This led to the crisis of classical determinism and the development of probabilistic quantum mechanics, which is a more accurate description of the world.7. Minkel, “If the Universe Were a Computer”.8. Phythian, ‘Intelligence Analysis and Social Science Methods: Exploring the Potential for and Possible Limits of Mutual Learning’. P. 603.9. Hendrickson, Reasoning for Intelligence Analysts: A Multidimensional Approach of Traits, Techniques, and Targets.10. Heuer, “The Evolution of Structured Analytic Techniques,” p. 4.11. Hendrickson, Reasoning for Intelligence Analysts: A Multidimensional Approach of Traits, Techniques, and Targets.12. According to Hendrickson, there is an epistemic continuum from data collection to strategic advice, and it can be divided into four separate stages that can be added up depending on the kind of intelligence to be produced. In particular, he divides that continuum into: what is happening? Why is this happening? When and where might this change? And how can the client respond to it? In turn, each of Hendrickson’s four problems becomes the protagonist in one of these stages. Moreover, this classification is similar to Edward Waltz’s epistemic domains: prescriptive, descriptive, exploratory, and predictive-evaluative.13. Godson and Wirtz, “Strategic Denial and Deception,” 426.14. Betts, Enemies of Intelligence: Knowledge and Power in American National Security, p. 60.15. Betts, “Warning Dilemmas: Normal Theory vs. Exceptional Theory,” 829.16. Betts, Enemies of Intelligence: Knowledge and Power in American National Security, 6217. Ross, Prospects for Crisis Prediction: A South Pacific Case Study., p. 3118. Hendrickson, Reasoning for Intelligence Analysts: A Multidimensional Approach of Traits, Techniques, and Targets19. Hart and Simon, “Thinking Straight and Talking Straight: Problems of Intelligence Analysis,“ 41.20. Waltz, Quantitative Intelligence Analysis: Applied Analytic Models, Simulations, and Games.21. Gaspard and Pili, “Integrating Intelligence Theory with Philosophy: Introduction to the Special Issue,” 763.22. Ben-Haim, “Positivism and Its Limitations for Strategic Intelligence: A Non-Constructivist Info-Gap Critique,” 912.23. Knightian uncertainty, coined by economist Frank Knight, is a form of uncertainty that arises when faced with new or unfamiliar situations where probabilities cannot be assigned. Shackle-Popper indeterminism is the inherent unpredictability of human behavior and complex systems due to the numerous and interconnected variables at play.24. Danks, “The Psychology of Causal Perception and Reasoning,” 458.25. Loewer, “Determinism and Chance,” 612.26. Psillos, “Regularity Theories,” 132–13327. Berofsky and Mackie, “The Cement of the Universe: A Study of Causation,” 86.28. Lebow, Forbidden Fruit: Counterfactuals and International Relations, 259–28629. Nolan, “Why Historians (and Everyone Else) Should Care about Counterfactuals,” 333.30. Abel and Ofer, “Subjective Causality and Counterfactuals in the Social Sciences: Toward an Ethnographic Causality?,” 15.31. Lebow, “What’s so Different about a Counterfactual?,” 557.32. Menzies and Beebee, “Counterfactual Theories of Causation”.33. Lebow, “What’s so Different about a Counterfactual?,” 554–55534. Weber, “Counterfactuals, Past and Future,” 278.35. Lebow, Forbidden Fruit: Counterfactuals and International Relations, p. 3036. Lebow, “What’s so Different about a Counterfactual?,” 566.37. Kiser and Levi, Using Counterfactuals in Historical Analysis: Theories of Revolution., p. 18938. Kiser and Levi, Using Counterfactuals in Historical Analysis: Theories of Revolution., p. 19239. Lebow, “What’s so Different about a Counterfactual?,” 556.40. Lebow, “What’s so Different about a Counterfactual?,” 574.41. Harbecke, “Counterfactual Theories of Causation and the Problem of Large Causes,” 1652.42. Papineau, “Can We Reduce Causal Direction to Probabilities?,” 239–24043. Pearl, “Probabilities Of Causation: Three Counterfactual Interpretations And Their Identification,” 94.44. Hájek, “Probabilities of Counterfactuals and Counterfactual Probabilities,” 237.45. Longworth, “Causation, Pluralism and Responsibility,” 54.46. The Second Law of Thermodynamics is responsible for the future being uncertain. It basically describes why processes in the world are irreversible and defines why the Arrow of Time always goes forward and why the past is defined, but the future is not. In fact, this law is one of the most solid claims Science has ever made. In Einstein’s opinion, ‘the second law of thermodynamics is the only physical theory of universal content concerning which I am convinced that, within the framework of the applicability of its basic concepts, it will never be overthrown’.47. de Finetti, “Foresight: Its Logical Laws, Its Subjective Sources,” 139.48. Marrin and Torres, “Improving How to Think in Intelligence Analysis and Medicine,” 649.49. Zlotnick, ‘Bayes’ Theorem for Intelligence Analysis”.50. Marchio, “Overcoming the Inertia of ‘Old Ways of Producing Intelligence’ – the IC’s Development and Use of New Analytic Methods in the 1970s,” 990.51. Sloman, Causal Models: How People Think about the World and Its Alternatives., pp. 116–13152. Zlotnick, “A Theorem for Prediction,” 5.53. Martin and Popper, “Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach,” 276–27754. Lewis, “Postscripts to ‘Causation’,” 50.55. Jøsang, “A Logic for Uncertain Probabilities”; Jøsang, “Subjective Evidential Reasoning,” p. 282.56. Although Subjective Logic is a powerful tool, it requires considerable knowledge on Statistics and Logic. An introduction to Subjective’s Logic can be found at Subjective Logic: A Formalism for Reasoning Under Uncertainty. Subjective Logic is a solid and well-developed theory that permits complex operators in causal networks to be evaluated to determine nested causal chains, for example. Some simple calculators are available online at: https://folk.universitetetioslo.no/josang/sl/Op.html57. M. Isaksen and McNaught, “Towards a Better Framework for Estimative Intelligence – Addressing Quality through a Systematic Approach to Uncertainty Handling”.Additional informationNotes on contributorsCarles OrtolaCarles Ortola Associate Professor of Strategic Intelligence at Universitat de Barcelona and PhD Candidate at UNED (Universidad Nacional de Eduación a Distancia) in Spain.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
1.80
自引率
41.70%
发文量
93
期刊介绍: Intelligence has never played a more prominent role in international politics than it does now in the early years of the twenty-first century. National intelligence services are larger than ever, and they are more transparent in their activities in the policy making of democratic nations. Intelligence and National Security is widely regarded as the world''s leading scholarly journal focused on the role of intelligence and secretive agencies in international relations. It examines this aspect of national security from a variety of perspectives and academic disciplines, with insightful articles research and written by leading experts based around the globe. Among the topics covered in the journal are: • the historical development of intelligence agencies • representations of intelligence in popular culture • public understandings and expectations related to intelligence • intelligence and ethics • intelligence collection and analysis • covert action and counterintelligence • privacy and intelligence accountability • the outsourcing of intelligence operations • the role of politics in intelligence activities • international intelligence cooperation and burden-sharing • the relationships among intelligence agencies, military organizations, and civilian policy departments. Authors for Intelligence and National Security come from a range of disciplines, including international affairs, history, sociology, political science, law, anthropology, philosophy, medicine, statistics, psychology, bio-sciences, and mathematics. These perspectives are regularly augmented by research submitted from current and former intelligence practitioners in several different nations. Each issue features a rich menu of articles about the uses (and occasional misuses) of intelligence, supplemented from time to time with special forums on current intelligence issues and interviews with leading intelligence officials.
期刊最新文献
Ignorance, indifference, or incompetence: why are Russian covert actions so easily unmasked? The Russian hybrid intelligence state: reconceptualizing the politicization of intelligence and the ‘intelligencization’ of Politics Assessment tabling: an integrated structured analytic technique for improved intelligence analysis and reasoning visualisation Fake leads, defamation and destabilization: how online disinformation continues to impact Russia’s invasion of Ukraine Intelligence & the Russo-Ukrainian war: introduction to the special issue
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1