弗兰西斯·培根哲学实践中的反制度

IF 0.7 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES Pub Date : 2023-03-15 DOI:10.1080/09672559.2023.2235370
Robert Miner
{"title":"弗兰西斯·培根哲学实践中的反制度","authors":"Robert Miner","doi":"10.1080/09672559.2023.2235370","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTIn this paper, I ask whether Francis Bacon constitutes a revealing exception to the modern predilection for ‘system.’ First, I consider evidence for reading Bacon as a philosopher strongly attracted toward the ideal of system. Second, I show how reflecting on Bacon’s philosophical practice can motivate an ‘anti-system‘ reading of his texts. In considering the small number of works in which Bacon explicitly discusses ‘system’ under that name (in particular, the Descriptio globi intellectualis), I clarify what is and is not meant by ‘philosophical system’ as distinct from other ideas of system (e.g. ‘system of the heavens’). Third, I draw from the Temporis Masculus Partum and Novum Organum to argue that Bacon’s doctrine of the ‘idols of the mind’ amounts to a thoroughgoing critique of system in philosophy. Fourth, I show how and why Bacon deploys the aphoristic form in Novum Organum as an alternative to system. I conclude by suggesting some ways in which an ‘anti-system’ reading of Bacon has the power to enhance our appreciation of other early modern authors who write philosophy without pretensions to system.KEYWORDS: BaconSystemAphorismMethod Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. In the second section of this paper, I acknowledge a sense in which Aristotle’s dialectical inquiries might reasonably count as a ‘system.’2. References to Bacon’s Advancement of Learning are to Bacon (Citation2000), cited in the text as ‘Advancement,’ accompanied by book, chapter and section number, and followed by page number. I have modernized most of the spellings.3. References to Bacon’s Valerius Terminus are to Bacon (Citation1864–74), The Works of Francis Bacon, edited by J. Spedding, R.L. Ellis and D.D. Heath, volume 3, cited in the text as ‘VT’ and followed by page number.4. Citations of Bacon’s De augmentis scientiarum, abbreviated to ‘DAS,’ are to Bacon (Citation1864–74), by book and chapter number, followed by one reference to page number in volume 1 (containing the Latin text) and another reference to page number in volume 4 (containing the English translation of Francis Headlam). The former references are useful not just for Bacon’s Latin, but also for Ellis’s suggestive footnotes.5. Jardine (Citation1974, 178n1). The ‘division/partition’ distinction is not, however, original to Melanchthon. As Vickers (Citation1968, 36) observes, it appears in both Cicero and Quintilian.6. Those who impose ‘system’ onto Bacon include his editors, early and recent. For James Spedding, the question is ‘how far, by what means, and with what motive, Bacon at one time wished to keep his system secret’ (Bacon Citation1864–74, vol. 1, 107). That Bacon has a system, he takes as beyond question. Graham Rees, the most recent editor of Bacon’s texts, seems equally convinced that Bacon has a ‘system.’ But the list of those who take for granted that Bacon has a system, never noticing the virtual absence of the term in his writings, is a long one. Even Ellis, despite his polymathic brilliance, could not help himself from applying the term to Bacon (see, e.g., Bacon Citation1864–74, vol. 1, 23–24).7. References to the Novum Organum are to Bacon (Citation2004), cited in both text and notes as ‘NO’ with book number and aphorism number, followed by page number. Translations of passages from NO are mostly my own, though I have occasionally used renderings that appear in Bacon (Citation1864–74), vol. 1. This translation was commissioned and corrected by Ellis and Spedding, but the actual translator preferred to remain anonymous; see Spedding’s note at Bacon (Citation1864–74), vol. 1, xiv.8. References to the Descriptio globi intellectualis are to Bacon (Citation1996), vol. 6 of The Oxford Francis Bacon, Philosophical Studies c.1611–1619, ed. Graham Rees, cited in the text as ‘DGI’ followed by page number. I have occasionally modified the renderings that appear in this volume.9. I take this formulation from e-mail correspondence with Mark Jordan, for whom it signals the sense in which Thomas Aquinas neither thinks nor writes a system.10. Therefore, despite the occurrences of systema in Bacon’s corpus, it remains true to say that Bacon’s published works contain no occurrences of either ‘system’ or ‘systema.’ I do not mean to suggest that Bacon’s cosmological speculations are irrelevant for understanding the deeper intentions of his thought. Minkov Citation2018 has many helpful suggestions for grasping the relevance of what he aptly terms ‘Bacon’s psycho-political cosmology,’ particularly as deployed in De sapientia vetorum.11. Another place attesting Bacon’s awareness of the distinction (but also connection) between ‘system of the heavens’ and ‘philosophical system’ is aphorism 62 of the Novum Organum: ‘for as on the phenomena of the heavens many hypotheses may be constructed, so likewise (and more also) many various dogmas may be set up and established on the phaenomena of philosophy’ (NO 1.62, 96).12. The four complaints: the ‘triple motion’ of the earth, the separation of sun from the company of the planets, the introduction of so much immobility into nature, the desire for the Moon to cling to the Earth as it were in Epicyclo (see DGI 121–23).13. The polymath Robert Leslie Ellis, who edited parts of Bacon’s works, ruefully comments: ‘No man less deserved to be spoken of as a merely calculating astronomer’ (Bacon Citation1864–74, vol. 3, 740n1).14. References to the Temporis Partus Masculus are to the Latin text as it appears in Bacon (Citation1864–74), vol. 3, hereafter cited as ‘TPM.’ Readers will benefit from the new translation of the TPM scheduled to appear in volume V of the Oxford Francis Bacon, Early Philosophical Writings to c.1611, ed. Rhodri Lewis, Sophie Weeks and Daniel Andersson. The translations that appear in Farrington (Citation1964) sometimes hit the mark, but they are not always reliable. Except where indicated, I have made my own translations of passages from the TPM.15. To call Bacon himself a stuprator would be a gross libel. Nevertheless, one can observe that in his Brief Lives, Aubrey writes: ‘He was a παιδεραστἠς’ (Citation1898, 71). Read in context, it seems doubtful that Aubrey meant this description as an attack. Just one page earlier, we learn that ‘all that were great and good loved and honoured him.’16. Compare Nietzsche, Human, All Too Human sec.9 on the prestige and domination of ‘the very worst methods, not the very best’ (Citation1996, 15). A very ‘Baconian’ passage appears in an 1884 notebook entry: ‘It is something childish or even a kind of deceit when a thinker presents a whole of knowledge, a system—we are too clever not to harbor the deepest doubts about the possibility of such a whole. It is enough if we agree on a whole of premises of method—on ‘preliminary truths’ by which to work, as the navigator in the sea adheres to a certain direction’ (Citation2009, Spring 1884, 25[449]; the entry is titled ‘Die vorläufigen Wahrheiten’ [‘The preliminary truths’]).17. A point made compellingly by Weeks (Citation2019).18. Here I use the translation of Weeks (Citation2019, 33).19. Here I adopt Farrington’s rendering (Citation1964, 64). But more literally: ‘invented a variety of things from their nothings.’20. Farrington’s rendering. More literally, ‘leveled things into a wilderness of nothings.’21. Farrington’s rendering (not literal, but it captures the spirit aptly).22. For helpful perspective on the occasional use of ‘system’ (along with ratio and via) as a synonym for methodus, see Zagorin (Citation1998, 52).23. Compare what Bacon says in the Advancement of Learning: ‘There is a seducement that worketh by the strength of the impression, and not by the subtilty of the illaqueation; not so much perplexing the reason, as overruling it by power of the imagination’ (Advancement 2.14.8, 394).24. See, for example, Bacon’s favorable allusion to the Phaedrus in part 2 of Novum Organum (NO 2.26, 288).25. Bacon is clear that the division of idols into classes is only for pedagogical convenience, given ‘for the sake of teaching’ (docendi gratia: NO 1.39, 78).26. A notebook entry that illuminates what Nietzsche might mean by describing Bacon as a ‘realist’ reads: ‘Idealists—e.g. in the sky, the measure, the order, the tremendous kind of system and simplicity, shuddering admiring, put things far away, ignore the individual. The realists want the opposite shudder, that of the innumerable many: that is why they overwhelm the foreground, their enjoyment is the belief in the superabundance of creative powers, the impossibility of being able to count’ (Nietzsche Citation2009, 1884.25[195]).27. That is, Pope Alexander VI.28. For a helpful discussion of the contrast between ‘magistral’ and ‘initiative’ discourse, see Jardine (Citation1974, 174–178).29. As Crilly (Citation2022, 100) observes in a fascinating chapter on Bacon’s most brilliant editor, Robert Leslie Ellis attributes the following remark to Bacon: ‘When knowledge is systemized it is less likely to increase than before.’ Unfortunately, I have not succeeded in locating these exact words (or the Latin they might translate) anywhere in Bacon’s corpus. For Ellis’s attribution to the maxim to Bacon, see pp. 34–35 of his 1846 report to the British Association for the Advancement of Science, accessible at www.biodiversitylibrary.org/item/4663530. See, for example, Melzer (Citation2014, 317).31. Vickers in Bacon (Citation1999, xvii), quoted in Weeks (Citation2019, 11n51).32. A point suggested by Vickers himself when he speaks of ‘the formulation of téchnai, ‘arts’ or systems generally’ (Citation1968, 35). But what do we gain by conflating ‘techne’ with ‘system,’ especially when the interpretation of a philosophical text is at stake? The conflation might be more excusable in other contexts, e.g. a technical workplace in which problem-solvers might speak indifferently of systems, techniques, or methods (cf. my first sense of ‘system’ in section two). A more recent instance of confusion generated by equivocating on ‘system’ appears in Andrew Hui’s otherwise helpful discussion of Bacon’s use of the aphorism. Within a single paragraph, Hui (Citation2019, 19) suggests both that Bacon has a system (‘Bacon looks forward in forging a modern system of natural history’) and that he does not have a system (‘Method, order, and systems are basically anticoncepts for Bacon, Pascal and Nietzsche’).33. As Mark Jordan observes, a list of thinkers in the history of ethics unconstrained by ‘academic notions of philosophy’ might easily ‘see Samuel Johnson as the leading moral philosopher writing in English’ (Citation1992, 503n32).34. For an illuminating assessment of efforts to expand the canon of early modern philosophy to include women philosophers, see O’Neill (Citation2005). As O’Neill notes, a large contributing factor to the exclusion of women from the philosophical canon is the habit of ‘taking Kantianism as the culmination of early modern philosophy and as providing the project for all future philosophy inquiry,’ one that viewed ‘treatments of ‘the woman question’ as a precritical issue of purely anthropological interest. So, by the nineteenth century, much of the published material by women once deemed philosophical no longer seemed so’ (186). O’Neill gives a useful survey of progress made from 1992 to 2005 in producing more and better editions of texts by women philosophers. For a more recent assessment of ways to overcome the hold of the figures who have tended to dominate the main canon of modern philosophy, see Shapiro (Citation2016).","PeriodicalId":51828,"journal":{"name":"INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2023-03-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Anti-System in the Philosophical Practice of Francis Bacon\",\"authors\":\"Robert Miner\",\"doi\":\"10.1080/09672559.2023.2235370\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"ABSTRACTIn this paper, I ask whether Francis Bacon constitutes a revealing exception to the modern predilection for ‘system.’ First, I consider evidence for reading Bacon as a philosopher strongly attracted toward the ideal of system. Second, I show how reflecting on Bacon’s philosophical practice can motivate an ‘anti-system‘ reading of his texts. In considering the small number of works in which Bacon explicitly discusses ‘system’ under that name (in particular, the Descriptio globi intellectualis), I clarify what is and is not meant by ‘philosophical system’ as distinct from other ideas of system (e.g. ‘system of the heavens’). Third, I draw from the Temporis Masculus Partum and Novum Organum to argue that Bacon’s doctrine of the ‘idols of the mind’ amounts to a thoroughgoing critique of system in philosophy. Fourth, I show how and why Bacon deploys the aphoristic form in Novum Organum as an alternative to system. I conclude by suggesting some ways in which an ‘anti-system’ reading of Bacon has the power to enhance our appreciation of other early modern authors who write philosophy without pretensions to system.KEYWORDS: BaconSystemAphorismMethod Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. In the second section of this paper, I acknowledge a sense in which Aristotle’s dialectical inquiries might reasonably count as a ‘system.’2. References to Bacon’s Advancement of Learning are to Bacon (Citation2000), cited in the text as ‘Advancement,’ accompanied by book, chapter and section number, and followed by page number. I have modernized most of the spellings.3. References to Bacon’s Valerius Terminus are to Bacon (Citation1864–74), The Works of Francis Bacon, edited by J. Spedding, R.L. Ellis and D.D. Heath, volume 3, cited in the text as ‘VT’ and followed by page number.4. Citations of Bacon’s De augmentis scientiarum, abbreviated to ‘DAS,’ are to Bacon (Citation1864–74), by book and chapter number, followed by one reference to page number in volume 1 (containing the Latin text) and another reference to page number in volume 4 (containing the English translation of Francis Headlam). The former references are useful not just for Bacon’s Latin, but also for Ellis’s suggestive footnotes.5. Jardine (Citation1974, 178n1). The ‘division/partition’ distinction is not, however, original to Melanchthon. As Vickers (Citation1968, 36) observes, it appears in both Cicero and Quintilian.6. Those who impose ‘system’ onto Bacon include his editors, early and recent. For James Spedding, the question is ‘how far, by what means, and with what motive, Bacon at one time wished to keep his system secret’ (Bacon Citation1864–74, vol. 1, 107). That Bacon has a system, he takes as beyond question. Graham Rees, the most recent editor of Bacon’s texts, seems equally convinced that Bacon has a ‘system.’ But the list of those who take for granted that Bacon has a system, never noticing the virtual absence of the term in his writings, is a long one. Even Ellis, despite his polymathic brilliance, could not help himself from applying the term to Bacon (see, e.g., Bacon Citation1864–74, vol. 1, 23–24).7. References to the Novum Organum are to Bacon (Citation2004), cited in both text and notes as ‘NO’ with book number and aphorism number, followed by page number. Translations of passages from NO are mostly my own, though I have occasionally used renderings that appear in Bacon (Citation1864–74), vol. 1. This translation was commissioned and corrected by Ellis and Spedding, but the actual translator preferred to remain anonymous; see Spedding’s note at Bacon (Citation1864–74), vol. 1, xiv.8. References to the Descriptio globi intellectualis are to Bacon (Citation1996), vol. 6 of The Oxford Francis Bacon, Philosophical Studies c.1611–1619, ed. Graham Rees, cited in the text as ‘DGI’ followed by page number. I have occasionally modified the renderings that appear in this volume.9. I take this formulation from e-mail correspondence with Mark Jordan, for whom it signals the sense in which Thomas Aquinas neither thinks nor writes a system.10. Therefore, despite the occurrences of systema in Bacon’s corpus, it remains true to say that Bacon’s published works contain no occurrences of either ‘system’ or ‘systema.’ I do not mean to suggest that Bacon’s cosmological speculations are irrelevant for understanding the deeper intentions of his thought. Minkov Citation2018 has many helpful suggestions for grasping the relevance of what he aptly terms ‘Bacon’s psycho-political cosmology,’ particularly as deployed in De sapientia vetorum.11. Another place attesting Bacon’s awareness of the distinction (but also connection) between ‘system of the heavens’ and ‘philosophical system’ is aphorism 62 of the Novum Organum: ‘for as on the phenomena of the heavens many hypotheses may be constructed, so likewise (and more also) many various dogmas may be set up and established on the phaenomena of philosophy’ (NO 1.62, 96).12. The four complaints: the ‘triple motion’ of the earth, the separation of sun from the company of the planets, the introduction of so much immobility into nature, the desire for the Moon to cling to the Earth as it were in Epicyclo (see DGI 121–23).13. The polymath Robert Leslie Ellis, who edited parts of Bacon’s works, ruefully comments: ‘No man less deserved to be spoken of as a merely calculating astronomer’ (Bacon Citation1864–74, vol. 3, 740n1).14. References to the Temporis Partus Masculus are to the Latin text as it appears in Bacon (Citation1864–74), vol. 3, hereafter cited as ‘TPM.’ Readers will benefit from the new translation of the TPM scheduled to appear in volume V of the Oxford Francis Bacon, Early Philosophical Writings to c.1611, ed. Rhodri Lewis, Sophie Weeks and Daniel Andersson. The translations that appear in Farrington (Citation1964) sometimes hit the mark, but they are not always reliable. Except where indicated, I have made my own translations of passages from the TPM.15. To call Bacon himself a stuprator would be a gross libel. Nevertheless, one can observe that in his Brief Lives, Aubrey writes: ‘He was a παιδεραστἠς’ (Citation1898, 71). Read in context, it seems doubtful that Aubrey meant this description as an attack. Just one page earlier, we learn that ‘all that were great and good loved and honoured him.’16. Compare Nietzsche, Human, All Too Human sec.9 on the prestige and domination of ‘the very worst methods, not the very best’ (Citation1996, 15). A very ‘Baconian’ passage appears in an 1884 notebook entry: ‘It is something childish or even a kind of deceit when a thinker presents a whole of knowledge, a system—we are too clever not to harbor the deepest doubts about the possibility of such a whole. It is enough if we agree on a whole of premises of method—on ‘preliminary truths’ by which to work, as the navigator in the sea adheres to a certain direction’ (Citation2009, Spring 1884, 25[449]; the entry is titled ‘Die vorläufigen Wahrheiten’ [‘The preliminary truths’]).17. A point made compellingly by Weeks (Citation2019).18. Here I use the translation of Weeks (Citation2019, 33).19. Here I adopt Farrington’s rendering (Citation1964, 64). But more literally: ‘invented a variety of things from their nothings.’20. Farrington’s rendering. More literally, ‘leveled things into a wilderness of nothings.’21. Farrington’s rendering (not literal, but it captures the spirit aptly).22. For helpful perspective on the occasional use of ‘system’ (along with ratio and via) as a synonym for methodus, see Zagorin (Citation1998, 52).23. Compare what Bacon says in the Advancement of Learning: ‘There is a seducement that worketh by the strength of the impression, and not by the subtilty of the illaqueation; not so much perplexing the reason, as overruling it by power of the imagination’ (Advancement 2.14.8, 394).24. See, for example, Bacon’s favorable allusion to the Phaedrus in part 2 of Novum Organum (NO 2.26, 288).25. Bacon is clear that the division of idols into classes is only for pedagogical convenience, given ‘for the sake of teaching’ (docendi gratia: NO 1.39, 78).26. A notebook entry that illuminates what Nietzsche might mean by describing Bacon as a ‘realist’ reads: ‘Idealists—e.g. in the sky, the measure, the order, the tremendous kind of system and simplicity, shuddering admiring, put things far away, ignore the individual. The realists want the opposite shudder, that of the innumerable many: that is why they overwhelm the foreground, their enjoyment is the belief in the superabundance of creative powers, the impossibility of being able to count’ (Nietzsche Citation2009, 1884.25[195]).27. That is, Pope Alexander VI.28. For a helpful discussion of the contrast between ‘magistral’ and ‘initiative’ discourse, see Jardine (Citation1974, 174–178).29. As Crilly (Citation2022, 100) observes in a fascinating chapter on Bacon’s most brilliant editor, Robert Leslie Ellis attributes the following remark to Bacon: ‘When knowledge is systemized it is less likely to increase than before.’ Unfortunately, I have not succeeded in locating these exact words (or the Latin they might translate) anywhere in Bacon’s corpus. For Ellis’s attribution to the maxim to Bacon, see pp. 34–35 of his 1846 report to the British Association for the Advancement of Science, accessible at www.biodiversitylibrary.org/item/4663530. See, for example, Melzer (Citation2014, 317).31. Vickers in Bacon (Citation1999, xvii), quoted in Weeks (Citation2019, 11n51).32. A point suggested by Vickers himself when he speaks of ‘the formulation of téchnai, ‘arts’ or systems generally’ (Citation1968, 35). But what do we gain by conflating ‘techne’ with ‘system,’ especially when the interpretation of a philosophical text is at stake? The conflation might be more excusable in other contexts, e.g. a technical workplace in which problem-solvers might speak indifferently of systems, techniques, or methods (cf. my first sense of ‘system’ in section two). A more recent instance of confusion generated by equivocating on ‘system’ appears in Andrew Hui’s otherwise helpful discussion of Bacon’s use of the aphorism. Within a single paragraph, Hui (Citation2019, 19) suggests both that Bacon has a system (‘Bacon looks forward in forging a modern system of natural history’) and that he does not have a system (‘Method, order, and systems are basically anticoncepts for Bacon, Pascal and Nietzsche’).33. As Mark Jordan observes, a list of thinkers in the history of ethics unconstrained by ‘academic notions of philosophy’ might easily ‘see Samuel Johnson as the leading moral philosopher writing in English’ (Citation1992, 503n32).34. For an illuminating assessment of efforts to expand the canon of early modern philosophy to include women philosophers, see O’Neill (Citation2005). As O’Neill notes, a large contributing factor to the exclusion of women from the philosophical canon is the habit of ‘taking Kantianism as the culmination of early modern philosophy and as providing the project for all future philosophy inquiry,’ one that viewed ‘treatments of ‘the woman question’ as a precritical issue of purely anthropological interest. So, by the nineteenth century, much of the published material by women once deemed philosophical no longer seemed so’ (186). O’Neill gives a useful survey of progress made from 1992 to 2005 in producing more and better editions of texts by women philosophers. For a more recent assessment of ways to overcome the hold of the figures who have tended to dominate the main canon of modern philosophy, see Shapiro (Citation2016).\",\"PeriodicalId\":51828,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.7000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-03-15\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1080/09672559.2023.2235370\",\"RegionNum\":3,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"PHILOSOPHY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/09672559.2023.2235370","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

在本文中,我提出了一个问题:弗朗西斯·培根是否构成了现代对“系统”偏爱的一个具有启发性的例外?首先,我认为有证据表明培根是一位被系统理想强烈吸引的哲学家。其次,我展示了反思培根的哲学实践如何激发对他的文本的“反系统”阅读。考虑到培根在少数著作中明确地以这个名字讨论了“系统”(特别是《全球知性描述》),我澄清了“哲学系统”与其他系统概念(例如“天堂系统”)不同的含义。第三,我从《男性产期》和《新事物》中得出结论,认为培根的“心灵偶像”学说是对哲学体系的彻底批判。第四,我展示了培根如何以及为什么在《新事物》中使用警句形式作为系统的替代品。最后,我提出了一些对培根的“反体系”阅读的方法,这些方法有能力增强我们对其他早期现代作家的欣赏,这些作家写哲学时不以体系为前提。关键词:培根系统格言方法披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。在本文的第二部分,我承认在某种意义上,亚里士多德的辩证研究可以合理地算作一个“系统”。参考培根的《学习的进步》(Citation2000),在文本中引用为“进步”,伴随着书,章节和节号,然后是页码。我把大部分拼写都现代化了。参考培根的Valerius Terminus是Bacon (Citation1864-74),弗朗西斯·培根的作品,由J. Spedding, R.L. Ellis和D.D. Heath编辑,卷3,在文本中引用为“VT”,后面是页码4。引用培根的De augmentis scientiarum,缩写为“DAS”,是对培根(Citation1864-74)的引用,按书和章节编号,然后参考第一卷的页码(包含拉丁文本),另一个参考第四卷的页码(包含弗朗西斯·海德拉姆的英文翻译)。前面的参考文献不仅对培根的拉丁文有用,而且对埃利斯的暗示性脚注也有用。怡和(Citation1974, 1781)。然而,“划分/分割”的区别并不是梅兰希顿的独创。正如维克斯(引文1968,36)所观察到的,它出现在西塞罗和昆提连的著作中。那些把“系统”强加给培根的人包括他早期和最近的编辑们。对于James Spedding来说,问题是“培根曾经希望在多大程度上,以什么方式,以及出于什么动机,将他的体系保密”(Bacon Citation1864-74, vol. 1, 107)。培根有一套体系,他认为这是毋庸置疑的。最近的培根文本编辑格雷厄姆·里斯(Graham Rees)似乎同样相信培根有一套“体系”。但是,那些想当然地认为培根有一套体系的人,却从未注意到他的作品中几乎没有这个词,他们的名单很长。即使是埃利斯,尽管他的博学才华,也忍不住把这个词用在培根身上(例如,参见Bacon Citation1864-74, vol. 1, 23-24)。参考文献Novum Organum是指培根(Citation2004),在文本和注释中都以“NO”的形式引用,后面是书号和格言号,然后是页码。《NO》中的段落大多是我自己翻译的,尽管我偶尔也会使用培根(Citation1864-74)第1卷中的译文。这篇翻译是由埃利斯和斯佩丁委托并修改的,但实际的译者希望保持匿名;参见Spedding对Bacon的注解(Citation1864-74),卷1,xiv.8。《全球知识分子描述》的参考文献是《牛津弗朗西斯·培根哲学研究》第6卷《培根》(Citation1996),格雷厄姆·里斯编辑,1611 - 1619年,文中引用的是“DGI”,后面跟着页码。我偶尔会修改本卷中出现的效果图。我从与马克·乔丹的电子邮件通信中得到了这个提法,对他来说,这表明托马斯·阿奎那既不思考也不写一个系统。因此,尽管systema在培根的语料库中出现,但培根发表的作品中没有出现“system”或“systema”,这仍然是正确的。我并不是说培根的宇宙学推测与理解其思想的深层意图无关。Minkov Citation2018有许多有用的建议,可以帮助我们理解他恰当地称之为“培根的心理-政治宇宙论”的相关性,特别是在《论智慧》一书中。另一个证明培根意识到“天堂体系”和“哲学体系”之间的区别(但也有联系)的地方是《新事物》(Novum Organum)的第62句格言:“因为就像在天堂的现象上可以建立许多假设一样,同样(而且更多),许多不同的教条可以建立在哲学现象上”(NO . 1)。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Anti-System in the Philosophical Practice of Francis Bacon
ABSTRACTIn this paper, I ask whether Francis Bacon constitutes a revealing exception to the modern predilection for ‘system.’ First, I consider evidence for reading Bacon as a philosopher strongly attracted toward the ideal of system. Second, I show how reflecting on Bacon’s philosophical practice can motivate an ‘anti-system‘ reading of his texts. In considering the small number of works in which Bacon explicitly discusses ‘system’ under that name (in particular, the Descriptio globi intellectualis), I clarify what is and is not meant by ‘philosophical system’ as distinct from other ideas of system (e.g. ‘system of the heavens’). Third, I draw from the Temporis Masculus Partum and Novum Organum to argue that Bacon’s doctrine of the ‘idols of the mind’ amounts to a thoroughgoing critique of system in philosophy. Fourth, I show how and why Bacon deploys the aphoristic form in Novum Organum as an alternative to system. I conclude by suggesting some ways in which an ‘anti-system’ reading of Bacon has the power to enhance our appreciation of other early modern authors who write philosophy without pretensions to system.KEYWORDS: BaconSystemAphorismMethod Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. In the second section of this paper, I acknowledge a sense in which Aristotle’s dialectical inquiries might reasonably count as a ‘system.’2. References to Bacon’s Advancement of Learning are to Bacon (Citation2000), cited in the text as ‘Advancement,’ accompanied by book, chapter and section number, and followed by page number. I have modernized most of the spellings.3. References to Bacon’s Valerius Terminus are to Bacon (Citation1864–74), The Works of Francis Bacon, edited by J. Spedding, R.L. Ellis and D.D. Heath, volume 3, cited in the text as ‘VT’ and followed by page number.4. Citations of Bacon’s De augmentis scientiarum, abbreviated to ‘DAS,’ are to Bacon (Citation1864–74), by book and chapter number, followed by one reference to page number in volume 1 (containing the Latin text) and another reference to page number in volume 4 (containing the English translation of Francis Headlam). The former references are useful not just for Bacon’s Latin, but also for Ellis’s suggestive footnotes.5. Jardine (Citation1974, 178n1). The ‘division/partition’ distinction is not, however, original to Melanchthon. As Vickers (Citation1968, 36) observes, it appears in both Cicero and Quintilian.6. Those who impose ‘system’ onto Bacon include his editors, early and recent. For James Spedding, the question is ‘how far, by what means, and with what motive, Bacon at one time wished to keep his system secret’ (Bacon Citation1864–74, vol. 1, 107). That Bacon has a system, he takes as beyond question. Graham Rees, the most recent editor of Bacon’s texts, seems equally convinced that Bacon has a ‘system.’ But the list of those who take for granted that Bacon has a system, never noticing the virtual absence of the term in his writings, is a long one. Even Ellis, despite his polymathic brilliance, could not help himself from applying the term to Bacon (see, e.g., Bacon Citation1864–74, vol. 1, 23–24).7. References to the Novum Organum are to Bacon (Citation2004), cited in both text and notes as ‘NO’ with book number and aphorism number, followed by page number. Translations of passages from NO are mostly my own, though I have occasionally used renderings that appear in Bacon (Citation1864–74), vol. 1. This translation was commissioned and corrected by Ellis and Spedding, but the actual translator preferred to remain anonymous; see Spedding’s note at Bacon (Citation1864–74), vol. 1, xiv.8. References to the Descriptio globi intellectualis are to Bacon (Citation1996), vol. 6 of The Oxford Francis Bacon, Philosophical Studies c.1611–1619, ed. Graham Rees, cited in the text as ‘DGI’ followed by page number. I have occasionally modified the renderings that appear in this volume.9. I take this formulation from e-mail correspondence with Mark Jordan, for whom it signals the sense in which Thomas Aquinas neither thinks nor writes a system.10. Therefore, despite the occurrences of systema in Bacon’s corpus, it remains true to say that Bacon’s published works contain no occurrences of either ‘system’ or ‘systema.’ I do not mean to suggest that Bacon’s cosmological speculations are irrelevant for understanding the deeper intentions of his thought. Minkov Citation2018 has many helpful suggestions for grasping the relevance of what he aptly terms ‘Bacon’s psycho-political cosmology,’ particularly as deployed in De sapientia vetorum.11. Another place attesting Bacon’s awareness of the distinction (but also connection) between ‘system of the heavens’ and ‘philosophical system’ is aphorism 62 of the Novum Organum: ‘for as on the phenomena of the heavens many hypotheses may be constructed, so likewise (and more also) many various dogmas may be set up and established on the phaenomena of philosophy’ (NO 1.62, 96).12. The four complaints: the ‘triple motion’ of the earth, the separation of sun from the company of the planets, the introduction of so much immobility into nature, the desire for the Moon to cling to the Earth as it were in Epicyclo (see DGI 121–23).13. The polymath Robert Leslie Ellis, who edited parts of Bacon’s works, ruefully comments: ‘No man less deserved to be spoken of as a merely calculating astronomer’ (Bacon Citation1864–74, vol. 3, 740n1).14. References to the Temporis Partus Masculus are to the Latin text as it appears in Bacon (Citation1864–74), vol. 3, hereafter cited as ‘TPM.’ Readers will benefit from the new translation of the TPM scheduled to appear in volume V of the Oxford Francis Bacon, Early Philosophical Writings to c.1611, ed. Rhodri Lewis, Sophie Weeks and Daniel Andersson. The translations that appear in Farrington (Citation1964) sometimes hit the mark, but they are not always reliable. Except where indicated, I have made my own translations of passages from the TPM.15. To call Bacon himself a stuprator would be a gross libel. Nevertheless, one can observe that in his Brief Lives, Aubrey writes: ‘He was a παιδεραστἠς’ (Citation1898, 71). Read in context, it seems doubtful that Aubrey meant this description as an attack. Just one page earlier, we learn that ‘all that were great and good loved and honoured him.’16. Compare Nietzsche, Human, All Too Human sec.9 on the prestige and domination of ‘the very worst methods, not the very best’ (Citation1996, 15). A very ‘Baconian’ passage appears in an 1884 notebook entry: ‘It is something childish or even a kind of deceit when a thinker presents a whole of knowledge, a system—we are too clever not to harbor the deepest doubts about the possibility of such a whole. It is enough if we agree on a whole of premises of method—on ‘preliminary truths’ by which to work, as the navigator in the sea adheres to a certain direction’ (Citation2009, Spring 1884, 25[449]; the entry is titled ‘Die vorläufigen Wahrheiten’ [‘The preliminary truths’]).17. A point made compellingly by Weeks (Citation2019).18. Here I use the translation of Weeks (Citation2019, 33).19. Here I adopt Farrington’s rendering (Citation1964, 64). But more literally: ‘invented a variety of things from their nothings.’20. Farrington’s rendering. More literally, ‘leveled things into a wilderness of nothings.’21. Farrington’s rendering (not literal, but it captures the spirit aptly).22. For helpful perspective on the occasional use of ‘system’ (along with ratio and via) as a synonym for methodus, see Zagorin (Citation1998, 52).23. Compare what Bacon says in the Advancement of Learning: ‘There is a seducement that worketh by the strength of the impression, and not by the subtilty of the illaqueation; not so much perplexing the reason, as overruling it by power of the imagination’ (Advancement 2.14.8, 394).24. See, for example, Bacon’s favorable allusion to the Phaedrus in part 2 of Novum Organum (NO 2.26, 288).25. Bacon is clear that the division of idols into classes is only for pedagogical convenience, given ‘for the sake of teaching’ (docendi gratia: NO 1.39, 78).26. A notebook entry that illuminates what Nietzsche might mean by describing Bacon as a ‘realist’ reads: ‘Idealists—e.g. in the sky, the measure, the order, the tremendous kind of system and simplicity, shuddering admiring, put things far away, ignore the individual. The realists want the opposite shudder, that of the innumerable many: that is why they overwhelm the foreground, their enjoyment is the belief in the superabundance of creative powers, the impossibility of being able to count’ (Nietzsche Citation2009, 1884.25[195]).27. That is, Pope Alexander VI.28. For a helpful discussion of the contrast between ‘magistral’ and ‘initiative’ discourse, see Jardine (Citation1974, 174–178).29. As Crilly (Citation2022, 100) observes in a fascinating chapter on Bacon’s most brilliant editor, Robert Leslie Ellis attributes the following remark to Bacon: ‘When knowledge is systemized it is less likely to increase than before.’ Unfortunately, I have not succeeded in locating these exact words (or the Latin they might translate) anywhere in Bacon’s corpus. For Ellis’s attribution to the maxim to Bacon, see pp. 34–35 of his 1846 report to the British Association for the Advancement of Science, accessible at www.biodiversitylibrary.org/item/4663530. See, for example, Melzer (Citation2014, 317).31. Vickers in Bacon (Citation1999, xvii), quoted in Weeks (Citation2019, 11n51).32. A point suggested by Vickers himself when he speaks of ‘the formulation of téchnai, ‘arts’ or systems generally’ (Citation1968, 35). But what do we gain by conflating ‘techne’ with ‘system,’ especially when the interpretation of a philosophical text is at stake? The conflation might be more excusable in other contexts, e.g. a technical workplace in which problem-solvers might speak indifferently of systems, techniques, or methods (cf. my first sense of ‘system’ in section two). A more recent instance of confusion generated by equivocating on ‘system’ appears in Andrew Hui’s otherwise helpful discussion of Bacon’s use of the aphorism. Within a single paragraph, Hui (Citation2019, 19) suggests both that Bacon has a system (‘Bacon looks forward in forging a modern system of natural history’) and that he does not have a system (‘Method, order, and systems are basically anticoncepts for Bacon, Pascal and Nietzsche’).33. As Mark Jordan observes, a list of thinkers in the history of ethics unconstrained by ‘academic notions of philosophy’ might easily ‘see Samuel Johnson as the leading moral philosopher writing in English’ (Citation1992, 503n32).34. For an illuminating assessment of efforts to expand the canon of early modern philosophy to include women philosophers, see O’Neill (Citation2005). As O’Neill notes, a large contributing factor to the exclusion of women from the philosophical canon is the habit of ‘taking Kantianism as the culmination of early modern philosophy and as providing the project for all future philosophy inquiry,’ one that viewed ‘treatments of ‘the woman question’ as a precritical issue of purely anthropological interest. So, by the nineteenth century, much of the published material by women once deemed philosophical no longer seemed so’ (186). O’Neill gives a useful survey of progress made from 1992 to 2005 in producing more and better editions of texts by women philosophers. For a more recent assessment of ways to overcome the hold of the figures who have tended to dominate the main canon of modern philosophy, see Shapiro (Citation2016).
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
0.90
自引率
0.00%
发文量
29
期刊介绍: The International Journal of Philosophical Studies (IJPS) publishes academic articles of the highest quality from both analytic and continental traditions and provides a forum for publishing on a broader range of issues than is currently available in philosophical journals. IJPS also publishes annual special issues devoted to key thematic areas or to critical engagements with contemporary philosophers of note. Through its Discussion section, it provides a lively forum for exchange of ideas and encourages dialogue and mutual comprehension across all philosophical traditions. The journal also contains an extensive book review section, including occasional book symposia. It also provides Critical Notices which review major books or themes in depth.
期刊最新文献
Nietzsche and the Size of Future History as a Normative Criterion Becoming Foucault: The Poitiers Years Transgenerational Frontiers: The Capabilities Approach And the New Challenge of Justice Intuitional Content or Avoiding the Myth of the Given – A Dilemma for McDowell Ethics in the Gray Area: A Gradualist Theory of Right and Wrong Ethics in the Gray Area: A Gradualist Theory of Right and Wrong , by Martin Peterson, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2023, 236 pp., £85.00 (hbk), ISBN 9781009336789
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1