引言——回归形式

IF 0.6 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Ratio Pub Date : 2023-11-04 DOI:10.1111/rati.12394
Petter Sandstad
{"title":"引言——回归形式","authors":"Petter Sandstad","doi":"10.1111/rati.12394","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Starting roughly thirty years ago, essences and essentialism has seen a gradual rise in interest and support, not only as measured in the number of publications, but also in terms of applicability to distinct philosophical issues. This special issue showcases this wide applicability. Michail Peramatzis opens with a paper on Aristotle. On Aristotle's hylomorphism, a substance such as Socrates is made up of both material parts and a form, namely that of being a human. The issue of the paper concerns how and what makes these parts into something unified, namely Socrates. Peramatzis defends an integrated reading of Metaphysics Ζ.12, Ζ17, and Η.6, and the position that the compound's unity is derivative of the form's primitive unity. This paper will be of interest not only to scholars of Aristotle, but also to metaphysicians working on hylomorphism and the problem of unity. Naomi Thompson contributes a paper on the relatively recent topic of metaphysical explanation, namely as explanations fundamentally distinct from causal explanations, typically exemplified by the relation of grounding. Her paper provides much needed clarity on the possible antirealist positions available, explores the connections between these positions, and lays out the reasons for and against each of them. This paper will be instrumental in shaping future research on antirealist positions on metaphysical explanation. Robin Hendry defends microstructural essentialism for chemical substances: the position that the molecular structure is what determines the identity of a chemical substance. With a detailed range of examples from chemistry, Hendry explains the notion of structure, presents the arguments for microstructural essentialism, and replies to the counterarguments in the literature. In the final section, the paper discusses the Aristotelian problems of mixture, especially in the case of super-heavy elements like oganesson. Presupposing a broadly Aristotelian view, Hendry argues that oganesson the element does not exist because its characteristic nuclei does not exist long enough to exhibit the element's characteristic powers. Jessica Leech seeks to reintroduce Barcan Marcus' account of the relation between essence and necessity, that of minimal essentialism. Leech shows that Barcan Marcus, in common with several of her contemporaries in the late 60's and early 70's, did recognise the distinction, famously made by Kit Fine, between essential properties and properties that are merely necessary. Moreover, she argues that minimal essentialism is able to adequately deal with the problematic cases raised by Fine, and therefore that Barcan Marcus' account should be a serious contender in the current discussion of modality and essence. Ludger Jansen explores the applicability of essences to the social domain. He argues that essences are to be found for both social kinds and for social identities. However, these two variants exhibit essences with radically distinct characteristics. Social kinds are extrinsically constituted, namely in some historical social act, while social identities are internally constituted, namely in some mental act. And while social kinds are stable and immune to change, social identities can be replaced and changed. Jansen explores the benefits of endorsing essentialism in the social domain, and rebuts the possible objection that essentialism is dangerous because it supports oppressive social structures. Acceptance of essentialism in fact turns out to be a necessary precondition for ending these oppressive structures, by identifying the essential features of the oppressive structure, thereby pointing out how these oppressive structures can be ended. Kathrin Koslicki and Olivier Massin contribute a paper on metametaphysics. In response to the recent neo-Carnapian view that definitional disputes—for instance the what-is-F disputes found in Socratic dialogues—turn out to simply be verbal disputes (see for instance the work of Amie Thomasson), they instead argue that such disputes are typically substantive. Moreover, the resolving of such disputes presuppose an ontological commitment to essences, specifically that ‘some […] phenomena have essences, and that these essences can be rigorously studied by philosophical or scientific means.’ (Koslicki & Massin, this issue, pp. 319-333) And while the authors do not deny that there are also verbal disputes, what is typical of these cases is that instead of a single phenomenon we find out that there are two distinct phenomena, and argue that such cases require the recognition of more, not fewer, essences. Jeremy W. Skrzypek develops an account of Aristotle's hylomorphism which takes into account the insights of the recent literature on biological processualism, especially the view of Dupré. The resultant position, which Skrzypek following Mark Steen calls ‘hyloenergeism’, is able to capture these insights without abandoning the Aristotelian commitment to essences and to substances, and is argued to have further theoretical advantages compared to Dupré's position. While this is a systematic paper, at the end of the paper Skrzypek also suggests that hyloenergeism might in fact have been Aristotle's actual position. Martin Glazier presents an objection to priority monism, which is the position recently defended by Jonathan Schaffer that there is only one substance, viz. the whole cosmos. The objection is that priority monism violates the basic tenet that every substance is necessarily a substance, because it turns out that the cosmos is not necessarily a substance, and thus that priority monism is false. Glazier discusses Schaffer's three arguments, and shows that neither justifies a rejection of the tenet that every substance is necessarily a substance. Further, Glazier shows that this tenet poses a problem for a distinct issue, namely what Schaffer calls the ‘Aristotelian principle’: that no substance is composed of substances. Finally, the pluralist position that there are many substances, viz. mereological simples, is argued to not violate the tenet that every substance is necessarily a substance. Of the papers in this issue, four were presented at the annual Ratio conference 2022. This was organised as a hybrid conference, with 18 live and 24 virtual participants registered. Robin Hendry, Michail Peramatzis, and Naomi Thompson presented their papers in Reading, while Ludger Jansen did his presentation remotely. Once more I want to thank the speakers, the participants, the staff and caterers involved, and especially David Oderberg, for making the event run smoothly and successfully. The other four papers, by Martin Glazier, Kathrin Koslicki & Olivier Massin, Jessica Leech, and Jeremy W. Skrzypek, were commissioned for this special issue. Both the Ratio conference and my own position while organising and editing this issue, was funded by the European commision through my MSCA individual fellowship, Formal Causation: Rivals and Extensions (FCRE 101028122).","PeriodicalId":46553,"journal":{"name":"Ratio","volume":"7 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6000,"publicationDate":"2023-11-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Introduction—A return to form\",\"authors\":\"Petter Sandstad\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/rati.12394\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Starting roughly thirty years ago, essences and essentialism has seen a gradual rise in interest and support, not only as measured in the number of publications, but also in terms of applicability to distinct philosophical issues. This special issue showcases this wide applicability. Michail Peramatzis opens with a paper on Aristotle. On Aristotle's hylomorphism, a substance such as Socrates is made up of both material parts and a form, namely that of being a human. The issue of the paper concerns how and what makes these parts into something unified, namely Socrates. Peramatzis defends an integrated reading of Metaphysics Ζ.12, Ζ17, and Η.6, and the position that the compound's unity is derivative of the form's primitive unity. This paper will be of interest not only to scholars of Aristotle, but also to metaphysicians working on hylomorphism and the problem of unity. Naomi Thompson contributes a paper on the relatively recent topic of metaphysical explanation, namely as explanations fundamentally distinct from causal explanations, typically exemplified by the relation of grounding. Her paper provides much needed clarity on the possible antirealist positions available, explores the connections between these positions, and lays out the reasons for and against each of them. This paper will be instrumental in shaping future research on antirealist positions on metaphysical explanation. Robin Hendry defends microstructural essentialism for chemical substances: the position that the molecular structure is what determines the identity of a chemical substance. With a detailed range of examples from chemistry, Hendry explains the notion of structure, presents the arguments for microstructural essentialism, and replies to the counterarguments in the literature. In the final section, the paper discusses the Aristotelian problems of mixture, especially in the case of super-heavy elements like oganesson. Presupposing a broadly Aristotelian view, Hendry argues that oganesson the element does not exist because its characteristic nuclei does not exist long enough to exhibit the element's characteristic powers. Jessica Leech seeks to reintroduce Barcan Marcus' account of the relation between essence and necessity, that of minimal essentialism. Leech shows that Barcan Marcus, in common with several of her contemporaries in the late 60's and early 70's, did recognise the distinction, famously made by Kit Fine, between essential properties and properties that are merely necessary. Moreover, she argues that minimal essentialism is able to adequately deal with the problematic cases raised by Fine, and therefore that Barcan Marcus' account should be a serious contender in the current discussion of modality and essence. Ludger Jansen explores the applicability of essences to the social domain. He argues that essences are to be found for both social kinds and for social identities. However, these two variants exhibit essences with radically distinct characteristics. Social kinds are extrinsically constituted, namely in some historical social act, while social identities are internally constituted, namely in some mental act. And while social kinds are stable and immune to change, social identities can be replaced and changed. Jansen explores the benefits of endorsing essentialism in the social domain, and rebuts the possible objection that essentialism is dangerous because it supports oppressive social structures. Acceptance of essentialism in fact turns out to be a necessary precondition for ending these oppressive structures, by identifying the essential features of the oppressive structure, thereby pointing out how these oppressive structures can be ended. Kathrin Koslicki and Olivier Massin contribute a paper on metametaphysics. In response to the recent neo-Carnapian view that definitional disputes—for instance the what-is-F disputes found in Socratic dialogues—turn out to simply be verbal disputes (see for instance the work of Amie Thomasson), they instead argue that such disputes are typically substantive. Moreover, the resolving of such disputes presuppose an ontological commitment to essences, specifically that ‘some […] phenomena have essences, and that these essences can be rigorously studied by philosophical or scientific means.’ (Koslicki & Massin, this issue, pp. 319-333) And while the authors do not deny that there are also verbal disputes, what is typical of these cases is that instead of a single phenomenon we find out that there are two distinct phenomena, and argue that such cases require the recognition of more, not fewer, essences. Jeremy W. Skrzypek develops an account of Aristotle's hylomorphism which takes into account the insights of the recent literature on biological processualism, especially the view of Dupré. The resultant position, which Skrzypek following Mark Steen calls ‘hyloenergeism’, is able to capture these insights without abandoning the Aristotelian commitment to essences and to substances, and is argued to have further theoretical advantages compared to Dupré's position. While this is a systematic paper, at the end of the paper Skrzypek also suggests that hyloenergeism might in fact have been Aristotle's actual position. Martin Glazier presents an objection to priority monism, which is the position recently defended by Jonathan Schaffer that there is only one substance, viz. the whole cosmos. The objection is that priority monism violates the basic tenet that every substance is necessarily a substance, because it turns out that the cosmos is not necessarily a substance, and thus that priority monism is false. Glazier discusses Schaffer's three arguments, and shows that neither justifies a rejection of the tenet that every substance is necessarily a substance. Further, Glazier shows that this tenet poses a problem for a distinct issue, namely what Schaffer calls the ‘Aristotelian principle’: that no substance is composed of substances. Finally, the pluralist position that there are many substances, viz. mereological simples, is argued to not violate the tenet that every substance is necessarily a substance. Of the papers in this issue, four were presented at the annual Ratio conference 2022. This was organised as a hybrid conference, with 18 live and 24 virtual participants registered. Robin Hendry, Michail Peramatzis, and Naomi Thompson presented their papers in Reading, while Ludger Jansen did his presentation remotely. Once more I want to thank the speakers, the participants, the staff and caterers involved, and especially David Oderberg, for making the event run smoothly and successfully. The other four papers, by Martin Glazier, Kathrin Koslicki & Olivier Massin, Jessica Leech, and Jeremy W. Skrzypek, were commissioned for this special issue. Both the Ratio conference and my own position while organising and editing this issue, was funded by the European commision through my MSCA individual fellowship, Formal Causation: Rivals and Extensions (FCRE 101028122).\",\"PeriodicalId\":46553,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Ratio\",\"volume\":\"7 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.6000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-11-04\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Ratio\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1111/rati.12394\",\"RegionNum\":4,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"PHILOSOPHY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Ratio","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1111/rati.12394","RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

从大约30年前开始,本质和本质主义逐渐受到关注和支持,这不仅体现在出版物的数量上,而且体现在对不同哲学问题的适用性上。本期特刊展示了这种广泛的适用性。Michail Peramatzis以一篇关于亚里士多德的论文开篇。在亚里士多德的形说中,像苏格拉底这样的实体是由物质部分和形式组成的,即人的形式。这篇论文的主题是如何以及是什么使这些部分成为统一的东西,也就是苏格拉底。Peramatzis为《形而上学》的综合解读辩护Ζ。12、Ζ17和Η。6、化合物的统一性是从形式的原始统一性衍生出来的立场。这篇论文不仅会引起亚里士多德学者的兴趣,也会引起研究同质论和统一问题的形而上学家的兴趣。Naomi Thompson撰写了一篇关于相对较新的形而上学解释主题的论文,即从根本上区别于因果解释的解释,典型的例子是基础关系。她的论文为可能的反现实主义立场提供了非常必要的清晰度,探讨了这些立场之间的联系,并列出了支持和反对每一个立场的原因。本文将有助于塑造未来关于形而上学解释的反实在论立场的研究。罗宾·亨德利为化学物质的微观结构本质主义辩护:分子结构决定了化学物质的特性。亨德利从化学中详细列举了一系列例子,解释了结构的概念,提出了微观结构本质论的论点,并回答了文献中的反对意见。最后,讨论了亚里斯多德的混合问题,特别是在超重元素如有机物的情况下。亨德利假设一个宽泛的亚里士多德观点,认为元素的组织不存在,因为它的特征核存在的时间不够长,不足以表现出元素的特征能量。Jessica Leech试图重新引入Barcan Marcus关于本质和必然性之间关系的描述,即最小本质主义。Leech指出,Barcan Marcus和她在60年代末和70年代初的几位同代人一样,确实认识到Kit Fine提出的基本属性和仅仅是必要属性之间的区别。此外,她认为最小本质主义能够充分处理Fine提出的问题案例,因此Barcan Marcus的描述应该是当前关于形态和本质的讨论中的一个严肃的竞争者。Ludger Jansen探讨了本质在社会领域的适用性。他认为,社会类型和社会身份都需要找到本质。然而,这两种变体表现出本质上截然不同的特征。社会类型是外在形成的,即在某种历史的社会行为中形成;而社会身份是内在形成的,即在某种心理行为中形成。虽然社会类型是稳定的,不受变化的影响,但社会身份可以被取代和改变。詹森探讨了在社会领域支持本质主义的好处,并反驳了可能存在的反对意见,即本质主义是危险的,因为它支持压迫性的社会结构。接受本质主义实际上是结束这些压迫结构的必要前提,通过识别压迫结构的本质特征,从而指出如何结束这些压迫结构。Kathrin Koslicki和Olivier Massin撰写了一篇关于形而上学的论文。最近新卡尔纳普主义的观点认为,定义上的争论——例如苏格拉底对话中发现的“什么是f”的争论——结果只是口头上的争论(参见艾米·托马森的著作),他们对此的回应是,这样的争论通常是实质性的。此外,解决这些争议的前提是对本质的本体论承诺,特别是“一些[…]现象具有本质,并且这些本质可以通过哲学或科学手段进行严格研究。”(Koslicki & Massin,本刊,第319-333页)虽然作者不否认也存在言语纠纷,但这些案例的典型之处是,我们发现存在两种截然不同的现象,而不是单一的现象,并认为这些案例需要认识到更多而不是更少的本质。Jeremy W. Skrzypek发展了亚里士多德的类形说,其中考虑到最近关于生物过程主义的文献的见解,特别是杜普莱尔的观点。 由此产生的立场,Skrzypek在马克·斯蒂恩之后称之为“水能论”,能够在不放弃亚里士多德对本质和物质的承诺的情况下获得这些见解,并且被认为与杜普雷尔的立场相比具有进一步的理论优势。虽然这是一篇系统的论文,但在论文的最后,Skrzypek还指出,水能论实际上可能是亚里士多德的实际立场。Martin Glazier提出了对优先一元论的反对意见,这是Jonathan Schaffer最近捍卫的立场,即只有一种物质,即整个宇宙。反对意见是,优先一元论违背了基本原则,即每一种物质都必然是一种物质,因为事实证明宇宙不一定是一种物质,因此优先一元论是错误的。Glazier讨论了Schaffer的三个论点,并表明,这两个论点都不能证明拒绝所有物质必然是物质的原则是正当的。此外,Glazier指出,这一原则提出了一个截然不同的问题,即Schaffer所谓的“亚里士多德原则”:没有物质是由物质组成的。最后,多元主义的立场,即有许多实体,即单一形态,被认为不违反每一个实体必然是一个实体的原则。在本期的论文中,有四篇是在2022年的年度比率会议上发表的。这是一个混合会议,有18名现场和24名虚拟参与者注册。Robin Hendry, Michail Peramatzis和Naomi Thompson在雷丁发表了他们的论文,Ludger Jansen则是远程发表的。我要再次感谢演讲者、与会者、工作人员和餐饮承办者,特别是David Oderberg,感谢你们使这次活动顺利成功地进行。Martin Glazier, Kathrin Koslicki & Olivier Massin, Jessica Leech和Jeremy W. Skrzypek的另外四篇论文是为本期特刊委托撰写的。比率会议和我自己在组织和编辑这一期时的立场,都是由欧盟委员会通过我的MSCA个人奖学金资助的,正式因果关系:竞争对手和扩展(FCRE 101028122)。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Introduction—A return to form
Starting roughly thirty years ago, essences and essentialism has seen a gradual rise in interest and support, not only as measured in the number of publications, but also in terms of applicability to distinct philosophical issues. This special issue showcases this wide applicability. Michail Peramatzis opens with a paper on Aristotle. On Aristotle's hylomorphism, a substance such as Socrates is made up of both material parts and a form, namely that of being a human. The issue of the paper concerns how and what makes these parts into something unified, namely Socrates. Peramatzis defends an integrated reading of Metaphysics Ζ.12, Ζ17, and Η.6, and the position that the compound's unity is derivative of the form's primitive unity. This paper will be of interest not only to scholars of Aristotle, but also to metaphysicians working on hylomorphism and the problem of unity. Naomi Thompson contributes a paper on the relatively recent topic of metaphysical explanation, namely as explanations fundamentally distinct from causal explanations, typically exemplified by the relation of grounding. Her paper provides much needed clarity on the possible antirealist positions available, explores the connections between these positions, and lays out the reasons for and against each of them. This paper will be instrumental in shaping future research on antirealist positions on metaphysical explanation. Robin Hendry defends microstructural essentialism for chemical substances: the position that the molecular structure is what determines the identity of a chemical substance. With a detailed range of examples from chemistry, Hendry explains the notion of structure, presents the arguments for microstructural essentialism, and replies to the counterarguments in the literature. In the final section, the paper discusses the Aristotelian problems of mixture, especially in the case of super-heavy elements like oganesson. Presupposing a broadly Aristotelian view, Hendry argues that oganesson the element does not exist because its characteristic nuclei does not exist long enough to exhibit the element's characteristic powers. Jessica Leech seeks to reintroduce Barcan Marcus' account of the relation between essence and necessity, that of minimal essentialism. Leech shows that Barcan Marcus, in common with several of her contemporaries in the late 60's and early 70's, did recognise the distinction, famously made by Kit Fine, between essential properties and properties that are merely necessary. Moreover, she argues that minimal essentialism is able to adequately deal with the problematic cases raised by Fine, and therefore that Barcan Marcus' account should be a serious contender in the current discussion of modality and essence. Ludger Jansen explores the applicability of essences to the social domain. He argues that essences are to be found for both social kinds and for social identities. However, these two variants exhibit essences with radically distinct characteristics. Social kinds are extrinsically constituted, namely in some historical social act, while social identities are internally constituted, namely in some mental act. And while social kinds are stable and immune to change, social identities can be replaced and changed. Jansen explores the benefits of endorsing essentialism in the social domain, and rebuts the possible objection that essentialism is dangerous because it supports oppressive social structures. Acceptance of essentialism in fact turns out to be a necessary precondition for ending these oppressive structures, by identifying the essential features of the oppressive structure, thereby pointing out how these oppressive structures can be ended. Kathrin Koslicki and Olivier Massin contribute a paper on metametaphysics. In response to the recent neo-Carnapian view that definitional disputes—for instance the what-is-F disputes found in Socratic dialogues—turn out to simply be verbal disputes (see for instance the work of Amie Thomasson), they instead argue that such disputes are typically substantive. Moreover, the resolving of such disputes presuppose an ontological commitment to essences, specifically that ‘some […] phenomena have essences, and that these essences can be rigorously studied by philosophical or scientific means.’ (Koslicki & Massin, this issue, pp. 319-333) And while the authors do not deny that there are also verbal disputes, what is typical of these cases is that instead of a single phenomenon we find out that there are two distinct phenomena, and argue that such cases require the recognition of more, not fewer, essences. Jeremy W. Skrzypek develops an account of Aristotle's hylomorphism which takes into account the insights of the recent literature on biological processualism, especially the view of Dupré. The resultant position, which Skrzypek following Mark Steen calls ‘hyloenergeism’, is able to capture these insights without abandoning the Aristotelian commitment to essences and to substances, and is argued to have further theoretical advantages compared to Dupré's position. While this is a systematic paper, at the end of the paper Skrzypek also suggests that hyloenergeism might in fact have been Aristotle's actual position. Martin Glazier presents an objection to priority monism, which is the position recently defended by Jonathan Schaffer that there is only one substance, viz. the whole cosmos. The objection is that priority monism violates the basic tenet that every substance is necessarily a substance, because it turns out that the cosmos is not necessarily a substance, and thus that priority monism is false. Glazier discusses Schaffer's three arguments, and shows that neither justifies a rejection of the tenet that every substance is necessarily a substance. Further, Glazier shows that this tenet poses a problem for a distinct issue, namely what Schaffer calls the ‘Aristotelian principle’: that no substance is composed of substances. Finally, the pluralist position that there are many substances, viz. mereological simples, is argued to not violate the tenet that every substance is necessarily a substance. Of the papers in this issue, four were presented at the annual Ratio conference 2022. This was organised as a hybrid conference, with 18 live and 24 virtual participants registered. Robin Hendry, Michail Peramatzis, and Naomi Thompson presented their papers in Reading, while Ludger Jansen did his presentation remotely. Once more I want to thank the speakers, the participants, the staff and caterers involved, and especially David Oderberg, for making the event run smoothly and successfully. The other four papers, by Martin Glazier, Kathrin Koslicki & Olivier Massin, Jessica Leech, and Jeremy W. Skrzypek, were commissioned for this special issue. Both the Ratio conference and my own position while organising and editing this issue, was funded by the European commision through my MSCA individual fellowship, Formal Causation: Rivals and Extensions (FCRE 101028122).
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
Ratio
Ratio PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
1.00
自引率
0.00%
发文量
33
期刊介绍: Ratio publishes work of a high quality on a wide variety of topics. It encourages articles which meet the highest standards of philosophical expertise, while at the same time remaining accessible to readers from a broad range of philosophical disciplines. The journal"s main emphasis is on analytic philosophy, but it also includes work from other traditions.
期刊最新文献
Intrinsic Properties and the Problem of “Other Things” Rejecting norms of standing for private blame The property of goal‐directedness: Lessons from the dispositions debate The limits of compromise Prime matter emergentism: Unity without reduction
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1