医学教育的变革:审慎的视角

Donald Boudreau, Abraham Fuks
{"title":"医学教育的变革:审慎的视角","authors":"Donald Boudreau,&nbsp;Abraham Fuks","doi":"10.1002/hcs2.86","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>A decade ago we asked the question, “Is there something in medicine that is eternal or enduring?” Our aim was to write a manuscript entitled, “That which does not change in medicine.” The publication begins as follows: “The practice of medicine involves continual change, driven by a constant stream of developments in the understanding of biological structure and function relevant to human diseases, and the parallel improvements in pharmacologic and other technological interventions. This change is also driven by evolving social philosophies, ethical trends, and lifestyles.” [<span>1</span>] That preamble reverberates as strongly now as then, perhaps even more so, given the velocity of technological change. When we deliberated on which aspects of medical practice should remain stable, we had few premonitions that implantable chips, robotic surgery, virtual reality, and artificial intelligence (AI) would soon become ubiquitous. The needle has clearly moved, propelled by extraordinary advances in bioengineering, computer and data sciences; major shifts in the governance and organization of clinical practice; and powerful sociocultural trends.</p><p>As we explore current transformative developments we are reminded of our earlier conclusions: that certain dimensions of medical practice are, indeed, immutable. Most importantly, the relationship between physician and patient depends on moral obligations, characterized by a compassionate response best described as clinical engagement [<span>2</span>]. The requisite virtues are affective as much as cognitive. The challenge for educators, physicians, and policymakers is to accommodate the benefits of transformational change, both technological and conceptual, whilst remaining true to the fundamental, dyadic clinical relationship. Thus, pedagogic change should welcome innovations but do so with restraint that is, with an attitudinal disposition that is neither cynical nor inhibitory but rather alert and mindful, especially when faced with announcements that a given innovation will solve the problems of an overburdened hospital system. By insisting on a cautious approach we may avoid the pendulum that swings too far, resulting in unintended consequences and costly backtracking to undo the damage of untrammeled enthusiasms.</p><p>We consider two illustrative innovations germane to healthcare delivery: one in medical education and one in technology. We try to anticipate and understand impacts and conclude by posing a set of questions that may be useful to those who manage systemic changes.</p><p>An innovation, unfolding in medical schools world-wide and often regarded as “transformative,” is competency-based medical education (CBME). We analyze this trend, relying on a hierarchy of knowledge as a frame of reference.</p><p>The historian Jill Lepore, using the metaphor of a filing cabinet with four drawers, proposed a categorization of knowledge [<span>3</span>]. Each drawer contains knowledge of a different kind. The top one is for “mysteries”; the second one is for “facts”; the third is for “numbers”; and the lowest is for “data”. With respect to their epistemologies, she suggests that mysteries are accessible by revelation (thus, discernable by “God”); facts are derived by way of experimental scientific methods or observations (i.e., the product of the natural sciences and the humanities); numbers are entities that can be counted (e.g., measured by statisticians and epidemiologists); and, data are generated by computers (i.e., the product of data science). Each of these categories is potentially valuable to medical practice.</p><p>CBME lives, metaphorically speaking, in Lepore's third drawer. Its ontology is reductionist; it views professional development as the accumulation of small quanta of knowledge, accompanied by the accretion of discrete psychomotor skills, which are then presented as stepwise progress in personal abilities. Its epistemology, given the tenacity with which it defines educational outcomes in behaviorally measurable ways, is aligned with psychometrics. The model has been able to mitigate well-documented deficiencies in the assessments of clinical performance; however, its implementation, theoretical coherence, and axiological foundations have been criticized. Numerous commentators have bemoaned that CBME has monopolized resources, distracted educational leaders, undermined the <i>in loco parentis</i> nature of clinical teaching, and, most distressingly, failed to provide a holistic picture of students' evolving professional capabilities [<span>4</span>].</p><p>CBME is fraught with controversy. It has become apparent that tensions exist between CBME and the obligation to attend to professional identity formation [<span>5</span>]. A recent commentary attempts to rescue the concept of “competencies” by distinguishing it from “competence” and foregrounding the latter; it argues that competence is multilayered and visualizes the continuum of medical education as existing on three separate levels [<span>6</span>]. The first layer, considered to develop primarily in undergraduate medical education (UGME) and labeled “canonical competence,” represents an amalgam of foundational declarative knowledge with a sprinkling of basic skills. Higher order capabilities, such as creativity, curiosity, adaptability, humility, and leadership, are postponed to later phases of training, in layers encapsulated by the hackneyed phrase, “the art of medicine.” The “art” is supposedly acquired preferentially during residency and in independent practice. This curricular edifice reinforces reductionist aspects of CBME and, in suggesting that it first needs to focus on rote knowledge and skills, undermines arguments for its appropriateness in UGME. There is also a striking disconnect between the wholesale adoption of CBME and the paucity of compelling evidence for its superiority. In Canada, a country that has long promoted CBME, a report of the Royal College of Physicians and Surgeons has confirmed that only a small minority of resident physicians are supportive [<span>7</span>]. Understandably, many jurisdictions have decided to slacken their transition to CBME or to consider adopting a competency-compatible approach in lieu of a competency-based model.</p><p>The experience with CBME should serve as a note of caution for leaders in the health professions. When faced with changes that are presumed to be salutary, we recommend the following reflections: Might the knowledge represented by this transformation risk overwhelming alternative ways of understanding indispensable to professional or institutional values? Could the change be deforming as much as transforming? To what extent does the adoption of a new concept or innovative tool result in advantages for the adopter (in this illustration, educational managers) and culminate in improved outcomes for the client (in this illustration, clinical teachers and learners)? Perhaps it is time to make haste slowly!</p><p>The introduction of AI illustrates how new ideas are received, adopted, and translated strategically and pragmatically in medicine. It has been heralded as exciting yet also as disruptive. This technology has unfolded pari passu in educational and clinical domains. Its promises and pitfalls in the former have been summarized [<span>8</span>] and there has been an avalanche of studies, reviews, and commentaries on the scope, risks and benefits of introducing various types of AI to clinically related tasks (e.g., diagnosis, documentation, scheduling, workflow, and simple surgery) and in diverse medical specialities [<span>9</span>]. For purposes of our analysis, we will put aside the specific modes and domains of application and consider the essences of technology, writ large. We turn to Aristotelian philosophical constructs.</p><p>The etymology of the word is the Greek <i>technē</i> (or <i>ars</i>, in Latin)—commonly translated as craft. The ancient Greeks viewed <i>technē</i> as the antithesis of <i>tuchē</i> (luck). <i>Tuchē</i> refers to happenstance that is, events that occur by chance and are not controlled by humans. <i>Technē</i> aims to introduce order and predictability. Philosopher Martha Nussbaum notes, “<i>Technē</i> …. is a deliberate application of human intelligence to some part of the world, yielding control over <i>tuchē</i>; it is concerned with the management of need and prediction and control concerning future contingencies” [<span>10</span>]. Control of contingencies is the cardinal feature. This is highly relevant given that the practice of medicine is awash in contingencies.</p><p>Clinical medicine has been defined as: “a science-using practice that must diagnose and treat illnesses one by one” [<span>11</span>]. That definition helps situate AI in the context of medical practices. AI reinforces the notion that clinical medicine is “science-using.” It may support physicians' abilities in diagnosing, treating, and prognosticating by reducing the contingencies inherent in these clinical responsibilities. Although AI is founded on databases with an “N” measured in gigabytes, its application in clinical practice must remain resolutely in a mode of “one by one.”</p><p>Aristotle distinguished two branches of thought pertinent to human activities in practical domains: fabricating something (e.g., forging a porcelain plate) versus performing something (e.g., navigating a ship). Each activity requires a distinct cognitive disposition. The former requires <i>technē</i>—a productive mode with the following characteristics: it identifies features common to a group of cases (i.e., that which is generalizable); it culminates in definable outcomes external to the agent who was involved in the making; it explains phenomena through cause and effect; it is directly teachable; and, it succeeds in creating artifacts through the application of canonical methods. These characteristics of technology, especially the normative aspects, hearken back to the layer of <i>canonical competence</i>, as proposed in the retrofit of competence to CBME that we noted earlier.</p><p>In contrast to a technological pursuit, performing something corresponds to <i>phronēsis</i>. <i>Phronēsis</i> has been translated as prudence or practical wisdom. An analogous virtue in Confucianism is <i>ren</i> (humanness), moderated by <i>yi</i> (justice), which guides a person “to consider contingencies and localized factors” [<span>12</span>]. Practical wisdom allows one to apprehend the singular and its contextual factors (i.e., that which is particular to a case). It is less formulaic than <i>technē</i>; requires deliberation about worthwhileness and is thus tied to ethical judgment; is dependent on excellence of character; results in outcomes that are inextricable from the agent; and, is nurtured and transmitted through experiential learning. It has been argued that practices such as medicine and teaching, both focused on an N of 1, are endeavors best understood through the lens of <i>phronēsis</i> [<span>13, 14</span>].</p><p>It is important to underline that the above concepts have not been defined in crystalline terms and are open to debate. A discussion of philosophical controversies is beyond the remit of this article. The point we wish to make is that medical and pedagogical reasoning involve a choreography between generalization and particularization. These activities must integrate both nomothetic and idiographic approaches, concepts described by the philosopher Wilhelm Windelband [<span>15</span>]. AI, like all technology, cannot escape that dance.</p><p>AI will, undoubtedly, help formulate and support the generalizations and precepts routinely used in medicine. Its outputs will improve clinical decision making by rendering diagnostic evaluations, notably those that rely on visual interpretations (e.g., dermatology and radiology), and prognostications increasingly accurate. Time-honored heuristics that have served physicians well for generations will be fine-tuned or rendered obsolete by AI. If clinical trials confirm that overall patient outcomes are improved with AI, that is all to the good. However, it is not only the nameless “generic” patient that counts. The singular individual matters …. greatly. Would an AI robot be able to engage with a suffering patient in the manners of a wise clinician? Would a social robot be able to <i>see</i> the patient, apprehend their personhood, and accompany them on a healing journey in a comparable three-dimensional space as would a fellow human being? Randomized controlled studies have demonstrated that large language model-based systems can generate clinically relevant questions and responses as empathic in tone as those provided by clinicians [<span>16</span>]. Some have interpreted these findings as proof that Chatbot displays “bedside manners” equivalent or superior to those of clinicians [<span>17</span>]. Such conclusions are unwarranted. Interpersonal connections and empathy are complex and multifaceted constructs that cannot be reduced to a question-and-answer duet. Considering the nature of practical wisdom can sharpen distinctions between a human and machine clinical encounter.</p><p>Two empirical studies on <i>clinical phronēsis</i> have revealed some of its characteristics; these include having a capacity for sustaining hope, compassionate rule breaking, creating a bubble of undivided attention, encountering patients in ways that reveal the centrality of their care, and making decisions influenced by embodied perceptions such as gut feelings and intuitions [<span>2, 18</span>]. These, and the development of moral agency, are unlikely to be achievable by robots. AI is destined to become highly desirable for its assistive functions, particularly with respect to generalizations, computations, and pattern recognition. However, in terms of particularization and idiographic approaches within clinical and educational domains, and with respect to moral decision-making and clinical engagement, we contend that AI will never pass muster. A second reason to make haste … slowly!</p><p>The “Data, Information, Knowledge, Wisdom” pyramid has been used to represent the intellectual progression from possession of unprocessed data and facts to that of understanding and insight. The origins of this pyramid are uncertain [<span>19</span>]. We find it useful, not least because it positions “wisdom” at the pinnacle. This is, perhaps, more accessible than the “mysteries” visualized by Lepore in the top drawer of her knowledge hierarchy [<span>3</span>]. We propose practical wisdom as an aspirational goal. However, we do not have a magic recipe for its acquisition. Practiced discernment, guided reflection, and longitudinal experiential learning, preferably accompanied by sage mentors, are candidate ingredients.</p><p>The following commentary on technology, by Benjamin Chin-Yee, can help direct necessary reflections. He argues that “… technology does not refer simply to material artifacts but describes a particular way of thinking and interacting with the world; …(it) is not value-neutral but rather reflects a range of social choices and human values; …(it) does not serve as pure ends to fixed means but instead exists as a continuum of evolving means and ends” [<span>20</span>]. This framing suggests prudence is warranted when one is presented with new technology or new pedagogical models. Critical questions should be posed: (i) Whose interests are served by the innovation, and will anyone be overlooked? (ii) Will any tradition be threatened and if so, is the loss acceptable? (iii) Does its deployment suggest a realignment of core values and beliefs and if so, which are (intentionally or inadvertently) at risk of promotion or demotion? If the guiding principles of clinical medicine find their ethos and telos in the foundational relationship between patient and physician, then we, as healthcare professionals, are obliged to recall that we serve patients and students as the focal point of our duties. We must, therefore, assure that those who have entrusted us with their clinical and pedagogical care will benefit from and not be harmed by our innovations and creativity.</p><p>Both authors participated in the conception and design of this written perspective. Both authors worked on manuscript revisions and contributed to the final version.</p><p>The authors declare no conflict of interest.</p><p>Not applicable.</p><p>Informed consent is not applicable to this article as no human subjects were involved.</p>","PeriodicalId":100601,"journal":{"name":"Health Care Science","volume":"3 2","pages":"73-77"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2024-03-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1002/hcs2.86","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Transformations in medical education: A prudential perspective\",\"authors\":\"Donald Boudreau,&nbsp;Abraham Fuks\",\"doi\":\"10.1002/hcs2.86\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>A decade ago we asked the question, “Is there something in medicine that is eternal or enduring?” Our aim was to write a manuscript entitled, “That which does not change in medicine.” The publication begins as follows: “The practice of medicine involves continual change, driven by a constant stream of developments in the understanding of biological structure and function relevant to human diseases, and the parallel improvements in pharmacologic and other technological interventions. This change is also driven by evolving social philosophies, ethical trends, and lifestyles.” [<span>1</span>] That preamble reverberates as strongly now as then, perhaps even more so, given the velocity of technological change. When we deliberated on which aspects of medical practice should remain stable, we had few premonitions that implantable chips, robotic surgery, virtual reality, and artificial intelligence (AI) would soon become ubiquitous. The needle has clearly moved, propelled by extraordinary advances in bioengineering, computer and data sciences; major shifts in the governance and organization of clinical practice; and powerful sociocultural trends.</p><p>As we explore current transformative developments we are reminded of our earlier conclusions: that certain dimensions of medical practice are, indeed, immutable. Most importantly, the relationship between physician and patient depends on moral obligations, characterized by a compassionate response best described as clinical engagement [<span>2</span>]. The requisite virtues are affective as much as cognitive. The challenge for educators, physicians, and policymakers is to accommodate the benefits of transformational change, both technological and conceptual, whilst remaining true to the fundamental, dyadic clinical relationship. Thus, pedagogic change should welcome innovations but do so with restraint that is, with an attitudinal disposition that is neither cynical nor inhibitory but rather alert and mindful, especially when faced with announcements that a given innovation will solve the problems of an overburdened hospital system. By insisting on a cautious approach we may avoid the pendulum that swings too far, resulting in unintended consequences and costly backtracking to undo the damage of untrammeled enthusiasms.</p><p>We consider two illustrative innovations germane to healthcare delivery: one in medical education and one in technology. We try to anticipate and understand impacts and conclude by posing a set of questions that may be useful to those who manage systemic changes.</p><p>An innovation, unfolding in medical schools world-wide and often regarded as “transformative,” is competency-based medical education (CBME). We analyze this trend, relying on a hierarchy of knowledge as a frame of reference.</p><p>The historian Jill Lepore, using the metaphor of a filing cabinet with four drawers, proposed a categorization of knowledge [<span>3</span>]. Each drawer contains knowledge of a different kind. The top one is for “mysteries”; the second one is for “facts”; the third is for “numbers”; and the lowest is for “data”. With respect to their epistemologies, she suggests that mysteries are accessible by revelation (thus, discernable by “God”); facts are derived by way of experimental scientific methods or observations (i.e., the product of the natural sciences and the humanities); numbers are entities that can be counted (e.g., measured by statisticians and epidemiologists); and, data are generated by computers (i.e., the product of data science). Each of these categories is potentially valuable to medical practice.</p><p>CBME lives, metaphorically speaking, in Lepore's third drawer. Its ontology is reductionist; it views professional development as the accumulation of small quanta of knowledge, accompanied by the accretion of discrete psychomotor skills, which are then presented as stepwise progress in personal abilities. Its epistemology, given the tenacity with which it defines educational outcomes in behaviorally measurable ways, is aligned with psychometrics. The model has been able to mitigate well-documented deficiencies in the assessments of clinical performance; however, its implementation, theoretical coherence, and axiological foundations have been criticized. Numerous commentators have bemoaned that CBME has monopolized resources, distracted educational leaders, undermined the <i>in loco parentis</i> nature of clinical teaching, and, most distressingly, failed to provide a holistic picture of students' evolving professional capabilities [<span>4</span>].</p><p>CBME is fraught with controversy. It has become apparent that tensions exist between CBME and the obligation to attend to professional identity formation [<span>5</span>]. A recent commentary attempts to rescue the concept of “competencies” by distinguishing it from “competence” and foregrounding the latter; it argues that competence is multilayered and visualizes the continuum of medical education as existing on three separate levels [<span>6</span>]. The first layer, considered to develop primarily in undergraduate medical education (UGME) and labeled “canonical competence,” represents an amalgam of foundational declarative knowledge with a sprinkling of basic skills. Higher order capabilities, such as creativity, curiosity, adaptability, humility, and leadership, are postponed to later phases of training, in layers encapsulated by the hackneyed phrase, “the art of medicine.” The “art” is supposedly acquired preferentially during residency and in independent practice. This curricular edifice reinforces reductionist aspects of CBME and, in suggesting that it first needs to focus on rote knowledge and skills, undermines arguments for its appropriateness in UGME. There is also a striking disconnect between the wholesale adoption of CBME and the paucity of compelling evidence for its superiority. In Canada, a country that has long promoted CBME, a report of the Royal College of Physicians and Surgeons has confirmed that only a small minority of resident physicians are supportive [<span>7</span>]. Understandably, many jurisdictions have decided to slacken their transition to CBME or to consider adopting a competency-compatible approach in lieu of a competency-based model.</p><p>The experience with CBME should serve as a note of caution for leaders in the health professions. When faced with changes that are presumed to be salutary, we recommend the following reflections: Might the knowledge represented by this transformation risk overwhelming alternative ways of understanding indispensable to professional or institutional values? Could the change be deforming as much as transforming? To what extent does the adoption of a new concept or innovative tool result in advantages for the adopter (in this illustration, educational managers) and culminate in improved outcomes for the client (in this illustration, clinical teachers and learners)? Perhaps it is time to make haste slowly!</p><p>The introduction of AI illustrates how new ideas are received, adopted, and translated strategically and pragmatically in medicine. It has been heralded as exciting yet also as disruptive. This technology has unfolded pari passu in educational and clinical domains. Its promises and pitfalls in the former have been summarized [<span>8</span>] and there has been an avalanche of studies, reviews, and commentaries on the scope, risks and benefits of introducing various types of AI to clinically related tasks (e.g., diagnosis, documentation, scheduling, workflow, and simple surgery) and in diverse medical specialities [<span>9</span>]. For purposes of our analysis, we will put aside the specific modes and domains of application and consider the essences of technology, writ large. We turn to Aristotelian philosophical constructs.</p><p>The etymology of the word is the Greek <i>technē</i> (or <i>ars</i>, in Latin)—commonly translated as craft. The ancient Greeks viewed <i>technē</i> as the antithesis of <i>tuchē</i> (luck). <i>Tuchē</i> refers to happenstance that is, events that occur by chance and are not controlled by humans. <i>Technē</i> aims to introduce order and predictability. Philosopher Martha Nussbaum notes, “<i>Technē</i> …. is a deliberate application of human intelligence to some part of the world, yielding control over <i>tuchē</i>; it is concerned with the management of need and prediction and control concerning future contingencies” [<span>10</span>]. Control of contingencies is the cardinal feature. This is highly relevant given that the practice of medicine is awash in contingencies.</p><p>Clinical medicine has been defined as: “a science-using practice that must diagnose and treat illnesses one by one” [<span>11</span>]. That definition helps situate AI in the context of medical practices. AI reinforces the notion that clinical medicine is “science-using.” It may support physicians' abilities in diagnosing, treating, and prognosticating by reducing the contingencies inherent in these clinical responsibilities. Although AI is founded on databases with an “N” measured in gigabytes, its application in clinical practice must remain resolutely in a mode of “one by one.”</p><p>Aristotle distinguished two branches of thought pertinent to human activities in practical domains: fabricating something (e.g., forging a porcelain plate) versus performing something (e.g., navigating a ship). Each activity requires a distinct cognitive disposition. The former requires <i>technē</i>—a productive mode with the following characteristics: it identifies features common to a group of cases (i.e., that which is generalizable); it culminates in definable outcomes external to the agent who was involved in the making; it explains phenomena through cause and effect; it is directly teachable; and, it succeeds in creating artifacts through the application of canonical methods. These characteristics of technology, especially the normative aspects, hearken back to the layer of <i>canonical competence</i>, as proposed in the retrofit of competence to CBME that we noted earlier.</p><p>In contrast to a technological pursuit, performing something corresponds to <i>phronēsis</i>. <i>Phronēsis</i> has been translated as prudence or practical wisdom. An analogous virtue in Confucianism is <i>ren</i> (humanness), moderated by <i>yi</i> (justice), which guides a person “to consider contingencies and localized factors” [<span>12</span>]. Practical wisdom allows one to apprehend the singular and its contextual factors (i.e., that which is particular to a case). It is less formulaic than <i>technē</i>; requires deliberation about worthwhileness and is thus tied to ethical judgment; is dependent on excellence of character; results in outcomes that are inextricable from the agent; and, is nurtured and transmitted through experiential learning. It has been argued that practices such as medicine and teaching, both focused on an N of 1, are endeavors best understood through the lens of <i>phronēsis</i> [<span>13, 14</span>].</p><p>It is important to underline that the above concepts have not been defined in crystalline terms and are open to debate. A discussion of philosophical controversies is beyond the remit of this article. The point we wish to make is that medical and pedagogical reasoning involve a choreography between generalization and particularization. These activities must integrate both nomothetic and idiographic approaches, concepts described by the philosopher Wilhelm Windelband [<span>15</span>]. AI, like all technology, cannot escape that dance.</p><p>AI will, undoubtedly, help formulate and support the generalizations and precepts routinely used in medicine. Its outputs will improve clinical decision making by rendering diagnostic evaluations, notably those that rely on visual interpretations (e.g., dermatology and radiology), and prognostications increasingly accurate. Time-honored heuristics that have served physicians well for generations will be fine-tuned or rendered obsolete by AI. If clinical trials confirm that overall patient outcomes are improved with AI, that is all to the good. However, it is not only the nameless “generic” patient that counts. The singular individual matters …. greatly. Would an AI robot be able to engage with a suffering patient in the manners of a wise clinician? Would a social robot be able to <i>see</i> the patient, apprehend their personhood, and accompany them on a healing journey in a comparable three-dimensional space as would a fellow human being? Randomized controlled studies have demonstrated that large language model-based systems can generate clinically relevant questions and responses as empathic in tone as those provided by clinicians [<span>16</span>]. Some have interpreted these findings as proof that Chatbot displays “bedside manners” equivalent or superior to those of clinicians [<span>17</span>]. Such conclusions are unwarranted. Interpersonal connections and empathy are complex and multifaceted constructs that cannot be reduced to a question-and-answer duet. Considering the nature of practical wisdom can sharpen distinctions between a human and machine clinical encounter.</p><p>Two empirical studies on <i>clinical phronēsis</i> have revealed some of its characteristics; these include having a capacity for sustaining hope, compassionate rule breaking, creating a bubble of undivided attention, encountering patients in ways that reveal the centrality of their care, and making decisions influenced by embodied perceptions such as gut feelings and intuitions [<span>2, 18</span>]. These, and the development of moral agency, are unlikely to be achievable by robots. AI is destined to become highly desirable for its assistive functions, particularly with respect to generalizations, computations, and pattern recognition. However, in terms of particularization and idiographic approaches within clinical and educational domains, and with respect to moral decision-making and clinical engagement, we contend that AI will never pass muster. A second reason to make haste … slowly!</p><p>The “Data, Information, Knowledge, Wisdom” pyramid has been used to represent the intellectual progression from possession of unprocessed data and facts to that of understanding and insight. The origins of this pyramid are uncertain [<span>19</span>]. We find it useful, not least because it positions “wisdom” at the pinnacle. This is, perhaps, more accessible than the “mysteries” visualized by Lepore in the top drawer of her knowledge hierarchy [<span>3</span>]. We propose practical wisdom as an aspirational goal. However, we do not have a magic recipe for its acquisition. Practiced discernment, guided reflection, and longitudinal experiential learning, preferably accompanied by sage mentors, are candidate ingredients.</p><p>The following commentary on technology, by Benjamin Chin-Yee, can help direct necessary reflections. He argues that “… technology does not refer simply to material artifacts but describes a particular way of thinking and interacting with the world; …(it) is not value-neutral but rather reflects a range of social choices and human values; …(it) does not serve as pure ends to fixed means but instead exists as a continuum of evolving means and ends” [<span>20</span>]. This framing suggests prudence is warranted when one is presented with new technology or new pedagogical models. Critical questions should be posed: (i) Whose interests are served by the innovation, and will anyone be overlooked? (ii) Will any tradition be threatened and if so, is the loss acceptable? (iii) Does its deployment suggest a realignment of core values and beliefs and if so, which are (intentionally or inadvertently) at risk of promotion or demotion? If the guiding principles of clinical medicine find their ethos and telos in the foundational relationship between patient and physician, then we, as healthcare professionals, are obliged to recall that we serve patients and students as the focal point of our duties. We must, therefore, assure that those who have entrusted us with their clinical and pedagogical care will benefit from and not be harmed by our innovations and creativity.</p><p>Both authors participated in the conception and design of this written perspective. Both authors worked on manuscript revisions and contributed to the final version.</p><p>The authors declare no conflict of interest.</p><p>Not applicable.</p><p>Informed consent is not applicable to this article as no human subjects were involved.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":100601,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Health Care Science\",\"volume\":\"3 2\",\"pages\":\"73-77\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2024-03-18\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1002/hcs2.86\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Health Care Science\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/hcs2.86\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Health Care Science","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/hcs2.86","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

第一层主要在医学本科教育(UGME)中形成,被称为 "典型能力",是基础性陈述知识与基本技能的混合体。更高阶的能力,如创造力、好奇心、适应性、谦逊和领导力等,则被推迟到培训的后期阶段,用 "医学的艺术 "这个老生常谈的短语来概括。据称,"艺术 "主要是在实习和独立实践中获得的。这种课程体系强化了 CBME 的还原论,并暗示 CBME 首先需要关注死记硬背的知识和技能,从而削弱了其在 UGME 中的适用性。CBME 的全盘采用与缺乏有力证据证明其优越性之间也存在着明显的脱节。加拿大长期以来一直在推广 CBME,但皇家内科与外科学院的一份报告证实,只有少数住院医师表示支持[7]。可以理解的是,许多地区已经决定放缓向 CBME 的过渡,或者考虑采用能力兼容的方法来取代基于能力的模式。在面对假定是有益的变革时,我们建议进行以下反思:这种变革所代表的知识是否有可能压倒对专业或机构价值不可或缺的其他理解方式?这种变革会不会既是变形也是变革?采用新概念或创新工具会在多大程度上为采用者(在本例中为教育管理者)带来好处,并最终为客户(在本例中为临床教师和学习者)带来更好的结果?也许是时候慢慢来了!人工智能的引入说明了医学界是如何从战略和实用角度接受、采纳和转化新理念的。它既令人兴奋,又具有颠覆性。这项技术在教育和临床领域并行发展。前者的前景和隐患已得到总结[8],而在临床相关任务(如诊断、文档编制、日程安排、工作流程和简单手术)和不同医学专业中引入各种类型人工智能的范围、风险和益处方面的研究、评论和评论文章也层出不穷[9]。为了便于分析,我们将抛开具体的应用模式和领域,从总体上考虑技术的本质。技术一词的词源是希腊语 technē(或拉丁语 ars)--通常译为工艺。古希腊人将technē视为tuchē(运气)的对立面。Tuchē指的是偶然性,即偶然发生的、不受人类控制的事件。技术旨在引入秩序和可预测性。哲学家玛莎-努斯鲍姆(Martha Nussbaum)指出:"Technē .... 是将人类智慧有意识地应用于世界的某个部分,从而对世界进行控制;它涉及对需求的管理以及对未来突发事件的预测和控制"[10]。对突发事件的控制是其主要特征。临床医学被定义为:"一种使用科学的实践活动,必须对未来的突发事件进行预测和控制"[10]:临床医学被定义为:"必须逐一诊断和治疗疾病的科学实践"[11]。这一定义有助于将人工智能置于医疗实践的背景中。人工智能强化了临床医学是 "使用科学 "的概念。它可以通过减少这些临床职责中固有的偶然性来支持医生的诊断、治疗和预后能力。虽然人工智能建立在以千兆字节为单位的 "N "数据库之上,但其在临床实践中的应用必须坚决保持 "一个接一个 "的模式。"亚里士多德区分了与人类在实践领域的活动相关的两个思维分支:制造某物(如锻造瓷盘)和执行某物(如驾船航行)。每种活动都需要不同的认知倾向。前者需要 "技术"(technē)--一种具有以下特征的生产模式:它能识别一组案例的共同特征(即可推广的特征);它能最终产生可定义的结果,而这些结果是外在于参与制作的人的;它能通过因果关系解释现象;它是可直接传授的;它能通过应用经典方法成功地创造出人工制品。技术的这些特点,尤其是规范性方面的特点,与我们前面提到的将能力改造为 CBME 时提出的典型能力层如出一辙。 Phronēsis被译为谨慎或实践智慧。儒家思想中类似的美德是 "仁",由 "义 "调节,引导人们 "考虑突发事件和局部因素"[12]。实践智慧使人能够理解单个事物及其背景因素(即个案的特殊性)。它没有技术那么公式化;需要考虑是否值得,因此与道德判断有关;取决于卓越的品格;结果与行为者密不可分;通过经验学习培养和传播。有观点认为,医疗和教学等实践活动都以 "1 "的 "N "为重点,因此最好从 "phronēsis "的角度来理解这些活动[13, 14]。对哲学争议的讨论超出了本文的范围。我们想说的是,医学和教学推理涉及概括化和特殊化之间的编排。这些活动必须同时整合名学和特学方法,这些概念由哲学家威廉-温德尔班德(Wilhelm Windelband)[15]描述。毫无疑问,人工智能将有助于制定和支持医学中常用的概括和概念。人工智能的产出将改善临床决策,使诊断评估(尤其是依赖视觉解读的诊断评估(如皮肤病学和放射学))和预后越来越准确。人工智能将对世代相传、行之有效的启发式方法进行微调或使其过时。如果临床试验证实,人工智能能改善患者的整体治疗效果,那将是一件好事。然而,重要的不仅仅是无名的 "普通 "病人。单个的个体也非常重要....。人工智能机器人能否像睿智的临床医生那样与饱受痛苦的病人进行交流?社交机器人能否像人类同伴一样,看到病人,理解他们的人格,并在可比的三维空间中陪伴他们踏上治疗之旅?随机对照研究已经证明,基于大型语言模型的系统可以生成与临床相关的问题,并做出与临床医生一样具有同理心的回答[16]。有些人将这些研究结果解释为聊天机器人的 "床边礼仪 "等同于或优于临床医生的证明[17]。这种结论是没有根据的。人际关系和同理心是复杂的、多层面的概念,不能简化为一问一答的二重唱。关于临床用语的两项实证研究揭示了临床用语的一些特征,其中包括有能力维持希望、富有同情心地打破常规、创造一个全神贯注的气泡、以揭示患者护理中心地位的方式接触患者,以及受直觉和直觉等具身感知的影响做出决定[2, 18]。这些,以及道德代理的发展,都不太可能由机器人来实现。人工智能因其辅助功能,特别是在概括、计算和模式识别方面的功能,注定会变得非常受欢迎。然而,就临床和教育领域的特殊化和特异性方法而言,以及就道德决策和临床参与而言,我们认为人工智能永远不会通过审查。第二个理由是要抓紧时间......慢慢来!"数据、信息、知识、智慧 "金字塔被用来代表从拥有未经处理的数据和事实到理解和洞察的智力发展过程。这个金字塔的起源并不确定[19]。我们认为它很有用,尤其是因为它将 "智慧 "置于顶峰。这或许比列波尔(Lepore)将 "奥秘 "置于其知识层次结构的顶层更容易理解[3]。我们建议将实用智慧作为一个理想目标。然而,我们并没有获得这种智慧的神奇秘方。以下本杰明-钱-易(Benjamin Chin-Yee)关于技术的评论可以帮助我们进行必要的思考。他认为,"......技术不仅仅是指物质人工制品,而是描述了一种特定的思维方式和与世界互动的方式;......(技术)不是价值中立的,而是反映了一系列社会选择和人类价值观;......(技术)不是作为固定手段的纯粹目的,而是作为不断发展的手段和目的的连续体"[20]。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Transformations in medical education: A prudential perspective

A decade ago we asked the question, “Is there something in medicine that is eternal or enduring?” Our aim was to write a manuscript entitled, “That which does not change in medicine.” The publication begins as follows: “The practice of medicine involves continual change, driven by a constant stream of developments in the understanding of biological structure and function relevant to human diseases, and the parallel improvements in pharmacologic and other technological interventions. This change is also driven by evolving social philosophies, ethical trends, and lifestyles.” [1] That preamble reverberates as strongly now as then, perhaps even more so, given the velocity of technological change. When we deliberated on which aspects of medical practice should remain stable, we had few premonitions that implantable chips, robotic surgery, virtual reality, and artificial intelligence (AI) would soon become ubiquitous. The needle has clearly moved, propelled by extraordinary advances in bioengineering, computer and data sciences; major shifts in the governance and organization of clinical practice; and powerful sociocultural trends.

As we explore current transformative developments we are reminded of our earlier conclusions: that certain dimensions of medical practice are, indeed, immutable. Most importantly, the relationship between physician and patient depends on moral obligations, characterized by a compassionate response best described as clinical engagement [2]. The requisite virtues are affective as much as cognitive. The challenge for educators, physicians, and policymakers is to accommodate the benefits of transformational change, both technological and conceptual, whilst remaining true to the fundamental, dyadic clinical relationship. Thus, pedagogic change should welcome innovations but do so with restraint that is, with an attitudinal disposition that is neither cynical nor inhibitory but rather alert and mindful, especially when faced with announcements that a given innovation will solve the problems of an overburdened hospital system. By insisting on a cautious approach we may avoid the pendulum that swings too far, resulting in unintended consequences and costly backtracking to undo the damage of untrammeled enthusiasms.

We consider two illustrative innovations germane to healthcare delivery: one in medical education and one in technology. We try to anticipate and understand impacts and conclude by posing a set of questions that may be useful to those who manage systemic changes.

An innovation, unfolding in medical schools world-wide and often regarded as “transformative,” is competency-based medical education (CBME). We analyze this trend, relying on a hierarchy of knowledge as a frame of reference.

The historian Jill Lepore, using the metaphor of a filing cabinet with four drawers, proposed a categorization of knowledge [3]. Each drawer contains knowledge of a different kind. The top one is for “mysteries”; the second one is for “facts”; the third is for “numbers”; and the lowest is for “data”. With respect to their epistemologies, she suggests that mysteries are accessible by revelation (thus, discernable by “God”); facts are derived by way of experimental scientific methods or observations (i.e., the product of the natural sciences and the humanities); numbers are entities that can be counted (e.g., measured by statisticians and epidemiologists); and, data are generated by computers (i.e., the product of data science). Each of these categories is potentially valuable to medical practice.

CBME lives, metaphorically speaking, in Lepore's third drawer. Its ontology is reductionist; it views professional development as the accumulation of small quanta of knowledge, accompanied by the accretion of discrete psychomotor skills, which are then presented as stepwise progress in personal abilities. Its epistemology, given the tenacity with which it defines educational outcomes in behaviorally measurable ways, is aligned with psychometrics. The model has been able to mitigate well-documented deficiencies in the assessments of clinical performance; however, its implementation, theoretical coherence, and axiological foundations have been criticized. Numerous commentators have bemoaned that CBME has monopolized resources, distracted educational leaders, undermined the in loco parentis nature of clinical teaching, and, most distressingly, failed to provide a holistic picture of students' evolving professional capabilities [4].

CBME is fraught with controversy. It has become apparent that tensions exist between CBME and the obligation to attend to professional identity formation [5]. A recent commentary attempts to rescue the concept of “competencies” by distinguishing it from “competence” and foregrounding the latter; it argues that competence is multilayered and visualizes the continuum of medical education as existing on three separate levels [6]. The first layer, considered to develop primarily in undergraduate medical education (UGME) and labeled “canonical competence,” represents an amalgam of foundational declarative knowledge with a sprinkling of basic skills. Higher order capabilities, such as creativity, curiosity, adaptability, humility, and leadership, are postponed to later phases of training, in layers encapsulated by the hackneyed phrase, “the art of medicine.” The “art” is supposedly acquired preferentially during residency and in independent practice. This curricular edifice reinforces reductionist aspects of CBME and, in suggesting that it first needs to focus on rote knowledge and skills, undermines arguments for its appropriateness in UGME. There is also a striking disconnect between the wholesale adoption of CBME and the paucity of compelling evidence for its superiority. In Canada, a country that has long promoted CBME, a report of the Royal College of Physicians and Surgeons has confirmed that only a small minority of resident physicians are supportive [7]. Understandably, many jurisdictions have decided to slacken their transition to CBME or to consider adopting a competency-compatible approach in lieu of a competency-based model.

The experience with CBME should serve as a note of caution for leaders in the health professions. When faced with changes that are presumed to be salutary, we recommend the following reflections: Might the knowledge represented by this transformation risk overwhelming alternative ways of understanding indispensable to professional or institutional values? Could the change be deforming as much as transforming? To what extent does the adoption of a new concept or innovative tool result in advantages for the adopter (in this illustration, educational managers) and culminate in improved outcomes for the client (in this illustration, clinical teachers and learners)? Perhaps it is time to make haste slowly!

The introduction of AI illustrates how new ideas are received, adopted, and translated strategically and pragmatically in medicine. It has been heralded as exciting yet also as disruptive. This technology has unfolded pari passu in educational and clinical domains. Its promises and pitfalls in the former have been summarized [8] and there has been an avalanche of studies, reviews, and commentaries on the scope, risks and benefits of introducing various types of AI to clinically related tasks (e.g., diagnosis, documentation, scheduling, workflow, and simple surgery) and in diverse medical specialities [9]. For purposes of our analysis, we will put aside the specific modes and domains of application and consider the essences of technology, writ large. We turn to Aristotelian philosophical constructs.

The etymology of the word is the Greek technē (or ars, in Latin)—commonly translated as craft. The ancient Greeks viewed technē as the antithesis of tuchē (luck). Tuchē refers to happenstance that is, events that occur by chance and are not controlled by humans. Technē aims to introduce order and predictability. Philosopher Martha Nussbaum notes, “Technē …. is a deliberate application of human intelligence to some part of the world, yielding control over tuchē; it is concerned with the management of need and prediction and control concerning future contingencies” [10]. Control of contingencies is the cardinal feature. This is highly relevant given that the practice of medicine is awash in contingencies.

Clinical medicine has been defined as: “a science-using practice that must diagnose and treat illnesses one by one” [11]. That definition helps situate AI in the context of medical practices. AI reinforces the notion that clinical medicine is “science-using.” It may support physicians' abilities in diagnosing, treating, and prognosticating by reducing the contingencies inherent in these clinical responsibilities. Although AI is founded on databases with an “N” measured in gigabytes, its application in clinical practice must remain resolutely in a mode of “one by one.”

Aristotle distinguished two branches of thought pertinent to human activities in practical domains: fabricating something (e.g., forging a porcelain plate) versus performing something (e.g., navigating a ship). Each activity requires a distinct cognitive disposition. The former requires technē—a productive mode with the following characteristics: it identifies features common to a group of cases (i.e., that which is generalizable); it culminates in definable outcomes external to the agent who was involved in the making; it explains phenomena through cause and effect; it is directly teachable; and, it succeeds in creating artifacts through the application of canonical methods. These characteristics of technology, especially the normative aspects, hearken back to the layer of canonical competence, as proposed in the retrofit of competence to CBME that we noted earlier.

In contrast to a technological pursuit, performing something corresponds to phronēsis. Phronēsis has been translated as prudence or practical wisdom. An analogous virtue in Confucianism is ren (humanness), moderated by yi (justice), which guides a person “to consider contingencies and localized factors” [12]. Practical wisdom allows one to apprehend the singular and its contextual factors (i.e., that which is particular to a case). It is less formulaic than technē; requires deliberation about worthwhileness and is thus tied to ethical judgment; is dependent on excellence of character; results in outcomes that are inextricable from the agent; and, is nurtured and transmitted through experiential learning. It has been argued that practices such as medicine and teaching, both focused on an N of 1, are endeavors best understood through the lens of phronēsis [13, 14].

It is important to underline that the above concepts have not been defined in crystalline terms and are open to debate. A discussion of philosophical controversies is beyond the remit of this article. The point we wish to make is that medical and pedagogical reasoning involve a choreography between generalization and particularization. These activities must integrate both nomothetic and idiographic approaches, concepts described by the philosopher Wilhelm Windelband [15]. AI, like all technology, cannot escape that dance.

AI will, undoubtedly, help formulate and support the generalizations and precepts routinely used in medicine. Its outputs will improve clinical decision making by rendering diagnostic evaluations, notably those that rely on visual interpretations (e.g., dermatology and radiology), and prognostications increasingly accurate. Time-honored heuristics that have served physicians well for generations will be fine-tuned or rendered obsolete by AI. If clinical trials confirm that overall patient outcomes are improved with AI, that is all to the good. However, it is not only the nameless “generic” patient that counts. The singular individual matters …. greatly. Would an AI robot be able to engage with a suffering patient in the manners of a wise clinician? Would a social robot be able to see the patient, apprehend their personhood, and accompany them on a healing journey in a comparable three-dimensional space as would a fellow human being? Randomized controlled studies have demonstrated that large language model-based systems can generate clinically relevant questions and responses as empathic in tone as those provided by clinicians [16]. Some have interpreted these findings as proof that Chatbot displays “bedside manners” equivalent or superior to those of clinicians [17]. Such conclusions are unwarranted. Interpersonal connections and empathy are complex and multifaceted constructs that cannot be reduced to a question-and-answer duet. Considering the nature of practical wisdom can sharpen distinctions between a human and machine clinical encounter.

Two empirical studies on clinical phronēsis have revealed some of its characteristics; these include having a capacity for sustaining hope, compassionate rule breaking, creating a bubble of undivided attention, encountering patients in ways that reveal the centrality of their care, and making decisions influenced by embodied perceptions such as gut feelings and intuitions [2, 18]. These, and the development of moral agency, are unlikely to be achievable by robots. AI is destined to become highly desirable for its assistive functions, particularly with respect to generalizations, computations, and pattern recognition. However, in terms of particularization and idiographic approaches within clinical and educational domains, and with respect to moral decision-making and clinical engagement, we contend that AI will never pass muster. A second reason to make haste … slowly!

The “Data, Information, Knowledge, Wisdom” pyramid has been used to represent the intellectual progression from possession of unprocessed data and facts to that of understanding and insight. The origins of this pyramid are uncertain [19]. We find it useful, not least because it positions “wisdom” at the pinnacle. This is, perhaps, more accessible than the “mysteries” visualized by Lepore in the top drawer of her knowledge hierarchy [3]. We propose practical wisdom as an aspirational goal. However, we do not have a magic recipe for its acquisition. Practiced discernment, guided reflection, and longitudinal experiential learning, preferably accompanied by sage mentors, are candidate ingredients.

The following commentary on technology, by Benjamin Chin-Yee, can help direct necessary reflections. He argues that “… technology does not refer simply to material artifacts but describes a particular way of thinking and interacting with the world; …(it) is not value-neutral but rather reflects a range of social choices and human values; …(it) does not serve as pure ends to fixed means but instead exists as a continuum of evolving means and ends” [20]. This framing suggests prudence is warranted when one is presented with new technology or new pedagogical models. Critical questions should be posed: (i) Whose interests are served by the innovation, and will anyone be overlooked? (ii) Will any tradition be threatened and if so, is the loss acceptable? (iii) Does its deployment suggest a realignment of core values and beliefs and if so, which are (intentionally or inadvertently) at risk of promotion or demotion? If the guiding principles of clinical medicine find their ethos and telos in the foundational relationship between patient and physician, then we, as healthcare professionals, are obliged to recall that we serve patients and students as the focal point of our duties. We must, therefore, assure that those who have entrusted us with their clinical and pedagogical care will benefit from and not be harmed by our innovations and creativity.

Both authors participated in the conception and design of this written perspective. Both authors worked on manuscript revisions and contributed to the final version.

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

Not applicable.

Informed consent is not applicable to this article as no human subjects were involved.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
0.90
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
Study protocol: A national cross-sectional study on psychology and behavior investigation of Chinese residents in 2023. Caregiving in Asia: Priority areas for research, policy, and practice to support family caregivers. Innovative public strategies in response to COVID-19: A review of practices from China. Sixty years of ethical evolution: The 2024 revision of the Declaration of Helsinki (DoH). A novel ensemble ARIMA-LSTM approach for evaluating COVID-19 cases and future outbreak preparedness.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1