对基本最终价值的描述

Timothy Perrine
{"title":"对基本最终价值的描述","authors":"Timothy Perrine","doi":"10.1080/0020174x.2023.2262758","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTOrdinary and philosophical thought suggests recognizing a distinction between two ways something can be of final value. Something can be of final value in virtue of its connection to other things of value (‘non-basic final value’) or something can be of final value regardless of its connection to other things of value (‘basic final value’). The primary aim of this paper is to provide an account of this distinction. I argue that we have reason to draw this distinction as it helps avoid certain problems. I criticize accounts of this distinction due to Warren Quinn, Fred Feldman, and Michael Zimmerman. I then provide my own positive account which incorporates several of the insights of those accounts while avoiding their pitfalls. I conclude by relating my account to issues concerning partiality and appropriate attitudes.KEYWORDS: Final valuebasic final valuepro-attitudesFred FeldmanMichael Zimmerman Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.Notes1 As the examples illustrate, by things of value, I have in mind facts, events, states of affairs, or ways the world could be. I don’t have in mind specific concrete objects, like a frying pan. See fn. 3 for further relevant discussion.2 See, for instance, Brentano (Citation1902, 15f.), Ross (Citation1939, 279, 282), Ewing (Citation1947, 146ff.) Chisholm (Citation1986, 47ff.), Anderson (Citation1993, 2–3), Lemos (Citation1994, 6ff.), Scanlon (Citation1998, 78ff.), Zimmerman (Citation2001), Audi (Citation2004, 125). Merely maintaining that there is a substantive normative connection in no way identifies which property cluster is more fundamental. Further, this assumption does not require the particular kind of buck-passing popularized by Scanlon that is open to the wrong kind of reason objection. For a discussion of this last point, see Zimmerman (Citation2010).3 I focus on relationships between states of affairs of final value. Some authors might be interested in the relationships between concrete things that are of final value. For instance, Langton (Citation2007) suggests that something—e.g. a wedding ring—might be of final value but in virtue of something else—e.g., a personal relationship (see also Korsgaard (Citation1983)). These cases are sometimes called cases of ‘extrinsic final value,’ since the wedding ring is of final value, but the ‘source’ of its value is extrinsic to it. Since these cases involve individual objects, they are not the focus of my discussion. It’s an interesting question how exactly views about extrinsic final value interact with my proposals here. I don’t see any grand conflict. After all, if an object is of extrinsic final value, there’s a state of affairs about that object and its source of value that is, presumably, of final value. But I hope to explore this question in future work. For a negative view of how they might interact, see Bradley (Citation2006); for a critical discussion of extrinsic final value in general, see Tucker (Citation2016).4 The reasons are drawn from Harman (Citation1967), Feldman (Citation2000), and Zimmerman (Citation2001), though the presentation is mine. See also Moore (Citation1912, 36ff.) and Ross (Citation1930, 68ff.).5 I don’t assume that the value of complex states of affairs is always determined exclusively by the value of its parts. Nonetheless, I do assume that sometimes the value of complex states of affairs is determined at least partially by the value of its parts. Further, I do not assume that if the value of a complex state of affairs is determined by the value of its parts, then it is determined in a simple, additive way.6 For my discussion here, I want to leave open the possibility that there are some states of affairs that are not of basic value but whose value is not fully explained by states of affairs of basic value. If there are such states of affairs, then a full reckoning of the final value of a complex state of affairs—like an entire possible world—might have to be take them into consideration as well. For an opposite approach, see Feldman (Citation2000, 333) (thanks to a reviewer and Peter Finocchiaro for discussion of this topic).7 In brief, suppose S is of basic final value. From Basic Final Value 3 (b) it follows that we are not required to adopt any pro-attitudes towards any proper parts of S. Thus, from Basic Final Value 3 (a), it follows that no proper part of S is of basic final value. Suppose some proper part of S, S*, is of final value but not basic final value. On Zimmerman’s definition of final value (Citation2001, 122), S* contains some parts that are of basic final value. Given the transitivity of parthood, it would then follow that S contains a part that is of basic final value, which we already know cannot happen. Thus, no proper part of S can be of non-basic final value. Since all final value is basic or non-basic, if S is of basic final value, then no proper part of S is of any final value.8 For a fuller development of this criticism of Zimmerman, see Perrine (Citation2018).9 Ross (Citation1930, 138) thought that considerations of merit of goods and evil like pleasure and pain were relevant to their final value and disvalue. But Ross doesn’t explicitly endorse the view I describe here.10 Value conferring properties are not always less or more determinate properties of a CVCP. A value conferring property might simultaneously lack relevant information while also containing irrelevant information. (Consider, for instance, the property of experiencing some pleasure in a beer on a Tuesday.) In other words, while there are always non-CVCP on either side of the CVCP, not all non-CVCP will fit on a sliding scale with a CVCP.11 Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pressing me to address some of these issues.12 For more sophisticated accounts of this kind, see Fumerton (Citation1990, 132–2), Rønnow-Rasmussen (Citation2022, chp. 8), and Tenen (CitationForthcoming). For critical discussion, see Perrine (Citation2023).13 For related discussions, see Blanshard (Citation1961, 287–289), Lemos (Citation1994, 16–18; Citation2011); Olson (Citation2009); Bykvist (Citation2009); Zimmerman (Citation2001, 119–123; Citation2011, 472–480), Tappolet (Citation2016, 105–110), McHugh and Way (Citation2022).14 Some might posit the existence of so-called agent-relative value. It might be that the appropriateness of adopting pro- and con-attitudes is sufficient for agent-relative value, even if it is not sufficient for final value. But notice that the mere existence of agent-relative value, on its own, wouldn’t block this contradiction. One would still have to reject or modify some of these principles—presumably Final Value and Final Disvalue. For discussions of agent-relative value, see Smith, (Citation2003), Portmore (Citation2005), Schroeder (Citation2007), Wallace (Citation2010, 519ff.), Cullity (Citation2015), Johnson (Citation2021).15 Additionally, appropriateness or fittingness don’t seem emendable to the prima facie/ultimate facie distinction. So one couldn’t salvage Lemos’ view simply by replacing the property of obligation with these other properties.16 McHugh and Way (Citation2022, 254–256) offer a superficially similar response to Zimmerman. However, it is not clear that they are discussing adopting attitudes towards states of affairs. So it’s not clear that their response falls within the scope of this work.17 For helpful feedback and discussion of these issues, I thank David Fisher, Hao Hong, Noah Lemos, Nick Montgomery, Timothy O’Connor, Harrison Waldo, Phil Woodward, Michael Zimmerman as well as several anonymous reviewers for the journal.","PeriodicalId":47504,"journal":{"name":"Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0000,"publicationDate":"2023-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Towards an account of basic final value\",\"authors\":\"Timothy Perrine\",\"doi\":\"10.1080/0020174x.2023.2262758\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"ABSTRACTOrdinary and philosophical thought suggests recognizing a distinction between two ways something can be of final value. Something can be of final value in virtue of its connection to other things of value (‘non-basic final value’) or something can be of final value regardless of its connection to other things of value (‘basic final value’). The primary aim of this paper is to provide an account of this distinction. I argue that we have reason to draw this distinction as it helps avoid certain problems. I criticize accounts of this distinction due to Warren Quinn, Fred Feldman, and Michael Zimmerman. I then provide my own positive account which incorporates several of the insights of those accounts while avoiding their pitfalls. I conclude by relating my account to issues concerning partiality and appropriate attitudes.KEYWORDS: Final valuebasic final valuepro-attitudesFred FeldmanMichael Zimmerman Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.Notes1 As the examples illustrate, by things of value, I have in mind facts, events, states of affairs, or ways the world could be. I don’t have in mind specific concrete objects, like a frying pan. See fn. 3 for further relevant discussion.2 See, for instance, Brentano (Citation1902, 15f.), Ross (Citation1939, 279, 282), Ewing (Citation1947, 146ff.) Chisholm (Citation1986, 47ff.), Anderson (Citation1993, 2–3), Lemos (Citation1994, 6ff.), Scanlon (Citation1998, 78ff.), Zimmerman (Citation2001), Audi (Citation2004, 125). Merely maintaining that there is a substantive normative connection in no way identifies which property cluster is more fundamental. Further, this assumption does not require the particular kind of buck-passing popularized by Scanlon that is open to the wrong kind of reason objection. For a discussion of this last point, see Zimmerman (Citation2010).3 I focus on relationships between states of affairs of final value. Some authors might be interested in the relationships between concrete things that are of final value. For instance, Langton (Citation2007) suggests that something—e.g. a wedding ring—might be of final value but in virtue of something else—e.g., a personal relationship (see also Korsgaard (Citation1983)). These cases are sometimes called cases of ‘extrinsic final value,’ since the wedding ring is of final value, but the ‘source’ of its value is extrinsic to it. Since these cases involve individual objects, they are not the focus of my discussion. It’s an interesting question how exactly views about extrinsic final value interact with my proposals here. I don’t see any grand conflict. After all, if an object is of extrinsic final value, there’s a state of affairs about that object and its source of value that is, presumably, of final value. But I hope to explore this question in future work. For a negative view of how they might interact, see Bradley (Citation2006); for a critical discussion of extrinsic final value in general, see Tucker (Citation2016).4 The reasons are drawn from Harman (Citation1967), Feldman (Citation2000), and Zimmerman (Citation2001), though the presentation is mine. See also Moore (Citation1912, 36ff.) and Ross (Citation1930, 68ff.).5 I don’t assume that the value of complex states of affairs is always determined exclusively by the value of its parts. Nonetheless, I do assume that sometimes the value of complex states of affairs is determined at least partially by the value of its parts. Further, I do not assume that if the value of a complex state of affairs is determined by the value of its parts, then it is determined in a simple, additive way.6 For my discussion here, I want to leave open the possibility that there are some states of affairs that are not of basic value but whose value is not fully explained by states of affairs of basic value. If there are such states of affairs, then a full reckoning of the final value of a complex state of affairs—like an entire possible world—might have to be take them into consideration as well. For an opposite approach, see Feldman (Citation2000, 333) (thanks to a reviewer and Peter Finocchiaro for discussion of this topic).7 In brief, suppose S is of basic final value. From Basic Final Value 3 (b) it follows that we are not required to adopt any pro-attitudes towards any proper parts of S. Thus, from Basic Final Value 3 (a), it follows that no proper part of S is of basic final value. Suppose some proper part of S, S*, is of final value but not basic final value. On Zimmerman’s definition of final value (Citation2001, 122), S* contains some parts that are of basic final value. Given the transitivity of parthood, it would then follow that S contains a part that is of basic final value, which we already know cannot happen. Thus, no proper part of S can be of non-basic final value. Since all final value is basic or non-basic, if S is of basic final value, then no proper part of S is of any final value.8 For a fuller development of this criticism of Zimmerman, see Perrine (Citation2018).9 Ross (Citation1930, 138) thought that considerations of merit of goods and evil like pleasure and pain were relevant to their final value and disvalue. But Ross doesn’t explicitly endorse the view I describe here.10 Value conferring properties are not always less or more determinate properties of a CVCP. A value conferring property might simultaneously lack relevant information while also containing irrelevant information. (Consider, for instance, the property of experiencing some pleasure in a beer on a Tuesday.) In other words, while there are always non-CVCP on either side of the CVCP, not all non-CVCP will fit on a sliding scale with a CVCP.11 Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pressing me to address some of these issues.12 For more sophisticated accounts of this kind, see Fumerton (Citation1990, 132–2), Rønnow-Rasmussen (Citation2022, chp. 8), and Tenen (CitationForthcoming). For critical discussion, see Perrine (Citation2023).13 For related discussions, see Blanshard (Citation1961, 287–289), Lemos (Citation1994, 16–18; Citation2011); Olson (Citation2009); Bykvist (Citation2009); Zimmerman (Citation2001, 119–123; Citation2011, 472–480), Tappolet (Citation2016, 105–110), McHugh and Way (Citation2022).14 Some might posit the existence of so-called agent-relative value. It might be that the appropriateness of adopting pro- and con-attitudes is sufficient for agent-relative value, even if it is not sufficient for final value. But notice that the mere existence of agent-relative value, on its own, wouldn’t block this contradiction. One would still have to reject or modify some of these principles—presumably Final Value and Final Disvalue. For discussions of agent-relative value, see Smith, (Citation2003), Portmore (Citation2005), Schroeder (Citation2007), Wallace (Citation2010, 519ff.), Cullity (Citation2015), Johnson (Citation2021).15 Additionally, appropriateness or fittingness don’t seem emendable to the prima facie/ultimate facie distinction. So one couldn’t salvage Lemos’ view simply by replacing the property of obligation with these other properties.16 McHugh and Way (Citation2022, 254–256) offer a superficially similar response to Zimmerman. However, it is not clear that they are discussing adopting attitudes towards states of affairs. So it’s not clear that their response falls within the scope of this work.17 For helpful feedback and discussion of these issues, I thank David Fisher, Hao Hong, Noah Lemos, Nick Montgomery, Timothy O’Connor, Harrison Waldo, Phil Woodward, Michael Zimmerman as well as several anonymous reviewers for the journal.\",\"PeriodicalId\":47504,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-10-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174x.2023.2262758\",\"RegionNum\":2,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"ETHICS\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174x.2023.2262758","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

普通的哲学思维意味着认识到某物具有最终价值的两种方式之间的区别。某物可以由于与其他有价值的事物的联系而具有最终价值(“非基本最终价值”),也可以由于与其他有价值的事物的联系而具有最终价值(“基本最终价值”)。本文的主要目的是提供这种区别的说明。我认为我们有理由做出这种区分,因为它有助于避免某些问题。我批评Warren Quinn, Fred Feldman和Michael Zimmerman对这种区别的描述。然后,我提供了我自己的积极的解释,其中包含了这些解释的一些见解,同时避免了它们的陷阱。最后,我将我的叙述与偏袒和适当态度的问题联系起来。关键词:最终价值基本最终价值倾向弗雷德·费尔德曼迈克尔·齐默曼披露声明作者未报告潜在利益冲突。注1:正如这些例子所说明的,我所说的有价值的东西,指的是事实、事件、事态或世界可能的样子。我脑子里没有具体的东西,比如煎锅。看到fn。3 .进行进一步的相关讨论例如,参见布伦塔诺(Citation1902, 15f.),罗斯(Citation1939, 279, 282),尤因(Citation1947, 146ff.)奇泽姆(Citation1986, 47页)、安德森(Citation1993, 2-3页)、莱莫斯(Citation1994, 6页)、斯坎隆(Citation1998, 78页)、齐默尔曼(Citation2001)、奥迪(Citation2004, 125页)。仅仅认为存在实质性的规范联系并不能确定哪个属性集群更基本。此外,这一假设并不需要斯坎伦推广的那种特别的推诿责任,这种推诿责任对错误的理性反对是开放的。关于最后一点的讨论,请参见Zimmerman (Citation2010)我关注的是具有最终价值的事物状态之间的关系。有些作者可能对具有最终价值的具体事物之间的关系感兴趣。例如,兰顿(Citation2007)认为某些东西——例如:一枚结婚戒指——可能具有最终价值,但却有其他用处——例如:(参见Korsgaard (Citation1983))。这些情况有时被称为“外在最终价值”的情况,因为结婚戒指具有最终价值,但其价值的“来源”是外在的。由于这些情况涉及单个对象,因此它们不是我讨论的重点。这是一个有趣的问题,关于外在最终价值的观点是如何与我的建议相互作用的。我看不出有什么大的冲突。毕竟,如果一个物体具有外在的最终价值,那么这个物体的状态和它的价值来源大概就是最终价值。但我希望在未来的工作中探索这个问题。关于两者如何相互作用的负面观点,请参见Bradley (Citation2006);关于外在最终价值的批判性讨论,请参见Tucker (Citation2016)原因是由哈曼(Citation1967),费尔德曼(Citation2000)和齐默尔曼(Citation2001)提出的,尽管陈述是我的。另见摩尔(Citation1912, 36页)和罗斯(Citation1930, 68页)我并不认为复杂事态的价值总是完全由其组成部分的价值决定。尽管如此,我确实认为,有时复杂事态的价值至少部分地取决于其组成部分的价值。此外,我不认为,如果一个复杂状态的价值是由其各部分的价值决定的,那么它就是以一种简单的、加性的方式决定的对于我在这里的讨论,我想保留这样一种可能性,即存在一些不具有基本价值的事物状态,但其价值并不能被具有基本价值的事物状态完全解释。如果存在这样的事件状态,那么对复杂事件状态的最终价值的全面估算——就像整个可能的世界一样——可能也必须考虑到它们。关于相反的方法,请参阅Feldman (Citation2000, 333)(感谢审稿人和Peter Finocchiaro对该主题的讨论)简而言之,假设S是基本终值。由基本终值3 (b)可知,我们不需要对S的任何固有部分采取任何亲态度。因此,由基本终值3 (a)可知,S的任何固有部分都不具有基本终值。假设S的某个固有部分S*是终值,但不是基本终值。在Zimmerman对终值的定义(Citation2001, 122)中,S*包含了一些基本终值的部分。鉴于部分的及物性,那么就可以得出S包含一个具有基本最终值的部分,我们已经知道这是不可能发生的。因此,S的固有部分不可能是非基本终值。因为所有的终值都是基本的或非基本的,如果S是基本的终值,则S的固有部分没有任何终值。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Towards an account of basic final value
ABSTRACTOrdinary and philosophical thought suggests recognizing a distinction between two ways something can be of final value. Something can be of final value in virtue of its connection to other things of value (‘non-basic final value’) or something can be of final value regardless of its connection to other things of value (‘basic final value’). The primary aim of this paper is to provide an account of this distinction. I argue that we have reason to draw this distinction as it helps avoid certain problems. I criticize accounts of this distinction due to Warren Quinn, Fred Feldman, and Michael Zimmerman. I then provide my own positive account which incorporates several of the insights of those accounts while avoiding their pitfalls. I conclude by relating my account to issues concerning partiality and appropriate attitudes.KEYWORDS: Final valuebasic final valuepro-attitudesFred FeldmanMichael Zimmerman Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.Notes1 As the examples illustrate, by things of value, I have in mind facts, events, states of affairs, or ways the world could be. I don’t have in mind specific concrete objects, like a frying pan. See fn. 3 for further relevant discussion.2 See, for instance, Brentano (Citation1902, 15f.), Ross (Citation1939, 279, 282), Ewing (Citation1947, 146ff.) Chisholm (Citation1986, 47ff.), Anderson (Citation1993, 2–3), Lemos (Citation1994, 6ff.), Scanlon (Citation1998, 78ff.), Zimmerman (Citation2001), Audi (Citation2004, 125). Merely maintaining that there is a substantive normative connection in no way identifies which property cluster is more fundamental. Further, this assumption does not require the particular kind of buck-passing popularized by Scanlon that is open to the wrong kind of reason objection. For a discussion of this last point, see Zimmerman (Citation2010).3 I focus on relationships between states of affairs of final value. Some authors might be interested in the relationships between concrete things that are of final value. For instance, Langton (Citation2007) suggests that something—e.g. a wedding ring—might be of final value but in virtue of something else—e.g., a personal relationship (see also Korsgaard (Citation1983)). These cases are sometimes called cases of ‘extrinsic final value,’ since the wedding ring is of final value, but the ‘source’ of its value is extrinsic to it. Since these cases involve individual objects, they are not the focus of my discussion. It’s an interesting question how exactly views about extrinsic final value interact with my proposals here. I don’t see any grand conflict. After all, if an object is of extrinsic final value, there’s a state of affairs about that object and its source of value that is, presumably, of final value. But I hope to explore this question in future work. For a negative view of how they might interact, see Bradley (Citation2006); for a critical discussion of extrinsic final value in general, see Tucker (Citation2016).4 The reasons are drawn from Harman (Citation1967), Feldman (Citation2000), and Zimmerman (Citation2001), though the presentation is mine. See also Moore (Citation1912, 36ff.) and Ross (Citation1930, 68ff.).5 I don’t assume that the value of complex states of affairs is always determined exclusively by the value of its parts. Nonetheless, I do assume that sometimes the value of complex states of affairs is determined at least partially by the value of its parts. Further, I do not assume that if the value of a complex state of affairs is determined by the value of its parts, then it is determined in a simple, additive way.6 For my discussion here, I want to leave open the possibility that there are some states of affairs that are not of basic value but whose value is not fully explained by states of affairs of basic value. If there are such states of affairs, then a full reckoning of the final value of a complex state of affairs—like an entire possible world—might have to be take them into consideration as well. For an opposite approach, see Feldman (Citation2000, 333) (thanks to a reviewer and Peter Finocchiaro for discussion of this topic).7 In brief, suppose S is of basic final value. From Basic Final Value 3 (b) it follows that we are not required to adopt any pro-attitudes towards any proper parts of S. Thus, from Basic Final Value 3 (a), it follows that no proper part of S is of basic final value. Suppose some proper part of S, S*, is of final value but not basic final value. On Zimmerman’s definition of final value (Citation2001, 122), S* contains some parts that are of basic final value. Given the transitivity of parthood, it would then follow that S contains a part that is of basic final value, which we already know cannot happen. Thus, no proper part of S can be of non-basic final value. Since all final value is basic or non-basic, if S is of basic final value, then no proper part of S is of any final value.8 For a fuller development of this criticism of Zimmerman, see Perrine (Citation2018).9 Ross (Citation1930, 138) thought that considerations of merit of goods and evil like pleasure and pain were relevant to their final value and disvalue. But Ross doesn’t explicitly endorse the view I describe here.10 Value conferring properties are not always less or more determinate properties of a CVCP. A value conferring property might simultaneously lack relevant information while also containing irrelevant information. (Consider, for instance, the property of experiencing some pleasure in a beer on a Tuesday.) In other words, while there are always non-CVCP on either side of the CVCP, not all non-CVCP will fit on a sliding scale with a CVCP.11 Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pressing me to address some of these issues.12 For more sophisticated accounts of this kind, see Fumerton (Citation1990, 132–2), Rønnow-Rasmussen (Citation2022, chp. 8), and Tenen (CitationForthcoming). For critical discussion, see Perrine (Citation2023).13 For related discussions, see Blanshard (Citation1961, 287–289), Lemos (Citation1994, 16–18; Citation2011); Olson (Citation2009); Bykvist (Citation2009); Zimmerman (Citation2001, 119–123; Citation2011, 472–480), Tappolet (Citation2016, 105–110), McHugh and Way (Citation2022).14 Some might posit the existence of so-called agent-relative value. It might be that the appropriateness of adopting pro- and con-attitudes is sufficient for agent-relative value, even if it is not sufficient for final value. But notice that the mere existence of agent-relative value, on its own, wouldn’t block this contradiction. One would still have to reject or modify some of these principles—presumably Final Value and Final Disvalue. For discussions of agent-relative value, see Smith, (Citation2003), Portmore (Citation2005), Schroeder (Citation2007), Wallace (Citation2010, 519ff.), Cullity (Citation2015), Johnson (Citation2021).15 Additionally, appropriateness or fittingness don’t seem emendable to the prima facie/ultimate facie distinction. So one couldn’t salvage Lemos’ view simply by replacing the property of obligation with these other properties.16 McHugh and Way (Citation2022, 254–256) offer a superficially similar response to Zimmerman. However, it is not clear that they are discussing adopting attitudes towards states of affairs. So it’s not clear that their response falls within the scope of this work.17 For helpful feedback and discussion of these issues, I thank David Fisher, Hao Hong, Noah Lemos, Nick Montgomery, Timothy O’Connor, Harrison Waldo, Phil Woodward, Michael Zimmerman as well as several anonymous reviewers for the journal.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
2.60
自引率
23.10%
发文量
144
期刊最新文献
Ordinal type theory What is priority monism? Reply to Kovacs Responses to critics A new concept of replication Precis of Amie L. Thomasson, norms and necessity
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1