{"title":"非洲小说与非洲哲学中的社群主义问题","authors":"Zeyad El Nabolsy","doi":"10.1080/17533171.2023.2246266","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Click to increase image sizeClick to decrease image size Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.AcknowledgmentI wish to thank Migdalia Arcila Valenzuela and Christopher J. Lee for their helpful comments on an earlier draft of this article.Notes1 Jackson uses the term “philosophical thinking” explicitly in her book, see Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 185. She also uses the term “philosophical practice”, see Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 20. Jackson appears to be using these two terms as synonyms, and I will be following her in this practice.2 Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 22.3 Ibid., 116.4 Ibid, 125.5 Ibid, 134.6 Ibid, 121.7 Polycarp Ikuenobe, “Tradition and the Foundation for African Renaissance.”8 In the sense that these debates are centered around how we ought to live, they thus invoke a standard of goodness or rightness.9 Thaddeus Metz, “Toward an African Moral Theory.”10 Táíwò, “Against African Communalism.”11 Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 50.12 Cassirer, Rousseau, Kant and Goethe, 9.13 Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 71–3.14 Ibid, 156.15 Polycarp Ikuenobe, “The Idea of Personhood in Chinua Achebe’s Things Fall Apart.”16 Horton, Letters on the Political Condition of the Gold Coast, 167.17 Mazrui, “Africa, My Conscience, and I.” Also Táíwò, “Obafemi Awolowo: Knowledge, Leadership, Governance,” 64.18 See, for example, Ndlovu-Gatsheni, Coloniality of Power in Postcolonial Africa, 46; Imafidon, “Alterity, African Modernity, and the Critique of Change,” 14.19 Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 80.20 Táíwò, Against Decolonisation, 164–5.21 A similar point was also made by Wiredu, “Toward Decolonizing African Philosophy and Religion,” 295–6.22 See, for example, the misplaced critique of Samir Amin in Ndlovu-Gatsheni, Coloniality of Power in Postcolonial Africa, 11. This critique ultimately stems from an overly broad conception of decolonization. Ndlovu-Gatsheni’s conception of decolonization draws upon the notion of decoloniality as articulated by Walter Mignolo.23 Kant, “An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?,” 17.Additional informationFundingThis work was supported by a doctoral fellowship provided by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.Notes on contributorsZeyad El NabolsyZeyad El Nabolsy is an assistant professor of philosophy at York University. His work focuses on the history of African philosophy broadly conceived. His work has previously appeared in The Journal of African Cultural Studies, Kant Studies Online, Journal of Historical Sociology, and Science & Society.","PeriodicalId":43901,"journal":{"name":"Safundi-The Journal of South African and American Studies","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-10-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"The African novel and the question of communalism in African philosophy\",\"authors\":\"Zeyad El Nabolsy\",\"doi\":\"10.1080/17533171.2023.2246266\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Click to increase image sizeClick to decrease image size Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.AcknowledgmentI wish to thank Migdalia Arcila Valenzuela and Christopher J. Lee for their helpful comments on an earlier draft of this article.Notes1 Jackson uses the term “philosophical thinking” explicitly in her book, see Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 185. She also uses the term “philosophical practice”, see Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 20. Jackson appears to be using these two terms as synonyms, and I will be following her in this practice.2 Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 22.3 Ibid., 116.4 Ibid, 125.5 Ibid, 134.6 Ibid, 121.7 Polycarp Ikuenobe, “Tradition and the Foundation for African Renaissance.”8 In the sense that these debates are centered around how we ought to live, they thus invoke a standard of goodness or rightness.9 Thaddeus Metz, “Toward an African Moral Theory.”10 Táíwò, “Against African Communalism.”11 Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 50.12 Cassirer, Rousseau, Kant and Goethe, 9.13 Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 71–3.14 Ibid, 156.15 Polycarp Ikuenobe, “The Idea of Personhood in Chinua Achebe’s Things Fall Apart.”16 Horton, Letters on the Political Condition of the Gold Coast, 167.17 Mazrui, “Africa, My Conscience, and I.” Also Táíwò, “Obafemi Awolowo: Knowledge, Leadership, Governance,” 64.18 See, for example, Ndlovu-Gatsheni, Coloniality of Power in Postcolonial Africa, 46; Imafidon, “Alterity, African Modernity, and the Critique of Change,” 14.19 Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 80.20 Táíwò, Against Decolonisation, 164–5.21 A similar point was also made by Wiredu, “Toward Decolonizing African Philosophy and Religion,” 295–6.22 See, for example, the misplaced critique of Samir Amin in Ndlovu-Gatsheni, Coloniality of Power in Postcolonial Africa, 11. This critique ultimately stems from an overly broad conception of decolonization. Ndlovu-Gatsheni’s conception of decolonization draws upon the notion of decoloniality as articulated by Walter Mignolo.23 Kant, “An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?,” 17.Additional informationFundingThis work was supported by a doctoral fellowship provided by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.Notes on contributorsZeyad El NabolsyZeyad El Nabolsy is an assistant professor of philosophy at York University. His work focuses on the history of African philosophy broadly conceived. His work has previously appeared in The Journal of African Cultural Studies, Kant Studies Online, Journal of Historical Sociology, and Science & Society.\",\"PeriodicalId\":43901,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Safundi-The Journal of South African and American Studies\",\"volume\":\"1 1\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-10-02\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Safundi-The Journal of South African and American Studies\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1080/17533171.2023.2246266\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q4\",\"JCRName\":\"AREA STUDIES\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Safundi-The Journal of South African and American Studies","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17533171.2023.2246266","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q4","JCRName":"AREA STUDIES","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
摘要
点击放大图片点击缩小图片披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。我要感谢Migdalia Arcila Valenzuela和Christopher J. Lee对本文早期草稿的有益评论。注1杰克逊在她的书中明确地使用了“哲学思考”一词,见杰克逊,《非洲思想小说》,185页。她还使用了“哲学实践”一词,见杰克逊,《非洲思想小说》,20年。杰克逊似乎把这两个术语当作同义词来使用,我将按照她的做法来做杰克逊,《非洲思想小说》,22.3同上,116.4同上,125.5同上,134.6同上,121.7波利卡普·伊库诺布,《非洲文艺复兴的传统与基础》。从某种意义上说,这些争论的中心是我们应该如何生活,因此它们援引了一种善或对的标准塞迪斯·梅斯,《走向非洲道德理论》10 Táíwò,反对非洲社群主义。11杰克逊,《非洲思想小说》,50.12卡西尔,卢梭,康德和歌德,9.13杰克逊,《非洲思想小说》,71-3.14同上,156.15波利卡普·伊库诺布,《奇努阿·阿契贝的《分崩离析》中的人格观念》。16 Horton,黄金海岸政治状况的书信,167.17 Mazrui,“非洲,我的良心,和我”也Táíwò,“Obafemi Awolowo:知识,领导,治理,”64.18参见,例如,Ndlovu-Gatsheni,后殖民非洲的殖民权力,46;Imafidon,《另类、非洲现代性和变革批判》,14.19 Jackson,《非洲思想小说》,80.20 Táíwò,《反对非殖民化》,164-5.21 Wiredu也提出了类似的观点,《走向非殖民化的非洲哲学和宗教》,299 - 6.22,例如,参见Ndlovu-Gatsheni,《后殖民非洲的殖民权力》,11中对萨米尔·阿明的错位批判。这种批评最终源于过于宽泛的非殖民化概念。Ndlovu-Gatsheni的非殖民化概念借鉴了Walter mignolo所阐述的非殖民化概念。23康德,“对问题的回答:什么是启蒙?”,“17所示。本研究得到了加拿大社会科学与人文研究理事会提供的博士奖学金的支持。作者简介zeyad El Nabolsy是约克大学哲学助理教授。他的工作主要集中在广义的非洲哲学史上。他的作品曾发表在《非洲文化研究杂志》、《康德研究在线》、《历史社会学杂志》和《科学与社会》上。
The African novel and the question of communalism in African philosophy
Click to increase image sizeClick to decrease image size Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.AcknowledgmentI wish to thank Migdalia Arcila Valenzuela and Christopher J. Lee for their helpful comments on an earlier draft of this article.Notes1 Jackson uses the term “philosophical thinking” explicitly in her book, see Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 185. She also uses the term “philosophical practice”, see Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 20. Jackson appears to be using these two terms as synonyms, and I will be following her in this practice.2 Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 22.3 Ibid., 116.4 Ibid, 125.5 Ibid, 134.6 Ibid, 121.7 Polycarp Ikuenobe, “Tradition and the Foundation for African Renaissance.”8 In the sense that these debates are centered around how we ought to live, they thus invoke a standard of goodness or rightness.9 Thaddeus Metz, “Toward an African Moral Theory.”10 Táíwò, “Against African Communalism.”11 Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 50.12 Cassirer, Rousseau, Kant and Goethe, 9.13 Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 71–3.14 Ibid, 156.15 Polycarp Ikuenobe, “The Idea of Personhood in Chinua Achebe’s Things Fall Apart.”16 Horton, Letters on the Political Condition of the Gold Coast, 167.17 Mazrui, “Africa, My Conscience, and I.” Also Táíwò, “Obafemi Awolowo: Knowledge, Leadership, Governance,” 64.18 See, for example, Ndlovu-Gatsheni, Coloniality of Power in Postcolonial Africa, 46; Imafidon, “Alterity, African Modernity, and the Critique of Change,” 14.19 Jackson, The African Novel of Ideas, 80.20 Táíwò, Against Decolonisation, 164–5.21 A similar point was also made by Wiredu, “Toward Decolonizing African Philosophy and Religion,” 295–6.22 See, for example, the misplaced critique of Samir Amin in Ndlovu-Gatsheni, Coloniality of Power in Postcolonial Africa, 11. This critique ultimately stems from an overly broad conception of decolonization. Ndlovu-Gatsheni’s conception of decolonization draws upon the notion of decoloniality as articulated by Walter Mignolo.23 Kant, “An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?,” 17.Additional informationFundingThis work was supported by a doctoral fellowship provided by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.Notes on contributorsZeyad El NabolsyZeyad El Nabolsy is an assistant professor of philosophy at York University. His work focuses on the history of African philosophy broadly conceived. His work has previously appeared in The Journal of African Cultural Studies, Kant Studies Online, Journal of Historical Sociology, and Science & Society.