{"title":"对应理论与现实","authors":"","doi":"10.1007/s10992-024-09745-8","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<h3>Abstract</h3> <p>Lewis (<em>The Journal of Philosophy</em>, <em>65</em>(5), 113–126, <span>1968</span>) attempts to provide an account of modal talk in terms of the resources of <em>counterpart theory</em>, a first-order theory that eschews transworld identity. First, a regimentation of natural language modal claims into sentences of a formal first-order modal language L is assumed. Second, a translation scheme from L-sentences to sentences of the language of the theory is provided. According to Hazen (<em>The Journal of Philosophy</em>, <em>76</em>(6), 319–338, <span>1979</span>) and Fara & Williamson (<em>Mind</em>, <em>114</em>(453), 1–30, <span>2005</span>), the account cannot handle certain natural language modal claims involving a notion of <em>actuality</em>. The challenge has two parts. First, in order to handle such claims, the initial formal modal language that natural language modal claims are regimented into must extend L with something like an actuality operator. Second, certain ways that Lewis’ translation scheme for L might be extended to accommodate an actuality operator are unacceptable. Meyer (<em>Mind</em>, <em>122</em>(485), 27–42, <span>2013</span>) attempts to defend Lewis’ approach. First, Meyer holds that in order to handle such claims, the formal modal language L<span> <span>\\(^*\\)</span> </span> that we initially regiment our natural language claims into need not contain an actuality operator. Instead, we can make do with other resources. Next, Meyer provides an alternative translation scheme from L<span> <span>\\(^*\\)</span> </span>-sentences to sentences of an enriched language of counterpart theory. Unfortunately, Meyer’s approach fails to provide an appropriate counterpart theoretic account of natural language modal claims. In this paper, I demonstrate that failure.</p>","PeriodicalId":51526,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC","volume":"24 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2024-04-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Counterpart Theory and Actuality\",\"authors\":\"\",\"doi\":\"10.1007/s10992-024-09745-8\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<h3>Abstract</h3> <p>Lewis (<em>The Journal of Philosophy</em>, <em>65</em>(5), 113–126, <span>1968</span>) attempts to provide an account of modal talk in terms of the resources of <em>counterpart theory</em>, a first-order theory that eschews transworld identity. First, a regimentation of natural language modal claims into sentences of a formal first-order modal language L is assumed. Second, a translation scheme from L-sentences to sentences of the language of the theory is provided. According to Hazen (<em>The Journal of Philosophy</em>, <em>76</em>(6), 319–338, <span>1979</span>) and Fara & Williamson (<em>Mind</em>, <em>114</em>(453), 1–30, <span>2005</span>), the account cannot handle certain natural language modal claims involving a notion of <em>actuality</em>. The challenge has two parts. First, in order to handle such claims, the initial formal modal language that natural language modal claims are regimented into must extend L with something like an actuality operator. Second, certain ways that Lewis’ translation scheme for L might be extended to accommodate an actuality operator are unacceptable. Meyer (<em>Mind</em>, <em>122</em>(485), 27–42, <span>2013</span>) attempts to defend Lewis’ approach. First, Meyer holds that in order to handle such claims, the formal modal language L<span> <span>\\\\(^*\\\\)</span> </span> that we initially regiment our natural language claims into need not contain an actuality operator. Instead, we can make do with other resources. Next, Meyer provides an alternative translation scheme from L<span> <span>\\\\(^*\\\\)</span> </span>-sentences to sentences of an enriched language of counterpart theory. Unfortunately, Meyer’s approach fails to provide an appropriate counterpart theoretic account of natural language modal claims. In this paper, I demonstrate that failure.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":51526,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC\",\"volume\":\"24 1\",\"pages\":\"\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.7000,\"publicationDate\":\"2024-04-02\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-024-09745-8\",\"RegionNum\":1,\"RegionCategory\":\"哲学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"PHILOSOPHY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-024-09745-8","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
摘要
摘要 刘易斯(《哲学杂志》,65(5), 113-126, 1968 年)试图从对应理论(一种回避跨世界同一性的一阶理论)的资源角度来解释模态话语。首先,假定将自然语言的模态主张规范化为形式一阶模态语言 L 的句子。其次,提供了一个从 L 句子到理论语言句子的翻译方案。根据 Hazen(《哲学杂志》,76(6), 319-338, 1979 年)和 Fara & Williamson(《心智》,114(453), 1-30, 2005 年)的观点,该论述无法处理某些涉及实际性概念的自然语言模态主张。这一难题有两个方面。首先,为了处理这类主张,自然语言模态主张所规范的初始形式模态语言必须用类似实际性运算符的东西来扩展 L。其次,刘易斯的 L 翻译方案可能会扩展以容纳一个实际性算子,但这种扩展的某些方式是不可接受的。迈耶(Mind,122(485),27-42,2013)试图为刘易斯的方法辩护。首先,迈耶认为,为了处理这样的诉求,我们最初将自然语言诉求规范化的形式模态语言L \(^*\)不需要包含实存性运算符。相反,我们可以利用其他资源。接下来,迈耶提供了一个从 L (^*\)句子到对应理论的丰富语言句子的另一种翻译方案。不幸的是,Meyer 的方法未能为自然语言模态主张提供一个合适的对应理论解释。在本文中,我将证明这一失败。
Lewis (The Journal of Philosophy, 65(5), 113–126, 1968) attempts to provide an account of modal talk in terms of the resources of counterpart theory, a first-order theory that eschews transworld identity. First, a regimentation of natural language modal claims into sentences of a formal first-order modal language L is assumed. Second, a translation scheme from L-sentences to sentences of the language of the theory is provided. According to Hazen (The Journal of Philosophy, 76(6), 319–338, 1979) and Fara & Williamson (Mind, 114(453), 1–30, 2005), the account cannot handle certain natural language modal claims involving a notion of actuality. The challenge has two parts. First, in order to handle such claims, the initial formal modal language that natural language modal claims are regimented into must extend L with something like an actuality operator. Second, certain ways that Lewis’ translation scheme for L might be extended to accommodate an actuality operator are unacceptable. Meyer (Mind, 122(485), 27–42, 2013) attempts to defend Lewis’ approach. First, Meyer holds that in order to handle such claims, the formal modal language L\(^*\) that we initially regiment our natural language claims into need not contain an actuality operator. Instead, we can make do with other resources. Next, Meyer provides an alternative translation scheme from L\(^*\)-sentences to sentences of an enriched language of counterpart theory. Unfortunately, Meyer’s approach fails to provide an appropriate counterpart theoretic account of natural language modal claims. In this paper, I demonstrate that failure.
期刊介绍:
The Journal of Philosophical Logic aims to provide a forum for work at the crossroads of philosophy and logic, old and new, with contributions ranging from conceptual to technical. Accordingly, the Journal invites papers in all of the traditional areas of philosophical logic, including but not limited to: various versions of modal, temporal, epistemic, and deontic logic; constructive logics; relevance and other sub-classical logics; many-valued logics; logics of conditionals; quantum logic; decision theory, inductive logic, logics of belief change, and formal epistemology; defeasible and nonmonotonic logics; formal philosophy of language; vagueness; and theories of truth and validity. In addition to publishing papers on philosophical logic in this familiar sense of the term, the Journal also invites papers on extensions of logic to new areas of application, and on the philosophical issues to which these give rise. The Journal places a special emphasis on the applications of philosophical logic in other disciplines, not only in mathematics and the natural sciences but also, for example, in computer science, artificial intelligence, cognitive science, linguistics, jurisprudence, and the social sciences, such as economics, sociology, and political science.