保护有争议的思想:在社交媒体助长愤怒的时代编辑生物伦理学。

IF 16.4 1区 化学 Q1 CHEMISTRY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Accounts of Chemical Research Pub Date : 2024-08-19 DOI:10.1111/bioe.13343
Udo Schuklenk
{"title":"保护有争议的思想:在社交媒体助长愤怒的时代编辑生物伦理学。","authors":"Udo Schuklenk","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13343","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Much has been said about the harmful role played by algorithms that are deployed by social media platforms to ensure engagement. Less has arguably been said about the impact this had on editorial practices of academic journals that publish content that is vulnerable to the machinations of said algorithms. We have seen a few of these events over the years in our field, bioethics. Interested readers of the journal will recall the global outcry a paper by Alberto Giubilini and Francesca Minerva. It was caused by what they called provocatively ‘after-birth abortion’.1 In academic terms, the paper has been a runaway success, netting our colleagues over at the <i>Journal of medical ethics</i> a bit more than a million article downloads. Career development wise there were negative consequences suffered by both authors. Given that the Editor of the journal was under tremendous pressure to resign or be fired, I did publish a supportive Editorial in this journal at the time.2 Do you recall Rebecca Tuvel's article about transracialism in <i>Hypathia</i> some years back?3 The Editor of the journal, and the—at the time—junior, tenure-track academic, who published the paper, were subjected to endless ad hominem attacks on various social media platforms. Particularly disturbing was the participation of senior tenured academics in what constituted a concerted effort of the academic outrage machine to effectively end the academic career of a junior female philosopher without job security. Much of this pressure, as in the other examples I'm about to mention, was facilitated by social media platforms. Academics seemingly take to signing petitions aimed at boycotting, demanding resignations, retractions, and worse, in case they find published peer reviewed content disagreeable. Virtue signalling at its finest. Perhaps a response in the pages of the journal that published the offending paper is seen as too old fashioned by this sort of academic activism.</p><p>I have always thought that these types of reactions display a deeply troubling understanding of academic freedom. They are celebrating and defending the academic freedom of agreeable content, while failing to defend academic freedom when it matters most, namely when the content is disagreeable. There will be all sorts of verbiage thrown around from ‘epistemic injustice’ to varieties of ‘privilege’, but typically, the apparently so obviously flawed substance of what one disagrees with isn't confronted. However, precisely that is what ought to happen if one cared enough to ensure that diversity of thought is maintained in a field of inquiry such as bioethics. That doesn't mean that one has to concede a methodological free-for-all. I have gone on the record stating that public reason-based arguments are a <i>conditio sine qua non</i> of bioethical analyses that aim to have a universal appeal. Somewhat reassuringly the outrage machine tends to direct its vitriol at particular conclusions rather than the bioethical method. In the case of Tuvel, for instance, vague claims were made that she (and apparently the journal's referees) showed a lack of understanding of ‘the literature’. Suffice it to say that this was never substantiated. It really was about the disagreeable conclusions Tuvel arrived at.</p><p>In this journal, we have published during the last few years a fair number of papers by a small group of—arguably—activist antichoice academic writers. The conclusion of their papers was, invariably, abortion is bad, or some such. Prochoice academic social media activists lambasted the journal for publishing such content, questioning the integrity of both us Editors of the journal as well as the competence of our reviewers. We gave quite a bit of space to these authors and their views, provided their content passed standard peer review. Our—unwritten—policy, when it comes to such content, is to try to secure at least two reviewers, one who is somewhat supportive of the conclusions reached by these authors and one who is likely opposed to their conclusions.</p><p>Still, the social media outrage machine would have none of it. Peer review or not, such offending content should not be published. Suspicions of us Editors' motives were raised, were we perhaps secret supporters of a Handmaid's Tale type society? Also, of course, questions about the quality of the journal and its review processes appeared. How could we publish such obviously flawed papers? The operating principle seemed to be to throw mud against the journal, its Editors and its reviewers and hope that something sticks. Those concerns strangely never seem to arise vis a vis content these same academic social media activists find agreeable. These papers generated a fair bit of traction in that authors responded critically to this content in the pages of the journal. Publishing these arguments and the responses tested these views in an academically rigorous way. Publishing these arguments also helps addressing common claims of liberal bias that are routinely leveled by conservatives against the field of bioethics.</p><p>Similar issues surrounded a provocative Guest Editorial by Joona Räsänen.4 He discusses the health implications of sexual loneliness and quotes at one point a controversial conservative psychologist who reportedly favours societally enforced monogamy. The Guest Editorial was seen by the internet outrage machine as condoning incels' sexual abuse of women, among other crimes. I encourage you to read it for yourself. I can't find much else than a call on bioethicists to undertake critical ethical analyses of the arguments the opposing camps present.</p><p>Currently the journal features a Call for Papers for a special issue analysing the bioethical and medical ethics issues implications of the human tragedy unfolding in Gaza. I wrote to the brave Guest Editors, who stepped forward with a special issue proposal, that they should expect no thanks and plenty of vitriol, guaranteed by social media algorithms and the actors that feed them. They chose, among possible topics for potential contributors to consider, ‘The ethics of treating terrorists, and specifically the right of healthcare providers to refuse providing care to terrorists.’ Well, to cut a long story short, labelling an unnamed side in this conflict ‘terrorist’ offended a fair number of academic social media activists who proceeded to declaring that they would cease reviewing henceforth for the journal or contributing to it. Virtue signalling at its finest. I hope I'm not divulging too much when I note that those who protested loudest never contributed to the journal, either as reviewers or as authors.</p><p>What puzzles me about this behaviour is that it is antithetical to what academic freedom is all about. An appropriate response, as in the other examples I mentioned, would have been to submit a paper to said guest editors that takes their framing of the issue to task.</p><p>Let me end this Editorial by stating that we, as Editors of <i>Bioethics</i>, remain committed to protecting the journal as a space where diverse views will be published, including views some readers will consider offensive. The reader would be well advised not to draw conclusions from what content we publish on the views we as Editors of the journal hold on those issues. The journal has never been and will never become a mouthpiece for our own views.</p>","PeriodicalId":1,"journal":{"name":"Accounts of Chemical Research","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":16.4000,"publicationDate":"2024-08-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/bioe.13343","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Protecting controversial thought: Editing Bioethics in the age of social media facilitated outrage\",\"authors\":\"Udo Schuklenk\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/bioe.13343\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>Much has been said about the harmful role played by algorithms that are deployed by social media platforms to ensure engagement. Less has arguably been said about the impact this had on editorial practices of academic journals that publish content that is vulnerable to the machinations of said algorithms. We have seen a few of these events over the years in our field, bioethics. Interested readers of the journal will recall the global outcry a paper by Alberto Giubilini and Francesca Minerva. It was caused by what they called provocatively ‘after-birth abortion’.1 In academic terms, the paper has been a runaway success, netting our colleagues over at the <i>Journal of medical ethics</i> a bit more than a million article downloads. Career development wise there were negative consequences suffered by both authors. Given that the Editor of the journal was under tremendous pressure to resign or be fired, I did publish a supportive Editorial in this journal at the time.2 Do you recall Rebecca Tuvel's article about transracialism in <i>Hypathia</i> some years back?3 The Editor of the journal, and the—at the time—junior, tenure-track academic, who published the paper, were subjected to endless ad hominem attacks on various social media platforms. Particularly disturbing was the participation of senior tenured academics in what constituted a concerted effort of the academic outrage machine to effectively end the academic career of a junior female philosopher without job security. Much of this pressure, as in the other examples I'm about to mention, was facilitated by social media platforms. Academics seemingly take to signing petitions aimed at boycotting, demanding resignations, retractions, and worse, in case they find published peer reviewed content disagreeable. Virtue signalling at its finest. Perhaps a response in the pages of the journal that published the offending paper is seen as too old fashioned by this sort of academic activism.</p><p>I have always thought that these types of reactions display a deeply troubling understanding of academic freedom. They are celebrating and defending the academic freedom of agreeable content, while failing to defend academic freedom when it matters most, namely when the content is disagreeable. There will be all sorts of verbiage thrown around from ‘epistemic injustice’ to varieties of ‘privilege’, but typically, the apparently so obviously flawed substance of what one disagrees with isn't confronted. However, precisely that is what ought to happen if one cared enough to ensure that diversity of thought is maintained in a field of inquiry such as bioethics. That doesn't mean that one has to concede a methodological free-for-all. I have gone on the record stating that public reason-based arguments are a <i>conditio sine qua non</i> of bioethical analyses that aim to have a universal appeal. Somewhat reassuringly the outrage machine tends to direct its vitriol at particular conclusions rather than the bioethical method. In the case of Tuvel, for instance, vague claims were made that she (and apparently the journal's referees) showed a lack of understanding of ‘the literature’. Suffice it to say that this was never substantiated. It really was about the disagreeable conclusions Tuvel arrived at.</p><p>In this journal, we have published during the last few years a fair number of papers by a small group of—arguably—activist antichoice academic writers. The conclusion of their papers was, invariably, abortion is bad, or some such. Prochoice academic social media activists lambasted the journal for publishing such content, questioning the integrity of both us Editors of the journal as well as the competence of our reviewers. We gave quite a bit of space to these authors and their views, provided their content passed standard peer review. Our—unwritten—policy, when it comes to such content, is to try to secure at least two reviewers, one who is somewhat supportive of the conclusions reached by these authors and one who is likely opposed to their conclusions.</p><p>Still, the social media outrage machine would have none of it. Peer review or not, such offending content should not be published. Suspicions of us Editors' motives were raised, were we perhaps secret supporters of a Handmaid's Tale type society? Also, of course, questions about the quality of the journal and its review processes appeared. How could we publish such obviously flawed papers? The operating principle seemed to be to throw mud against the journal, its Editors and its reviewers and hope that something sticks. Those concerns strangely never seem to arise vis a vis content these same academic social media activists find agreeable. These papers generated a fair bit of traction in that authors responded critically to this content in the pages of the journal. Publishing these arguments and the responses tested these views in an academically rigorous way. Publishing these arguments also helps addressing common claims of liberal bias that are routinely leveled by conservatives against the field of bioethics.</p><p>Similar issues surrounded a provocative Guest Editorial by Joona Räsänen.4 He discusses the health implications of sexual loneliness and quotes at one point a controversial conservative psychologist who reportedly favours societally enforced monogamy. The Guest Editorial was seen by the internet outrage machine as condoning incels' sexual abuse of women, among other crimes. I encourage you to read it for yourself. I can't find much else than a call on bioethicists to undertake critical ethical analyses of the arguments the opposing camps present.</p><p>Currently the journal features a Call for Papers for a special issue analysing the bioethical and medical ethics issues implications of the human tragedy unfolding in Gaza. I wrote to the brave Guest Editors, who stepped forward with a special issue proposal, that they should expect no thanks and plenty of vitriol, guaranteed by social media algorithms and the actors that feed them. They chose, among possible topics for potential contributors to consider, ‘The ethics of treating terrorists, and specifically the right of healthcare providers to refuse providing care to terrorists.’ Well, to cut a long story short, labelling an unnamed side in this conflict ‘terrorist’ offended a fair number of academic social media activists who proceeded to declaring that they would cease reviewing henceforth for the journal or contributing to it. Virtue signalling at its finest. I hope I'm not divulging too much when I note that those who protested loudest never contributed to the journal, either as reviewers or as authors.</p><p>What puzzles me about this behaviour is that it is antithetical to what academic freedom is all about. An appropriate response, as in the other examples I mentioned, would have been to submit a paper to said guest editors that takes their framing of the issue to task.</p><p>Let me end this Editorial by stating that we, as Editors of <i>Bioethics</i>, remain committed to protecting the journal as a space where diverse views will be published, including views some readers will consider offensive. The reader would be well advised not to draw conclusions from what content we publish on the views we as Editors of the journal hold on those issues. The journal has never been and will never become a mouthpiece for our own views.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":1,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Accounts of Chemical Research\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":16.4000,\"publicationDate\":\"2024-08-19\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/bioe.13343\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Accounts of Chemical Research\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"98\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.13343\",\"RegionNum\":1,\"RegionCategory\":\"化学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q1\",\"JCRName\":\"CHEMISTRY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Accounts of Chemical Research","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.13343","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"化学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"CHEMISTRY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

关于社交媒体平台为确保参与度而采用的算法所发挥的有害作用,人们已经说了很多。但这对学术期刊编辑工作的影响却很少有人提及,因为学术期刊发表的内容很容易受到上述算法的影响。多年来,我们在自己的领域--生命伦理学--就发生过几起这样的事件。对本刊感兴趣的读者一定还记得阿尔贝托-朱比利尼(Alberto Giubilini)和弗朗西斯卡-米涅瓦(Francesca Minerva)的一篇论文在全球引起的轩然大波。1 在学术方面,这篇论文取得了巨大成功,《医学伦理学杂志》的同事们因此获得了超过一百万次的文章下载。在职业发展方面,两位作者都受到了负面影响。2 您还记得几年前丽贝卡-图维尔(Rebecca Tuvel)在《Hypathia》杂志上发表的关于跨种族主义的文章吗?3 该杂志的编辑,以及当时发表该论文的那位终身教职的初级学者,在各种社交媒体平台上受到了无休止的人身攻击。尤其令人不安的是,资深终身教职学者参与了学术愤怒机器的协同努力,以有效结束一位没有工作保障的初级女哲学家的学术生涯。正如我将要提到的其他例子一样,这种压力在很大程度上是由社交媒体平台促成的。学者们一旦发现发表的同行评议内容令人不快,似乎就会签署旨在抵制、要求辞职、撤稿甚至更糟的请愿书。这是最完美的道德信号。也许在发表违规论文的期刊上做出回应在这类学术激进主义看来过于老套。我一直认为,这类反应显示了对学术自由的一种令人深感不安的理解。他们在赞美和捍卫内容合意的学术自由,而在最重要的时候,即内容不合意的时候,却没有捍卫学术自由。从 "认识论上的不公正 "到各种 "特权",他们会抛出各种各样的措辞,但通常情况下,他们不会正视自己不同意的内容中明显存在缺陷的实质。然而,如果一个人足够关心如何在生命伦理学这样的研究领域保持思想的多样性,那么恰恰就应该这样做。这并不意味着我们必须承认方法论上的自由竞争。我曾公开表示,以公共理性为基础的论证是生物伦理分析具有普遍吸引力的必要条件。令人稍感欣慰的是,"愤怒机器 "倾向于将矛头指向特定的结论,而不是生物伦理方法。例如,在图维尔的案例中,有人含糊其辞地声称她(显然还有期刊的审稿人)缺乏对 "文献 "的理解。可以说,这种说法从未得到证实。在过去几年里,我们在本刊上发表了相当数量的论文,这些论文是由一小群--可以说是积极的反选择学术作家--撰写的。他们论文的结论无一例外都是 "堕胎是坏事 "之类的。支持选择权的学术社交媒体活动家抨击期刊发表此类内容,质疑我们这些期刊编辑的诚信以及审稿人的能力。我们给了这些作者和他们的观点相当多的版面,只要他们的内容通过了标准的同行评审。对于此类内容,我们不成文的政策是尽量保证至少有两位审稿人,一位在某种程度上支持这些作者得出的结论,另一位则可能反对他们的结论。无论是否经过同行评议,这些冒犯性的内容都不应该发表。有人怀疑我们编辑的动机,难道我们是《女仆的故事》式社会的秘密支持者?当然,还有人质疑期刊的质量和审稿程序。我们怎么能发表这些明显有缺陷的论文呢?我们的工作原则似乎就是向期刊、期刊编辑和审稿人泼脏水,希望能有所收获。奇怪的是,对于这些学术社交媒体激进分子认为可以接受的内容,这些担忧似乎从未出现过。这些论文引起了相当大的反响,因为作者们在期刊上对这些内容做出了批判性的回应。发表这些论点和回应以严谨的学术方式检验了这些观点。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Protecting controversial thought: Editing Bioethics in the age of social media facilitated outrage

Much has been said about the harmful role played by algorithms that are deployed by social media platforms to ensure engagement. Less has arguably been said about the impact this had on editorial practices of academic journals that publish content that is vulnerable to the machinations of said algorithms. We have seen a few of these events over the years in our field, bioethics. Interested readers of the journal will recall the global outcry a paper by Alberto Giubilini and Francesca Minerva. It was caused by what they called provocatively ‘after-birth abortion’.1 In academic terms, the paper has been a runaway success, netting our colleagues over at the Journal of medical ethics a bit more than a million article downloads. Career development wise there were negative consequences suffered by both authors. Given that the Editor of the journal was under tremendous pressure to resign or be fired, I did publish a supportive Editorial in this journal at the time.2 Do you recall Rebecca Tuvel's article about transracialism in Hypathia some years back?3 The Editor of the journal, and the—at the time—junior, tenure-track academic, who published the paper, were subjected to endless ad hominem attacks on various social media platforms. Particularly disturbing was the participation of senior tenured academics in what constituted a concerted effort of the academic outrage machine to effectively end the academic career of a junior female philosopher without job security. Much of this pressure, as in the other examples I'm about to mention, was facilitated by social media platforms. Academics seemingly take to signing petitions aimed at boycotting, demanding resignations, retractions, and worse, in case they find published peer reviewed content disagreeable. Virtue signalling at its finest. Perhaps a response in the pages of the journal that published the offending paper is seen as too old fashioned by this sort of academic activism.

I have always thought that these types of reactions display a deeply troubling understanding of academic freedom. They are celebrating and defending the academic freedom of agreeable content, while failing to defend academic freedom when it matters most, namely when the content is disagreeable. There will be all sorts of verbiage thrown around from ‘epistemic injustice’ to varieties of ‘privilege’, but typically, the apparently so obviously flawed substance of what one disagrees with isn't confronted. However, precisely that is what ought to happen if one cared enough to ensure that diversity of thought is maintained in a field of inquiry such as bioethics. That doesn't mean that one has to concede a methodological free-for-all. I have gone on the record stating that public reason-based arguments are a conditio sine qua non of bioethical analyses that aim to have a universal appeal. Somewhat reassuringly the outrage machine tends to direct its vitriol at particular conclusions rather than the bioethical method. In the case of Tuvel, for instance, vague claims were made that she (and apparently the journal's referees) showed a lack of understanding of ‘the literature’. Suffice it to say that this was never substantiated. It really was about the disagreeable conclusions Tuvel arrived at.

In this journal, we have published during the last few years a fair number of papers by a small group of—arguably—activist antichoice academic writers. The conclusion of their papers was, invariably, abortion is bad, or some such. Prochoice academic social media activists lambasted the journal for publishing such content, questioning the integrity of both us Editors of the journal as well as the competence of our reviewers. We gave quite a bit of space to these authors and their views, provided their content passed standard peer review. Our—unwritten—policy, when it comes to such content, is to try to secure at least two reviewers, one who is somewhat supportive of the conclusions reached by these authors and one who is likely opposed to their conclusions.

Still, the social media outrage machine would have none of it. Peer review or not, such offending content should not be published. Suspicions of us Editors' motives were raised, were we perhaps secret supporters of a Handmaid's Tale type society? Also, of course, questions about the quality of the journal and its review processes appeared. How could we publish such obviously flawed papers? The operating principle seemed to be to throw mud against the journal, its Editors and its reviewers and hope that something sticks. Those concerns strangely never seem to arise vis a vis content these same academic social media activists find agreeable. These papers generated a fair bit of traction in that authors responded critically to this content in the pages of the journal. Publishing these arguments and the responses tested these views in an academically rigorous way. Publishing these arguments also helps addressing common claims of liberal bias that are routinely leveled by conservatives against the field of bioethics.

Similar issues surrounded a provocative Guest Editorial by Joona Räsänen.4 He discusses the health implications of sexual loneliness and quotes at one point a controversial conservative psychologist who reportedly favours societally enforced monogamy. The Guest Editorial was seen by the internet outrage machine as condoning incels' sexual abuse of women, among other crimes. I encourage you to read it for yourself. I can't find much else than a call on bioethicists to undertake critical ethical analyses of the arguments the opposing camps present.

Currently the journal features a Call for Papers for a special issue analysing the bioethical and medical ethics issues implications of the human tragedy unfolding in Gaza. I wrote to the brave Guest Editors, who stepped forward with a special issue proposal, that they should expect no thanks and plenty of vitriol, guaranteed by social media algorithms and the actors that feed them. They chose, among possible topics for potential contributors to consider, ‘The ethics of treating terrorists, and specifically the right of healthcare providers to refuse providing care to terrorists.’ Well, to cut a long story short, labelling an unnamed side in this conflict ‘terrorist’ offended a fair number of academic social media activists who proceeded to declaring that they would cease reviewing henceforth for the journal or contributing to it. Virtue signalling at its finest. I hope I'm not divulging too much when I note that those who protested loudest never contributed to the journal, either as reviewers or as authors.

What puzzles me about this behaviour is that it is antithetical to what academic freedom is all about. An appropriate response, as in the other examples I mentioned, would have been to submit a paper to said guest editors that takes their framing of the issue to task.

Let me end this Editorial by stating that we, as Editors of Bioethics, remain committed to protecting the journal as a space where diverse views will be published, including views some readers will consider offensive. The reader would be well advised not to draw conclusions from what content we publish on the views we as Editors of the journal hold on those issues. The journal has never been and will never become a mouthpiece for our own views.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
Accounts of Chemical Research
Accounts of Chemical Research 化学-化学综合
CiteScore
31.40
自引率
1.10%
发文量
312
审稿时长
2 months
期刊介绍: Accounts of Chemical Research presents short, concise and critical articles offering easy-to-read overviews of basic research and applications in all areas of chemistry and biochemistry. These short reviews focus on research from the author’s own laboratory and are designed to teach the reader about a research project. In addition, Accounts of Chemical Research publishes commentaries that give an informed opinion on a current research problem. Special Issues online are devoted to a single topic of unusual activity and significance. Accounts of Chemical Research replaces the traditional article abstract with an article "Conspectus." These entries synopsize the research affording the reader a closer look at the content and significance of an article. Through this provision of a more detailed description of the article contents, the Conspectus enhances the article's discoverability by search engines and the exposure for the research.
期刊最新文献
Management of Cholesteatoma: Hearing Rehabilitation. Congenital Cholesteatoma. Evaluation of Cholesteatoma. Management of Cholesteatoma: Extension Beyond Middle Ear/Mastoid. Recidivism and Recurrence.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1