外部性与庇古政策的局限性

IF 1.5 Q4 ENVIRONMENTAL STUDIES Ethics Policy & Environment Pub Date : 2023-11-02 DOI:10.1080/21550085.2023.2272549
Rebecca Livernois
{"title":"外部性与庇古政策的局限性","authors":"Rebecca Livernois","doi":"10.1080/21550085.2023.2272549","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTPigovian policy is developed in economic theory as an efficient resolution to externality problems. The use of this type of policy to resolve real-world externality problems, including climate change in the form of carbon taxes, assumes that the Pigovian policy result derived in theory holds in the real world. By examining the bridging conditions from theory to the real world, I argue that this assumption holds only in an ambiguously defined subset of externalities. It is thus unclear when Pigovian policy could be coherently applied, which is problematic given its widespread use in critical policy contexts.KEYWORDS: Carbon taxclimate policyexternalitymarket-based policyphilosophy of economics AcknowledgmentsI am grateful to Margaret Schabas, Alison Wylie, John Beatty, and Joseph Heath for their helpful comments and suggestions. I also benefitted from audiences at several conferences and seminars, including the Philosophy, Politics and Economics Research Seminar at Arizona State University and the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Pigovian policy is so called after the economist Alfred Pigou (Citation1920/2017) who is often cited as the progenitor of externality theory in economics (Medema, Citation2020).2. This is distinct to the question of whether implementing a specific Pigovian policy is justified, which has been extensively examined by economists. There are several well-known reasons that implementing such a policy might not be justifiable in practice, including high administrative costs relative to the expected benefits of the policy and insufficient information on the part of the policymaker about individual preferences (see Baumol, Citation1972; Tol, Citation2018; Winston, Citation2006). In order to assess the justifiability of implementing a particular Pigovian policy response, however, it must first be established that such a policy response is at least coherent in the given context. This paper is focused on this more basic question.3. Pigovian policy features prominently in justifying and guiding government carbon tax policies (Rennert & Kingdon, Citation2019). It is also endorsed by many leading economists in an open letter published in the Wall Street Journal (Akerlof et al., Citation2019) as well as in the informal ‘Pigou Club’, which is a list of economists and policymakers who endorse Pigovian policies (Mankiw, Citation2009).4. It is important to note that this paper does not call into question the general use of a carbon tax to address climate change. Instead, it calls into question the use of a particular type of tax that is justified by externality theory and which calls for a specific carbon tax rate determined by estimates of the value of the externality generated by carbon dioxide emissions.5. The concept of an externality in economics, however, is notoriously difficult to precisely define. In the latter half of the twentieth century, prominent economists including Kenneth Arrow (Citation1969), James M. Buchanan and William C. Stubblebine (Citation1962), Ronald Coase (Citation1960/2013), and James Meade (Citation1952) developed competing accounts of the concept of an externality. For more on the history of market failure and the concept of an externality, see Nathalie Berta (Citation2017), Nathalie Berta and Elodie Bertrand (Citation2014), Maurice Lagueux (Citation2010), Alain Marciano (Citation2011), Steven Medema (Citation2009, Citation2014, Citation2020), and Andreas Papandreou (Citation1994, Citation2003).6. Following economic terminology, I reserve the term optimality to refer to Pareto efficiency or Pareto optimality, which is also sometimes called social optimality. An outcome is Pareto optimal if there is no possible reallocation of resources that would make at least one agent better off without making any other agent worse off.7. A potential Pareto improvement exists when resources could be reallocated such that at least one person would be made better off and no agent would be made worse off.8. Ronald Coase’s (Citation1960/2013) influential critique of the Pigovian approach to externalities holds instead that externalities persist because of high transaction costs. If the two relevant parties could negotiate a contract over the externality, an efficient solution would ensue. Nevertheless, climate change is a case where Pigovian analysis is the appropriate approach. David D. Friedman (Citation2000), for example, argues that while Coase offers the correct general analysis, Pigovian analysis of externality problems is correct ‘under special circumstances, situations in which transaction costs are high, so that transaction between parties can be safely ignored, and in which the agent deciding which party is to be held liable already knows who the lowest-cost avoider of the problem is’ (Friedman, Citation2000, p. 42). Climate change is a clear case in which transaction costs are high because it is not possible for the current generation (those generating emissions) to form contracts with future generations (those impacted by the emissions). It is also a case in which there is good reason to believe that the current generation is the least-cost avoider of the problem. This is because there are hard limits to climate adaptation which indicates that it cannot be the case that the cost for the future to adapt to unmitigated climate change is lower than the cost for current generation to both mitigate and adapt (Pörtner et al., Citation2022).9. This paper focuses on Pigovian taxes because this is the most common form of Pigovian climate policy; however, these other forms of Pigovian policy are isomorphic in theory, and therefore the argument presented here is not specific to taxes and also apply to cap-and-trade as well as subsidy policies. If policymakers preferred a cap-and-trade policy, for example, and thus aimed to create a market for emissions, they would use the quantity at the Pareto optimal level to determine where to set the cap, and thus how to assign property rights over carbon emissions (which, in theory, could be assigned to polluters or those affected by pollution). Hence, what is called Pigovian theory in economics incorporates Coase’s (Citation1960/2013) insight that externalities are reciprocal and as such can be addressed by assigning property rights to either party. For more on the isomorphism of these policies in contemporary theory, see Martin L. Weitzman (Citation1974). The efficacy and political feasibility of these various policies, however, are not necessarily isomorphic in the real world. Lonergan and Sawers (Citation2022), for example, argue that positive incentives (e.g. subsidies) are often more effective than negative incentives (e.g. taxes), in part, because they are more likely to be viewed favorably by taxpayers.10. Versions of this framework can be seen in Charles Plott (Citation1966), Kenneth Arrow (Citation1970), Agnar Sandmo (Citation1980), and Hal Varian (Citation1994), for example.11. Those who prefer to skip the mathematical language of the theory can safely focus solely on the prose in this section.12. Derived utility is vi(p, wi, h) = max ui(xi, h) subject to p • xi ≤ wi ≡ øi(p, h) + wi. Since prices are unaffected by the choice of h, the price vector is suppressed. Therefore, derived utility is expressed as øi(h). See Mas-Colell et al. (Citation1995, pp. 352–354) for more detail.13. Note that contrary to the insights of Coase (Citation1960/2013), the model under scrutiny in this paper assumes that an analysis of the costs of administering the policy is separable from an analysis of the value of the externality. Hence, the model assumes that the reallocation of the unpriced good is costless, with the expectation that the administration costs and efficacy of a particular policy are assessed at a later stage of the policy analysis. Given that this paper aims to develop an internal critique of externality theory, it focuses on the first step of this process.14. Note that preference satisfaction refers to a state in which the object of a preference is realized, not the feeling of satisfaction (D. M. Hausman, Citation2012).15. Note that this terminology references contemporary Pigovian policy, not the type of externality or policy discussed directly by Pigou (Citation1920/2017). Pigou’s conception of an externality aligns more closely with the general view of externalities as unpriced spillover effects and, furthermore, Pigou’s economic framework for analyzing externalities differs significantly from contemporary economics. The term ‘Pigovian’ refers to a perceived economic tradition arising out of Pigou’s work. See Banzhaf (Citation2020) and Medema (Citation2020) for more on this topic.16. In economic terms, this means there is a corner solution in the two-agent constrained optimization framework.17. The scenario in which the budget constraint determines whether an externality is merely an unpriced spillover effect on welfare or a Pigovian externality raises well-known issues with the justifiability of implementing a particular Pigovian policy. One might reasonably question whether it is appropriate for a public policy to respond to income-constrained preference satisfaction (rather than preference satisfaction alone, for example), and thus instantiate an outcome dependent on existing income inequality (for example, see Anthoff & Tol, Citation2010; Sagoff, Citation2008). This paper sets aside this issue because it aims to examine the coherence of a Pigovian policy rather than the justifiability of implementing such a policy in a specific context.18. That is, where there is an internal solution to the joint welfare maximizing problem.19. As explained in the previous section, economics tends to hold that the converse is also true: if an individual’s welfare is reduced by an unpriced action taken by another individual, then this individual must have a willingness to pay to decrease the activity (at some level of income and at some quantity of the harmful activity, and barring non-economic values) that expresses both their preference satisfaction and welfare.20. This interpretation of Pigovian externalities resembles Buchanan and Stubblebine’s (Citation1962) account of relevant and irrelevant externalities. According to Buchanan and Stubblebine, externalities are irrelevant if individuals fail to eliminate them through exchange. This is because the persistence of an externality indicates that individuals have determined that it is costlier to eliminate the externality than to let it persist. Therefore, they argue that the persistence of some (irrelevant) externalities is consistent with a Pareto optimal state of affairs. The occurrence of exchange over an unpriced activity thus distinguishes between relevant and irrelevant externalities for Buchanan and Stubblebine (Citation1962), which implies that there is never a need for a Pigovian policy intervention. This is an inadequate account of policy-relevant and irrelevant externalities in the case of climate change in which exchange over the externality in question is not possible. In contrast, according to the view presented in this paper, the presence of untapped gains from exchange (not the occurrence of an actual exchange) based on preferences that are informative of welfare gains distinguishes Pigovian externalities from mere unpriced spillover effects. This is an important distinction especially in the context of climate change because it captures the value of the externality despite the time lag between the production and effect of the emissions. For more on Buchanan’s views on externalities, see James M. Buchanan (Citation1962, Citation1969) and Alain Marciano (Citation2011).21. In the case where insufficient income causes the divergence between gains from exchange and welfare gains, we would instead interpret hypothetical gains from exchange as what individuals would be willing to pay for an unpriced activity if they had sufficiently unconstrained income.22. In practice, the measurability of hypothetical gains from exchange could be delivered by a proxy; for example, lost GDP per capita caused by flooding could be used as a proxy for how much individuals should be willing to pay for improved flood mitigation infrastructure. An understanding of the concept being proxied, however, is required in order to justify the choice of proxy. This paper focuses directly on these foundational concepts.Additional informationFundingThis paper draws on research supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council.","PeriodicalId":45955,"journal":{"name":"Ethics Policy & Environment","volume":"31 4","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5000,"publicationDate":"2023-11-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Externalities and the Limits of Pigovian Policies\",\"authors\":\"Rebecca Livernois\",\"doi\":\"10.1080/21550085.2023.2272549\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"ABSTRACTPigovian policy is developed in economic theory as an efficient resolution to externality problems. The use of this type of policy to resolve real-world externality problems, including climate change in the form of carbon taxes, assumes that the Pigovian policy result derived in theory holds in the real world. By examining the bridging conditions from theory to the real world, I argue that this assumption holds only in an ambiguously defined subset of externalities. It is thus unclear when Pigovian policy could be coherently applied, which is problematic given its widespread use in critical policy contexts.KEYWORDS: Carbon taxclimate policyexternalitymarket-based policyphilosophy of economics AcknowledgmentsI am grateful to Margaret Schabas, Alison Wylie, John Beatty, and Joseph Heath for their helpful comments and suggestions. I also benefitted from audiences at several conferences and seminars, including the Philosophy, Politics and Economics Research Seminar at Arizona State University and the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Pigovian policy is so called after the economist Alfred Pigou (Citation1920/2017) who is often cited as the progenitor of externality theory in economics (Medema, Citation2020).2. This is distinct to the question of whether implementing a specific Pigovian policy is justified, which has been extensively examined by economists. There are several well-known reasons that implementing such a policy might not be justifiable in practice, including high administrative costs relative to the expected benefits of the policy and insufficient information on the part of the policymaker about individual preferences (see Baumol, Citation1972; Tol, Citation2018; Winston, Citation2006). In order to assess the justifiability of implementing a particular Pigovian policy response, however, it must first be established that such a policy response is at least coherent in the given context. This paper is focused on this more basic question.3. Pigovian policy features prominently in justifying and guiding government carbon tax policies (Rennert & Kingdon, Citation2019). It is also endorsed by many leading economists in an open letter published in the Wall Street Journal (Akerlof et al., Citation2019) as well as in the informal ‘Pigou Club’, which is a list of economists and policymakers who endorse Pigovian policies (Mankiw, Citation2009).4. It is important to note that this paper does not call into question the general use of a carbon tax to address climate change. Instead, it calls into question the use of a particular type of tax that is justified by externality theory and which calls for a specific carbon tax rate determined by estimates of the value of the externality generated by carbon dioxide emissions.5. The concept of an externality in economics, however, is notoriously difficult to precisely define. In the latter half of the twentieth century, prominent economists including Kenneth Arrow (Citation1969), James M. Buchanan and William C. Stubblebine (Citation1962), Ronald Coase (Citation1960/2013), and James Meade (Citation1952) developed competing accounts of the concept of an externality. For more on the history of market failure and the concept of an externality, see Nathalie Berta (Citation2017), Nathalie Berta and Elodie Bertrand (Citation2014), Maurice Lagueux (Citation2010), Alain Marciano (Citation2011), Steven Medema (Citation2009, Citation2014, Citation2020), and Andreas Papandreou (Citation1994, Citation2003).6. Following economic terminology, I reserve the term optimality to refer to Pareto efficiency or Pareto optimality, which is also sometimes called social optimality. An outcome is Pareto optimal if there is no possible reallocation of resources that would make at least one agent better off without making any other agent worse off.7. A potential Pareto improvement exists when resources could be reallocated such that at least one person would be made better off and no agent would be made worse off.8. Ronald Coase’s (Citation1960/2013) influential critique of the Pigovian approach to externalities holds instead that externalities persist because of high transaction costs. If the two relevant parties could negotiate a contract over the externality, an efficient solution would ensue. Nevertheless, climate change is a case where Pigovian analysis is the appropriate approach. David D. Friedman (Citation2000), for example, argues that while Coase offers the correct general analysis, Pigovian analysis of externality problems is correct ‘under special circumstances, situations in which transaction costs are high, so that transaction between parties can be safely ignored, and in which the agent deciding which party is to be held liable already knows who the lowest-cost avoider of the problem is’ (Friedman, Citation2000, p. 42). Climate change is a clear case in which transaction costs are high because it is not possible for the current generation (those generating emissions) to form contracts with future generations (those impacted by the emissions). It is also a case in which there is good reason to believe that the current generation is the least-cost avoider of the problem. This is because there are hard limits to climate adaptation which indicates that it cannot be the case that the cost for the future to adapt to unmitigated climate change is lower than the cost for current generation to both mitigate and adapt (Pörtner et al., Citation2022).9. This paper focuses on Pigovian taxes because this is the most common form of Pigovian climate policy; however, these other forms of Pigovian policy are isomorphic in theory, and therefore the argument presented here is not specific to taxes and also apply to cap-and-trade as well as subsidy policies. If policymakers preferred a cap-and-trade policy, for example, and thus aimed to create a market for emissions, they would use the quantity at the Pareto optimal level to determine where to set the cap, and thus how to assign property rights over carbon emissions (which, in theory, could be assigned to polluters or those affected by pollution). Hence, what is called Pigovian theory in economics incorporates Coase’s (Citation1960/2013) insight that externalities are reciprocal and as such can be addressed by assigning property rights to either party. For more on the isomorphism of these policies in contemporary theory, see Martin L. Weitzman (Citation1974). The efficacy and political feasibility of these various policies, however, are not necessarily isomorphic in the real world. Lonergan and Sawers (Citation2022), for example, argue that positive incentives (e.g. subsidies) are often more effective than negative incentives (e.g. taxes), in part, because they are more likely to be viewed favorably by taxpayers.10. Versions of this framework can be seen in Charles Plott (Citation1966), Kenneth Arrow (Citation1970), Agnar Sandmo (Citation1980), and Hal Varian (Citation1994), for example.11. Those who prefer to skip the mathematical language of the theory can safely focus solely on the prose in this section.12. Derived utility is vi(p, wi, h) = max ui(xi, h) subject to p • xi ≤ wi ≡ øi(p, h) + wi. Since prices are unaffected by the choice of h, the price vector is suppressed. Therefore, derived utility is expressed as øi(h). See Mas-Colell et al. (Citation1995, pp. 352–354) for more detail.13. Note that contrary to the insights of Coase (Citation1960/2013), the model under scrutiny in this paper assumes that an analysis of the costs of administering the policy is separable from an analysis of the value of the externality. Hence, the model assumes that the reallocation of the unpriced good is costless, with the expectation that the administration costs and efficacy of a particular policy are assessed at a later stage of the policy analysis. Given that this paper aims to develop an internal critique of externality theory, it focuses on the first step of this process.14. Note that preference satisfaction refers to a state in which the object of a preference is realized, not the feeling of satisfaction (D. M. Hausman, Citation2012).15. Note that this terminology references contemporary Pigovian policy, not the type of externality or policy discussed directly by Pigou (Citation1920/2017). Pigou’s conception of an externality aligns more closely with the general view of externalities as unpriced spillover effects and, furthermore, Pigou’s economic framework for analyzing externalities differs significantly from contemporary economics. The term ‘Pigovian’ refers to a perceived economic tradition arising out of Pigou’s work. See Banzhaf (Citation2020) and Medema (Citation2020) for more on this topic.16. In economic terms, this means there is a corner solution in the two-agent constrained optimization framework.17. The scenario in which the budget constraint determines whether an externality is merely an unpriced spillover effect on welfare or a Pigovian externality raises well-known issues with the justifiability of implementing a particular Pigovian policy. One might reasonably question whether it is appropriate for a public policy to respond to income-constrained preference satisfaction (rather than preference satisfaction alone, for example), and thus instantiate an outcome dependent on existing income inequality (for example, see Anthoff & Tol, Citation2010; Sagoff, Citation2008). This paper sets aside this issue because it aims to examine the coherence of a Pigovian policy rather than the justifiability of implementing such a policy in a specific context.18. That is, where there is an internal solution to the joint welfare maximizing problem.19. As explained in the previous section, economics tends to hold that the converse is also true: if an individual’s welfare is reduced by an unpriced action taken by another individual, then this individual must have a willingness to pay to decrease the activity (at some level of income and at some quantity of the harmful activity, and barring non-economic values) that expresses both their preference satisfaction and welfare.20. This interpretation of Pigovian externalities resembles Buchanan and Stubblebine’s (Citation1962) account of relevant and irrelevant externalities. According to Buchanan and Stubblebine, externalities are irrelevant if individuals fail to eliminate them through exchange. This is because the persistence of an externality indicates that individuals have determined that it is costlier to eliminate the externality than to let it persist. Therefore, they argue that the persistence of some (irrelevant) externalities is consistent with a Pareto optimal state of affairs. The occurrence of exchange over an unpriced activity thus distinguishes between relevant and irrelevant externalities for Buchanan and Stubblebine (Citation1962), which implies that there is never a need for a Pigovian policy intervention. This is an inadequate account of policy-relevant and irrelevant externalities in the case of climate change in which exchange over the externality in question is not possible. In contrast, according to the view presented in this paper, the presence of untapped gains from exchange (not the occurrence of an actual exchange) based on preferences that are informative of welfare gains distinguishes Pigovian externalities from mere unpriced spillover effects. This is an important distinction especially in the context of climate change because it captures the value of the externality despite the time lag between the production and effect of the emissions. For more on Buchanan’s views on externalities, see James M. Buchanan (Citation1962, Citation1969) and Alain Marciano (Citation2011).21. In the case where insufficient income causes the divergence between gains from exchange and welfare gains, we would instead interpret hypothetical gains from exchange as what individuals would be willing to pay for an unpriced activity if they had sufficiently unconstrained income.22. In practice, the measurability of hypothetical gains from exchange could be delivered by a proxy; for example, lost GDP per capita caused by flooding could be used as a proxy for how much individuals should be willing to pay for improved flood mitigation infrastructure. An understanding of the concept being proxied, however, is required in order to justify the choice of proxy. This paper focuses directly on these foundational concepts.Additional informationFundingThis paper draws on research supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council.\",\"PeriodicalId\":45955,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Ethics Policy & Environment\",\"volume\":\"31 4\",\"pages\":\"0\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.5000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-11-02\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Ethics Policy & Environment\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2023.2272549\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q4\",\"JCRName\":\"ENVIRONMENTAL STUDIES\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Ethics Policy & Environment","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2023.2272549","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q4","JCRName":"ENVIRONMENTAL STUDIES","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

摘要庇古政策是经济理论中作为解决外部性问题的有效方法而发展起来的。使用这种类型的政策来解决现实世界的外部性问题,包括以碳税的形式出现的气候变化,假设理论上推导的庇古政策结果在现实世界中成立。通过检查从理论到现实世界的桥梁条件,我认为这一假设只适用于外部性的一个模糊定义子集。因此,不清楚庇古政策何时可以连贯地应用,鉴于其在关键政策背景下的广泛使用,这是有问题的。关键词:碳税气候政策外向型市场政策经济学哲学致谢感谢玛格丽特·沙巴斯,艾莉森·怀利,约翰·比蒂和约瑟夫·希思提出的有益的意见和建议。我也从一些会议和研讨会上的听众中受益,包括亚利桑那州立大学的哲学、政治和经济研究研讨会和科学哲学协会的两年一次的会议。披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。庇古政策是以经济学家阿尔弗雷德·庇古(Citation1920/2017)的名字命名的,他经常被引用为经济学中外部性理论的鼻祖(Medema, Citation2020)。这与实施特定的庇古政策是否合理的问题是截然不同的,经济学家已经对这个问题进行了广泛的研究。有几个众所周知的原因,实施这样的政策在实践中可能是不合理的,包括相对于政策的预期收益的高行政成本和政策制定者关于个人偏好的信息不足(见Baumol, Citation1972;托尔,Citation2018;温斯顿,Citation2006)。然而,为了评估执行特定庇古政策反应的合理性,必须首先确定这种政策反应至少在给定的背景下是连贯的。本文的重点是这个更基本的问题。庇古政策在证明和指导政府碳税政策方面发挥了重要作用(rennert&kingdon, Citation2019)。在《华尔街日报》(Akerlof et al., Citation2019)以及非正式的“庇古俱乐部”(Pigou Club)上发表的一封公开信中,许多知名经济学家也对庇古理论表示赞同(Mankiw, Citation2009)。庇古俱乐部由支持庇古政策的经济学家和政策制定者组成。值得注意的是,本文并没有对普遍使用碳税来应对气候变化提出质疑。相反,它对使用一种由外部性理论证明合理的特定类型的税提出了质疑,这种税要求根据对二氧化碳排放产生的外部性价值的估计来确定特定的碳税率。然而,经济学中的外部性概念是出了名的难以精确定义的。在20世纪下半叶,著名经济学家肯尼斯·阿罗(Citation1969)、詹姆斯·m·布坎南和威廉·c·斯塔布尔宾(Citation1962)、罗纳德·科斯(Citation1960/2013)和詹姆斯·米德(James Meade, Citation1952)对外部性概念提出了不同的解释。有关市场失灵的历史和外部性概念的更多信息,请参见Nathalie Berta (Citation2017)、Nathalie Berta和Elodie Bertrand (Citation2014)、Maurice Lagueux (Citation2010)、Alain Marciano (Citation2011)、Steven Medema (Citation2009、Citation2014、Citation2020)和Andreas Papandreou (Citation1994、Citation2003)。遵循经济学术语,我保留“最优性”一词指的是帕累托效率或帕累托最优性,有时也被称为社会最优性。如果没有可能的资源再分配使至少一个代理变得更好而不使其他代理变得更糟,那么结果是帕累托最优的。当资源可以重新分配时,至少有一个人会变得更好,没有代理人会变得更差,就存在潜在的帕累托改进。罗纳德·科斯(Citation1960/2013)对庇古学派的外部性方法提出了颇具影响力的批评,认为外部性之所以持续存在,是因为交易成本高。如果相关双方能够就外部性达成协议,就会产生有效的解决方案。然而,气候变化是庇古分析是适当方法的一个例子。例如,大卫·d·弗里德曼(David D. Friedman, Citation2000)认为,虽然科斯提供了正确的一般分析,但庇古对外部性问题的分析是正确的,“在特殊情况下,在交易成本高的情况下,各方之间的交易可以被安全地忽略,在这种情况下,决定哪一方承担责任的代理人已经知道谁是问题的最低成本规避者”(弗里德曼,Citation2000,第42页)。 气候变化显然是交易成本高的一个例子,因为当代人(产生排放的人)不可能与后代人(受排放影响的人)签订合同。在这种情况下,我们也有充分的理由相信,当前这一代是成本最低的问题规避者。这是因为气候适应存在硬性限制,这表明未来适应未减缓的气候变化的成本不可能低于当前一代减缓和适应的成本(Pörtner等人,Citation2022)。本文主要讨论庇古税,因为这是庇古气候政策最常见的形式;然而,这些其他形式的庇古政策在理论上是同构的,因此这里提出的论点不是针对税收的,也适用于限额与交易以及补贴政策。例如,如果政策制定者倾向于总量管制与交易政策,并以此为目标创建一个排放市场,他们就会利用帕累托最优水平上的数量来决定在哪里设置限额,从而决定如何分配碳排放的产权(理论上,这可以分配给污染者或受污染影响的人)。因此,经济学中所谓的庇古理论结合了科斯(Citation1960/2013)的见解,即外部性是相互的,因此可以通过将产权分配给任何一方来解决。有关这些政策在当代理论中的同构性的更多信息,请参见Martin L. Weitzman (Citation1974)。然而,这些不同政策的效力和政治可行性在现实世界中并不一定是同构的。例如,Lonergan和Sawers (Citation2022)认为,积极激励(如补贴)往往比消极激励(如税收)更有效,部分原因是它们更有可能被纳税人所接受。这个框架的版本可以在Charles Plott (Citation1966), Kenneth Arrow (Citation1970), Agnar Sandmo (Citation1980)和Hal Varian (Citation1994)中看到,例如。那些宁愿跳过理论的数学语言的人可以安全地专注于这一部分的散文。导出的效用为vi(p, wi, h) = max ui(xi, h),且p•xi≤wi≡øi(p, h) + wi。由于价格不受h的选择的影响,价格向量被抑制。因此,推导出的效用表示为øi(h)。参见Mas-Colell et al. (Citation1995, pp. 352-354)了解更多细节。请注意,与科斯(Citation1960/2013)的见解相反,本文审查的模型假设对管理政策的成本的分析与对外部性价值的分析是可分离的。因此,该模型假定未定价商品的重新分配是无成本的,并期望在政策分析的后期阶段评估特定政策的管理成本和效力。鉴于本文旨在对外部性理论进行内部批判,本文将重点关注这一过程的第一步。注意,偏好满意度指的是实现偏好目标的状态,而不是满足感(D. M. Hausman, Citation2012)。请注意,这个术语引用的是当代庇古政策,而不是庇古直接讨论的外部性或政策类型(Citation1920/2017)。庇古的外部性概念更接近于将外部性视为无法定价的溢出效应的一般观点,此外,庇古分析外部性的经济框架与当代经济学有很大不同。“庇古学派”一词指的是由庇古的著作产生的一种公认的经济传统。关于这个主题的更多信息,请参阅Banzhaf (Citation2020)和Medema (Citation2020)。从经济学的角度来看,这意味着在双智能体约束优化框架中存在一个角解。预算约束决定外部性仅仅是对福利的不可定价的溢出效应还是庇古外部性的情景,提出了实施特定庇古政策的合理性的众所周知的问题。人们可能会合理地质疑,一项公共政策应对收入受限的偏好满意度(而不是单独的偏好满意度)是否合适,从而实例化依赖于现有收入不平等的结果(例如,见Anthoff & Tol, Citation2010;Sagoff Citation2008)。本文把这个问题放在一边,因为它的目的是检查庇古政策的连贯性,而不是在特定情况下实施这种政策的合理性。也就是说,存在一个共同福利最大化问题的内部解决方案。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Externalities and the Limits of Pigovian Policies
ABSTRACTPigovian policy is developed in economic theory as an efficient resolution to externality problems. The use of this type of policy to resolve real-world externality problems, including climate change in the form of carbon taxes, assumes that the Pigovian policy result derived in theory holds in the real world. By examining the bridging conditions from theory to the real world, I argue that this assumption holds only in an ambiguously defined subset of externalities. It is thus unclear when Pigovian policy could be coherently applied, which is problematic given its widespread use in critical policy contexts.KEYWORDS: Carbon taxclimate policyexternalitymarket-based policyphilosophy of economics AcknowledgmentsI am grateful to Margaret Schabas, Alison Wylie, John Beatty, and Joseph Heath for their helpful comments and suggestions. I also benefitted from audiences at several conferences and seminars, including the Philosophy, Politics and Economics Research Seminar at Arizona State University and the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Pigovian policy is so called after the economist Alfred Pigou (Citation1920/2017) who is often cited as the progenitor of externality theory in economics (Medema, Citation2020).2. This is distinct to the question of whether implementing a specific Pigovian policy is justified, which has been extensively examined by economists. There are several well-known reasons that implementing such a policy might not be justifiable in practice, including high administrative costs relative to the expected benefits of the policy and insufficient information on the part of the policymaker about individual preferences (see Baumol, Citation1972; Tol, Citation2018; Winston, Citation2006). In order to assess the justifiability of implementing a particular Pigovian policy response, however, it must first be established that such a policy response is at least coherent in the given context. This paper is focused on this more basic question.3. Pigovian policy features prominently in justifying and guiding government carbon tax policies (Rennert & Kingdon, Citation2019). It is also endorsed by many leading economists in an open letter published in the Wall Street Journal (Akerlof et al., Citation2019) as well as in the informal ‘Pigou Club’, which is a list of economists and policymakers who endorse Pigovian policies (Mankiw, Citation2009).4. It is important to note that this paper does not call into question the general use of a carbon tax to address climate change. Instead, it calls into question the use of a particular type of tax that is justified by externality theory and which calls for a specific carbon tax rate determined by estimates of the value of the externality generated by carbon dioxide emissions.5. The concept of an externality in economics, however, is notoriously difficult to precisely define. In the latter half of the twentieth century, prominent economists including Kenneth Arrow (Citation1969), James M. Buchanan and William C. Stubblebine (Citation1962), Ronald Coase (Citation1960/2013), and James Meade (Citation1952) developed competing accounts of the concept of an externality. For more on the history of market failure and the concept of an externality, see Nathalie Berta (Citation2017), Nathalie Berta and Elodie Bertrand (Citation2014), Maurice Lagueux (Citation2010), Alain Marciano (Citation2011), Steven Medema (Citation2009, Citation2014, Citation2020), and Andreas Papandreou (Citation1994, Citation2003).6. Following economic terminology, I reserve the term optimality to refer to Pareto efficiency or Pareto optimality, which is also sometimes called social optimality. An outcome is Pareto optimal if there is no possible reallocation of resources that would make at least one agent better off without making any other agent worse off.7. A potential Pareto improvement exists when resources could be reallocated such that at least one person would be made better off and no agent would be made worse off.8. Ronald Coase’s (Citation1960/2013) influential critique of the Pigovian approach to externalities holds instead that externalities persist because of high transaction costs. If the two relevant parties could negotiate a contract over the externality, an efficient solution would ensue. Nevertheless, climate change is a case where Pigovian analysis is the appropriate approach. David D. Friedman (Citation2000), for example, argues that while Coase offers the correct general analysis, Pigovian analysis of externality problems is correct ‘under special circumstances, situations in which transaction costs are high, so that transaction between parties can be safely ignored, and in which the agent deciding which party is to be held liable already knows who the lowest-cost avoider of the problem is’ (Friedman, Citation2000, p. 42). Climate change is a clear case in which transaction costs are high because it is not possible for the current generation (those generating emissions) to form contracts with future generations (those impacted by the emissions). It is also a case in which there is good reason to believe that the current generation is the least-cost avoider of the problem. This is because there are hard limits to climate adaptation which indicates that it cannot be the case that the cost for the future to adapt to unmitigated climate change is lower than the cost for current generation to both mitigate and adapt (Pörtner et al., Citation2022).9. This paper focuses on Pigovian taxes because this is the most common form of Pigovian climate policy; however, these other forms of Pigovian policy are isomorphic in theory, and therefore the argument presented here is not specific to taxes and also apply to cap-and-trade as well as subsidy policies. If policymakers preferred a cap-and-trade policy, for example, and thus aimed to create a market for emissions, they would use the quantity at the Pareto optimal level to determine where to set the cap, and thus how to assign property rights over carbon emissions (which, in theory, could be assigned to polluters or those affected by pollution). Hence, what is called Pigovian theory in economics incorporates Coase’s (Citation1960/2013) insight that externalities are reciprocal and as such can be addressed by assigning property rights to either party. For more on the isomorphism of these policies in contemporary theory, see Martin L. Weitzman (Citation1974). The efficacy and political feasibility of these various policies, however, are not necessarily isomorphic in the real world. Lonergan and Sawers (Citation2022), for example, argue that positive incentives (e.g. subsidies) are often more effective than negative incentives (e.g. taxes), in part, because they are more likely to be viewed favorably by taxpayers.10. Versions of this framework can be seen in Charles Plott (Citation1966), Kenneth Arrow (Citation1970), Agnar Sandmo (Citation1980), and Hal Varian (Citation1994), for example.11. Those who prefer to skip the mathematical language of the theory can safely focus solely on the prose in this section.12. Derived utility is vi(p, wi, h) = max ui(xi, h) subject to p • xi ≤ wi ≡ øi(p, h) + wi. Since prices are unaffected by the choice of h, the price vector is suppressed. Therefore, derived utility is expressed as øi(h). See Mas-Colell et al. (Citation1995, pp. 352–354) for more detail.13. Note that contrary to the insights of Coase (Citation1960/2013), the model under scrutiny in this paper assumes that an analysis of the costs of administering the policy is separable from an analysis of the value of the externality. Hence, the model assumes that the reallocation of the unpriced good is costless, with the expectation that the administration costs and efficacy of a particular policy are assessed at a later stage of the policy analysis. Given that this paper aims to develop an internal critique of externality theory, it focuses on the first step of this process.14. Note that preference satisfaction refers to a state in which the object of a preference is realized, not the feeling of satisfaction (D. M. Hausman, Citation2012).15. Note that this terminology references contemporary Pigovian policy, not the type of externality or policy discussed directly by Pigou (Citation1920/2017). Pigou’s conception of an externality aligns more closely with the general view of externalities as unpriced spillover effects and, furthermore, Pigou’s economic framework for analyzing externalities differs significantly from contemporary economics. The term ‘Pigovian’ refers to a perceived economic tradition arising out of Pigou’s work. See Banzhaf (Citation2020) and Medema (Citation2020) for more on this topic.16. In economic terms, this means there is a corner solution in the two-agent constrained optimization framework.17. The scenario in which the budget constraint determines whether an externality is merely an unpriced spillover effect on welfare or a Pigovian externality raises well-known issues with the justifiability of implementing a particular Pigovian policy. One might reasonably question whether it is appropriate for a public policy to respond to income-constrained preference satisfaction (rather than preference satisfaction alone, for example), and thus instantiate an outcome dependent on existing income inequality (for example, see Anthoff & Tol, Citation2010; Sagoff, Citation2008). This paper sets aside this issue because it aims to examine the coherence of a Pigovian policy rather than the justifiability of implementing such a policy in a specific context.18. That is, where there is an internal solution to the joint welfare maximizing problem.19. As explained in the previous section, economics tends to hold that the converse is also true: if an individual’s welfare is reduced by an unpriced action taken by another individual, then this individual must have a willingness to pay to decrease the activity (at some level of income and at some quantity of the harmful activity, and barring non-economic values) that expresses both their preference satisfaction and welfare.20. This interpretation of Pigovian externalities resembles Buchanan and Stubblebine’s (Citation1962) account of relevant and irrelevant externalities. According to Buchanan and Stubblebine, externalities are irrelevant if individuals fail to eliminate them through exchange. This is because the persistence of an externality indicates that individuals have determined that it is costlier to eliminate the externality than to let it persist. Therefore, they argue that the persistence of some (irrelevant) externalities is consistent with a Pareto optimal state of affairs. The occurrence of exchange over an unpriced activity thus distinguishes between relevant and irrelevant externalities for Buchanan and Stubblebine (Citation1962), which implies that there is never a need for a Pigovian policy intervention. This is an inadequate account of policy-relevant and irrelevant externalities in the case of climate change in which exchange over the externality in question is not possible. In contrast, according to the view presented in this paper, the presence of untapped gains from exchange (not the occurrence of an actual exchange) based on preferences that are informative of welfare gains distinguishes Pigovian externalities from mere unpriced spillover effects. This is an important distinction especially in the context of climate change because it captures the value of the externality despite the time lag between the production and effect of the emissions. For more on Buchanan’s views on externalities, see James M. Buchanan (Citation1962, Citation1969) and Alain Marciano (Citation2011).21. In the case where insufficient income causes the divergence between gains from exchange and welfare gains, we would instead interpret hypothetical gains from exchange as what individuals would be willing to pay for an unpriced activity if they had sufficiently unconstrained income.22. In practice, the measurability of hypothetical gains from exchange could be delivered by a proxy; for example, lost GDP per capita caused by flooding could be used as a proxy for how much individuals should be willing to pay for improved flood mitigation infrastructure. An understanding of the concept being proxied, however, is required in order to justify the choice of proxy. This paper focuses directly on these foundational concepts.Additional informationFundingThis paper draws on research supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
Ethics Policy & Environment
Ethics Policy & Environment ENVIRONMENTAL STUDIES-
CiteScore
2.30
自引率
10.00%
发文量
32
期刊最新文献
Revising the Keystone Species Concept for Conservation: Value Neutrality and Non-Nativeness Why Conceptions of Scale Matter to Artificity Arguments in SRM Ethics Animal Dignity: Philosophical Reflections on Non-Human Existence Justice and Sustainability Tensions in Agriculture: Wicked Problems in the Case of Dutch Manure Policy Covert Moral Enhancement: Are Dirty Hands Needed to Save the Planet?
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1