终身监禁不得假释:比死亡还可怕?柯德史密斯,克莱斯图伯,雷吉,乔亚宾顿:劳特利奇出版社,2022。256页。£120.00 (hbk);34.99英镑(pbk) ISBN: 9780367572712;9780367752699

Q2 Social Sciences Howard Journal of Crime and Justice Pub Date : 2022-12-12 DOI:10.1111/hojo.12501
Hannah Gilman
{"title":"终身监禁不得假释:比死亡还可怕?柯德史密斯,克莱斯图伯,雷吉,乔亚宾顿:劳特利奇出版社,2022。256页。£120.00 (hbk);34.99英镑(pbk) ISBN: 9780367572712;9780367752699","authors":"Hannah Gilman","doi":"10.1111/hojo.12501","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>Internationally, whole life sentences are becoming an increasingly common sanction. They are supported by abolitionists of state executions and ‘tough on crime’ conservatives alike and, as a result, have flourished in recent years. The US has the highest number of persons serving whole life sentences anywhere in the world with an unprecedented 55,945 persons serving life without parole sentences in 2020 (p.94). Kleinstuber et al.’s <i>Life without parole: worse than death</i>? considers the purpose, development and impact of life without parole sentences in the US by focusing upon the increased use of life without parole sentences across the previous three decades. The authors examine the US's increasing dependency upon these sentences by considering arguments in support of their continued use and, in so doing, shine a light on the inhumane ‘pains’ suffered by those serving such sentences.</p><p>The book starts by considering the legitimacy of life without parole sentences, questioning whether life without parole sentences are humane and subsequently ‘just’ by considering the experiences of death row prisoners who – by most people's standards – are serving a significantly ‘worse’ sentence. The authors focus on ‘death penalty volunteers’ (p.21) (death row prisoners who purposely refuse to pursue any form of appeal so as to accelerate the execution process) in order to demonstrate the inhumane nature of life without parole sentences. The authors subsequently argue that the increasing number of ‘death penalty volunteers’ calls into question the notion that ‘life’ (without parole) is ‘better’ than death.</p><p>The second chapter continues to question the legitimacy of life without parole sentences by considering the experiences of life without parole prisoners. This chapter consolidates and builds upon existing literature on the pains of imprisonment (such as Sykes, <span>1958</span>) and life without parole (e.g., Hartman, <span>2016</span>; Johnson &amp; McGunigall-Smith, <span>2008</span>; Leigey, 2015; Zehr, <span>1996</span>) further emphasising the cruel and ‘inhuman’ (p.61) nature of life without parole sentences.</p><p>In the third chapter, the authors draw upon Van Zyl Smit and Appleton's (<span>2019</span>) <i>Life imprisonment: a global human rights analysis</i> to expose the ‘degrading’ (p.61) nature of life and whole life sentences and argue – in the words of Judge Power-Forde (see <i>Vinter and Others</i> v. <i>The UK</i> [2013] ECHR 645) – that prisoners ‘ought not to be deprived entirely of … hope’ (p.54).</p><p>These early chapters collectively present a persuasive argument against the increasing use of life without parole sentences. Nevertheless, many of these arguments have been made by various scholars within recent decades but – due to their predominantly theoretical nature – have failed to have any significant consequence; life without parole has continued to increase in popularity among legislators, judiciaries and society, resulting in a record number of life without parole prisoners in the US.</p><p>The fourth chapter subsequently recognises and discusses the limited judicial scrutiny that life without parole (in contrast to the death penalty) has received, despite it being considered the ‘worse’ of the two sentences by death row prisoners and life without parole prisoners alike, thereby contributing to abolitionist perspectives on the issue.</p><p>This argument is strengthened by the fifth chapter which considers the financial burden of life without parole sentences. It is traditionally argued that state executions are more costly, primarily as a consequence of the lengthy appeals process that must be fulfilled before a person can be executed; indeed, this argument (that it is cheaper to incarcerate a person for the remainder of their natural life) is often used in support of the abolition of state executions. Kleinstuber et al., however, argue that the cost ratio of state executions to life without parole sentences is outweighed by the greater use of life without parole sentences, determining that the total cost of life without parole sentences is greater than the total cost of state executions. While the author's conclusion inarguably supports their abolitionist perspective, it also risks encouraging state executions as the more cost-effective sanction.</p><p>The authors’ final argument in this section focuses on life without parole as a form of a racial control. Kleinstuber et al. argue that life without parole targets the disadvantaged (which in the US overlaps with the racially minoritised) due to the existence of ‘Three Strikes’ laws. The sixth chapter concludes with a brief discussion of the slightly newer notion of juvenile life without parole sentences, drawing upon data which show that 62% of juvenile life without parole prisoners are African American (p.127) further supporting their argument that life without parole sentences constitute a form of racialised control.</p><p>In Part Two, Kleinstuber et al. move on to consider the ‘tough on crime’ case for life without parole sentences. The seventh chapter considers whether life without parole has any crime-reducing consequences. The authors argue (having conducted a comprehensive statistical analysis) that life without parole sentences do not reduce the frequency of violent crime, nor do they produce measurably lower crime rates; indeed, the only statistically significant data suggest that the increasing use of life without parole sentences may actually increase crime (p.171).</p><p>The eighth chapter considers the utilitarian arguments in support of life without parole sentences, arguments which are frequently made in support of such sanctions. Kleinstuber et al., however, argue that life without parole sentences are imposed too frequently, for too many offences, and against offenders whose crimes do not warrant such a severe penalty. The authors subsequently argue that, if life without parole sentences are to meet the requirements of retribution, they must be reserved solely for offences which are considered to be incredibly severe, namely for offenders who would have received the death penalty.</p><p>The ninth chapter, which examines the ‘power of second chances’ (p.196), is, for me, the most poignant in the book. By considering the experiences of six former life without parole prisoners who have since been successfully released from prison, the chapter empirically challenges the idea that life without parole sentences are reserved solely for those whom society deems to be irredeemable. The case studies contained within this chapter demonstrate that life without parole prisoners can mature and make positive contributions to their communities, showing that it is impossible to predict at the time of sentencing what a person can go on to become. Kleinstuber et al. subsequently suggest that life without parole prisoners should be offered some form of review of their sentence in the years that follow and, eventually, parole.</p><p>As a PhD student studying whole life orders and whole life imprisonment within England and Wales, I can see that many of the earlier arguments made in the book have been made elsewhere, although the inclusion of the cost breakdown data and statistical analysis in Chapters 5 and 7 represent a true contribution to knowledge. The ninth chapter, however, adds real weight to the abolitionist argument. It is in this chapter that the continued and persistent belief that whole life sentence prisoners are beyond redemption (which drives our increasing use of such sentences) is forcefully refuted. I hope to see this aspect of the authors’ work explored further in future research.</p><p><i>Life without parole: worse than death?</i> is a must-read for fellow death penalty and whole life sentence abolitionists, as well as those concerned with the human rights of incarcerated persons. Nevertheless, I believe that this book would be a thought-provoking read for anyone with an interest in criminology, sociology and/or psychology as a whole and I would recommend <i>Life without parole: worse than death?</i> to students and scholars alike.</p>","PeriodicalId":37514,"journal":{"name":"Howard Journal of Crime and Justice","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2022-12-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/hojo.12501","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Life without parole: worse than death? , R. Kleinstuber, J. Coldsmith, M. Leigey & S. JoyAbingdon: Routledge. 2022. 256pp. £120.00 (hbk); £34.99 (pbk) ISBN: 9780367752712; 9780367752699\",\"authors\":\"Hannah Gilman\",\"doi\":\"10.1111/hojo.12501\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"<p>Internationally, whole life sentences are becoming an increasingly common sanction. They are supported by abolitionists of state executions and ‘tough on crime’ conservatives alike and, as a result, have flourished in recent years. The US has the highest number of persons serving whole life sentences anywhere in the world with an unprecedented 55,945 persons serving life without parole sentences in 2020 (p.94). Kleinstuber et al.’s <i>Life without parole: worse than death</i>? considers the purpose, development and impact of life without parole sentences in the US by focusing upon the increased use of life without parole sentences across the previous three decades. The authors examine the US's increasing dependency upon these sentences by considering arguments in support of their continued use and, in so doing, shine a light on the inhumane ‘pains’ suffered by those serving such sentences.</p><p>The book starts by considering the legitimacy of life without parole sentences, questioning whether life without parole sentences are humane and subsequently ‘just’ by considering the experiences of death row prisoners who – by most people's standards – are serving a significantly ‘worse’ sentence. The authors focus on ‘death penalty volunteers’ (p.21) (death row prisoners who purposely refuse to pursue any form of appeal so as to accelerate the execution process) in order to demonstrate the inhumane nature of life without parole sentences. The authors subsequently argue that the increasing number of ‘death penalty volunteers’ calls into question the notion that ‘life’ (without parole) is ‘better’ than death.</p><p>The second chapter continues to question the legitimacy of life without parole sentences by considering the experiences of life without parole prisoners. This chapter consolidates and builds upon existing literature on the pains of imprisonment (such as Sykes, <span>1958</span>) and life without parole (e.g., Hartman, <span>2016</span>; Johnson &amp; McGunigall-Smith, <span>2008</span>; Leigey, 2015; Zehr, <span>1996</span>) further emphasising the cruel and ‘inhuman’ (p.61) nature of life without parole sentences.</p><p>In the third chapter, the authors draw upon Van Zyl Smit and Appleton's (<span>2019</span>) <i>Life imprisonment: a global human rights analysis</i> to expose the ‘degrading’ (p.61) nature of life and whole life sentences and argue – in the words of Judge Power-Forde (see <i>Vinter and Others</i> v. <i>The UK</i> [2013] ECHR 645) – that prisoners ‘ought not to be deprived entirely of … hope’ (p.54).</p><p>These early chapters collectively present a persuasive argument against the increasing use of life without parole sentences. Nevertheless, many of these arguments have been made by various scholars within recent decades but – due to their predominantly theoretical nature – have failed to have any significant consequence; life without parole has continued to increase in popularity among legislators, judiciaries and society, resulting in a record number of life without parole prisoners in the US.</p><p>The fourth chapter subsequently recognises and discusses the limited judicial scrutiny that life without parole (in contrast to the death penalty) has received, despite it being considered the ‘worse’ of the two sentences by death row prisoners and life without parole prisoners alike, thereby contributing to abolitionist perspectives on the issue.</p><p>This argument is strengthened by the fifth chapter which considers the financial burden of life without parole sentences. It is traditionally argued that state executions are more costly, primarily as a consequence of the lengthy appeals process that must be fulfilled before a person can be executed; indeed, this argument (that it is cheaper to incarcerate a person for the remainder of their natural life) is often used in support of the abolition of state executions. Kleinstuber et al., however, argue that the cost ratio of state executions to life without parole sentences is outweighed by the greater use of life without parole sentences, determining that the total cost of life without parole sentences is greater than the total cost of state executions. While the author's conclusion inarguably supports their abolitionist perspective, it also risks encouraging state executions as the more cost-effective sanction.</p><p>The authors’ final argument in this section focuses on life without parole as a form of a racial control. Kleinstuber et al. argue that life without parole targets the disadvantaged (which in the US overlaps with the racially minoritised) due to the existence of ‘Three Strikes’ laws. The sixth chapter concludes with a brief discussion of the slightly newer notion of juvenile life without parole sentences, drawing upon data which show that 62% of juvenile life without parole prisoners are African American (p.127) further supporting their argument that life without parole sentences constitute a form of racialised control.</p><p>In Part Two, Kleinstuber et al. move on to consider the ‘tough on crime’ case for life without parole sentences. The seventh chapter considers whether life without parole has any crime-reducing consequences. The authors argue (having conducted a comprehensive statistical analysis) that life without parole sentences do not reduce the frequency of violent crime, nor do they produce measurably lower crime rates; indeed, the only statistically significant data suggest that the increasing use of life without parole sentences may actually increase crime (p.171).</p><p>The eighth chapter considers the utilitarian arguments in support of life without parole sentences, arguments which are frequently made in support of such sanctions. Kleinstuber et al., however, argue that life without parole sentences are imposed too frequently, for too many offences, and against offenders whose crimes do not warrant such a severe penalty. The authors subsequently argue that, if life without parole sentences are to meet the requirements of retribution, they must be reserved solely for offences which are considered to be incredibly severe, namely for offenders who would have received the death penalty.</p><p>The ninth chapter, which examines the ‘power of second chances’ (p.196), is, for me, the most poignant in the book. By considering the experiences of six former life without parole prisoners who have since been successfully released from prison, the chapter empirically challenges the idea that life without parole sentences are reserved solely for those whom society deems to be irredeemable. The case studies contained within this chapter demonstrate that life without parole prisoners can mature and make positive contributions to their communities, showing that it is impossible to predict at the time of sentencing what a person can go on to become. Kleinstuber et al. subsequently suggest that life without parole prisoners should be offered some form of review of their sentence in the years that follow and, eventually, parole.</p><p>As a PhD student studying whole life orders and whole life imprisonment within England and Wales, I can see that many of the earlier arguments made in the book have been made elsewhere, although the inclusion of the cost breakdown data and statistical analysis in Chapters 5 and 7 represent a true contribution to knowledge. The ninth chapter, however, adds real weight to the abolitionist argument. It is in this chapter that the continued and persistent belief that whole life sentence prisoners are beyond redemption (which drives our increasing use of such sentences) is forcefully refuted. I hope to see this aspect of the authors’ work explored further in future research.</p><p><i>Life without parole: worse than death?</i> is a must-read for fellow death penalty and whole life sentence abolitionists, as well as those concerned with the human rights of incarcerated persons. Nevertheless, I believe that this book would be a thought-provoking read for anyone with an interest in criminology, sociology and/or psychology as a whole and I would recommend <i>Life without parole: worse than death?</i> to students and scholars alike.</p>\",\"PeriodicalId\":37514,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Howard Journal of Crime and Justice\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2022-12-12\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/hojo.12501\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Howard Journal of Crime and Justice\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/hojo.12501\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q2\",\"JCRName\":\"Social Sciences\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Howard Journal of Crime and Justice","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/hojo.12501","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q2","JCRName":"Social Sciences","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

在国际上,终身监禁正成为越来越普遍的制裁。他们得到了国家死刑废除主义者和“严厉打击犯罪”的保守派的支持,因此近年来蓬勃发展。美国是世界上被判终身监禁人数最多的国家,2020年被判终身监禁不得假释的人数达到前所未有的55,945人(p.94)。Kleinstuber等人的《不得假释的终身监禁:比死亡还糟糕?》通过关注在过去三十年中不断增加的无假释终身监禁判决的使用,考虑了美国无假释终身监禁判决的目的、发展和影响。作者通过考虑支持这些刑罚继续使用的论据,研究了美国对这些刑罚的日益依赖,并在这样做的过程中,照亮了那些服刑者所遭受的不人道的“痛苦”。这本书首先考虑了终身监禁不得假释判决的合法性,质疑终身监禁不得假释判决是否人道,然后考虑了死囚的经历——按照大多数人的标准——他们的刑期明显“更糟”。提交人把重点放在"死刑志愿人员"(第21页)(故意拒绝进行任何形式的上诉以加速执行程序的死囚)上,以证明无假释终身监禁判决的非人道性质。作者随后认为,“死刑志愿者”数量的不断增加,对“终身监禁”(不得假释)比死亡“好”的观念提出了质疑。第二章通过对无假释囚犯经历的分析,继续质疑无假释终身监禁判决的合法性。本章巩固并建立在现有的关于监禁之痛(如Sykes, 1958)和无假释终身监禁(如Hartman, 2016;约翰逊,McGunigall-Smith, 2008;Leigey, 2015;Zehr, 1996)进一步强调了无假释终身监禁判决的残酷和“不人道”的性质(第61页)。在第三章中,作者借鉴了Van Zyl Smit和Appleton(2019)的《终身监禁:全球人权分析》(Life prison: a global human rights analysis),以揭露终身监禁和终身监禁的“有辱人格”(第61页)的性质,并用Power-Forde法官的话(见Vinter等人诉英国[2013]ECHR 645)来论证囚犯“不应该完全被剥夺……希望”(第54页)。这些早期章节共同提出了一个有说服力的论点,反对越来越多地使用无假释终身监禁。然而,近几十年来,许多学者提出了许多这样的论点,但由于它们主要是理论性的,没有产生任何重大的后果;无假释终身监禁在立法者、司法机构和社会上的受欢迎程度持续上升,导致美国无假释终身监禁人数创历史新高。随后,第四章承认并讨论了无假释终身监禁(与死刑相比)受到的有限司法审查,尽管死囚和无假释终身监禁被认为是两种刑罚中"较差"的一种,从而有助于对该问题的废除观点。第五章审议了不得假释终身监禁的经济负担,加强了这一论点。传统上认为,国家执行死刑的成本更高,主要是因为一个人在被处决之前必须完成漫长的上诉程序;事实上,这一论点(将一个人监禁到其自然生命的剩余时间更便宜)经常被用来支持废除国家死刑。然而,Kleinstuber等人认为,国家执行死刑与终身监禁判决的成本之比被更多地使用终身监禁判决所抵消,从而确定终身监禁判决的总成本大于国家执行死刑的总成本。虽然作者的结论无可争议地支持了他们的废奴主义观点,但它也有鼓励国家执行死刑作为更具成本效益的制裁的风险。作者在本节最后的论点集中在无假释的生活作为一种形式的种族控制。Kleinstuber等人认为,由于“三振出局”法律的存在,无假释终身监禁针对的是弱势群体(在美国与少数族裔重叠)。第六章最后简要讨论了青少年终身监禁判决的新概念,根据数据显示62%的青少年终身监禁囚犯是非裔美国人(第127页),进一步支持了他们的论点,即终身监禁判决构成了一种种族化的控制形式。在第二部分中,Kleinstuber等人继续考虑终身无假释判决的“严厉打击犯罪”案例。 在国际上,终身监禁正成为越来越普遍的制裁。他们得到了国家死刑废除主义者和“严厉打击犯罪”的保守派的支持,因此近年来蓬勃发展。美国是世界上被判终身监禁人数最多的国家,2020年被判终身监禁不得假释的人数达到前所未有的55,945人(p.94)。Kleinstuber等人的《不得假释的终身监禁:比死亡还糟糕?》通过关注在过去三十年中不断增加的无假释终身监禁判决的使用,考虑了美国无假释终身监禁判决的目的、发展和影响。作者通过考虑支持这些刑罚继续使用的论据,研究了美国对这些刑罚的日益依赖,并在这样做的过程中,照亮了那些服刑者所遭受的不人道的“痛苦”。这本书首先考虑了终身监禁不得假释判决的合法性,质疑终身监禁不得假释判决是否人道,然后考虑了死囚的经历——按照大多数人的标准——他们的刑期明显“更糟”。提交人把重点放在"死刑志愿人员"(第21页)(故意拒绝进行任何形式的上诉以加速执行程序的死囚)上,以证明无假释终身监禁判决的非人道性质。作者随后认为,“死刑志愿者”数量的不断增加,对“终身监禁”(不得假释)比死亡“好”的观念提出了质疑。第二章通过对无假释囚犯经历的分析,继续质疑无假释终身监禁判决的合法性。本章巩固并建立在现有的关于监禁之痛(如Sykes, 1958)和无假释终身监禁(如Hartman, 2016;约翰逊,McGunigall-Smith, 2008;Leigey, 2015;Zehr, 1996)进一步强调了无假释终身监禁判决的残酷和“不人道”的性质(第61页)。在第三章中,作者借鉴了Van Zyl Smit和Appleton(2019)的《终身监禁:全球人权分析》(Life prison: a global human rights analysis),以揭露终身监禁和终身监禁的“有辱人格”(第61页)的性质,并用Power-Forde法官的话(见Vinter等人诉英国[2013]ECHR 645)来论证囚犯“不应该完全被剥夺……希望”(第54页)。这些早期章节共同提出了一个有说服力的论点,反对越来越多地使用无假释终身监禁。然而,近几十年来,许多学者提出了许多这样的论点,但由于它们主要是理论性的,没有产生任何重大的后果;无假释终身监禁在立法者、司法机构和社会上的受欢迎程度持续上升,导致美国无假释终身监禁人数创历史新高。随后,第四章承认并讨论了无假释终身监禁(与死刑相比)受到的有限司法审查,尽管死囚和无假释终身监禁被认为是两种刑罚中"较差"的一种,从而有助于对该问题的废除观点。第五章审议了不得假释终身监禁的经济负担,加强了这一论点。传统上认为,国家执行死刑的成本更高,主要是因为一个人在被处决之前必须完成漫长的上诉程序;事实上,这一论点(将一个人监禁到其自然生命的剩余时间更便宜)经常被用来支持废除国家死刑。然而,Kleinstuber等人认为,国家执行死刑与终身监禁判决的成本之比被更多地使用终身监禁判决所抵消,从而确定终身监禁判决的总成本大于国家执行死刑的总成本。虽然作者的结论无可争议地支持了他们的废奴主义观点,但它也有鼓励国家执行死刑作为更具成本效益的制裁的风险。作者在本节最后的论点集中在无假释的生活作为一种形式的种族控制。Kleinstuber等人认为,由于“三振出局”法律的存在,无假释终身监禁针对的是弱势群体(在美国与少数族裔重叠)。第六章最后简要讨论了青少年终身监禁判决的新概念,根据数据显示62%的青少年终身监禁囚犯是非裔美国人(第127页),进一步支持了他们的论点,即终身监禁判决构成了一种种族化的控制形式。在第二部分中,Kleinstuber等人继续考虑终身无假释判决的“严厉打击犯罪”案例。 第七章论述无假释终身监禁是否具有减少犯罪的效果。作者认为(在进行了全面的统计分析后),无期徒刑不能减少暴力犯罪的频率,也不能显著降低犯罪率;事实上,唯一有统计意义的数据表明,越来越多地使用无假释终身监禁实际上可能增加犯罪(第171页)。第八章考虑了支持无假释终身监禁的功利主义论点,这些论点经常被用来支持这种制裁。然而,Kleinstuber等人认为,对于太多的罪行,以及对那些罪行不应受到如此严厉惩罚的罪犯,判处无假释终身监禁的刑罚过于频繁。提交人随后争辩说,如果要使无假释终身监禁符合报复的要求,就必须只适用于被认为极其严重的罪行,即适用于本应被判处死刑的罪犯。第九章探讨了“第二次机会的力量”(第196页),对我来说,这是本书中最深刻的部分。通过考虑六名前无假释囚犯的经历,他们后来成功地从监狱获释,本章从经验上挑战了“无假释终身监禁判决只适用于那些社会认为无可救药的人”的观点。本章所载的案例研究表明,无假释终身监禁的囚犯可以成熟起来,并为他们的社区做出积极贡献,这表明在宣判时不可能预测一个人将来会成为什么。Kleinstuber等人随后建议,终身监禁不得假释的囚犯应该在接下来的几年里获得某种形式的复审,并最终获得假释。作为一名在英格兰和威尔士研究终身监禁和终身监禁的博士生,我可以看到书中早期提出的许多论点已经在其他地方提出过,尽管在第5章和第7章中包含了成本分解数据和统计分析,这是对知识的真正贡献。然而,第九章为废奴主义者的论点增添了真正的分量。正是在这一章中,人们一直坚持认为终身监禁的囚犯是无法救赎的(这促使我们越来越多地使用这种判决),这一观点被有力地驳斥了。我希望在未来的研究中看到作者工作的这一方面得到进一步的探索。没有假释的终身监禁:比死亡还糟糕?是同为死刑和终身监禁废除主义者以及关心被监禁者人权的人的必读书籍。尽管如此,我相信这本书对于任何对犯罪学,社会学和/或心理学感兴趣的人来说都是一本发人深省的书,我要推荐终身监禁:比死亡更糟糕?对学生和学者都一样。 第七章论述无假释终身监禁是否具有减少犯罪的效果。作者认为(在进行了全面的统计分析后),无期徒刑不能减少暴力犯罪的频率,也不能显著降低犯罪率;事实上,唯一有统计意义的数据表明,越来越多地使用无假释终身监禁实际上可能增加犯罪(第171页)。第八章考虑了支持无假释终身监禁的功利主义论点,这些论点经常被用来支持这种制裁。然而,Kleinstuber等人认为,对于太多的罪行,以及对那些罪行不应受到如此严厉惩罚的罪犯,判处无假释终身监禁的刑罚过于频繁。提交人随后争辩说,如果要使无假释终身监禁符合报复的要求,就必须只适用于被认为极其严重的罪行,即适用于本应被判处死刑的罪犯。第九章探讨了“第二次机会的力量”(第196页),对我来说,这是本书中最深刻的部分。通过考虑六名前无假释囚犯的经历,他们后来成功地从监狱获释,本章从经验上挑战了“无假释终身监禁判决只适用于那些社会认为无可救药的人”的观点。本章所载的案例研究表明,无假释终身监禁的囚犯可以成熟起来,并为他们的社区做出积极贡献,这表明在宣判时不可能预测一个人将来会成为什么。Kleinstuber等人随后建议,终身监禁不得假释的囚犯应该在接下来的几年里获得某种形式的复审,并最终获得假释。作为一名在英格兰和威尔士研究终身监禁和终身监禁的博士生,我可以看到书中早期提出的许多论点已经在其他地方提出过,尽管在第5章和第7章中包含了成本分解数据和统计分析,这是对知识的真正贡献。然而,第九章为废奴主义者的论点增添了真正的分量。正是在这一章中,人们一直坚持认为终身监禁的囚犯是无法救赎的(这促使我们越来越多地使用这种判决),这一观点被有力地驳斥了。我希望在未来的研究中看到作者工作的这一方面得到进一步的探索。没有假释的终身监禁:比死亡还糟糕?是同为死刑和终身监禁废除主义者以及关心被监禁者人权的人的必读书籍。尽管如此,我相信这本书对于任何对犯罪学,社会学和/或心理学感兴趣的人来说都是一本发人深省的书,我要推荐终身监禁:比死亡更糟糕?对学生和学者都一样。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Life without parole: worse than death? , R. Kleinstuber, J. Coldsmith, M. Leigey & S. JoyAbingdon: Routledge. 2022. 256pp. £120.00 (hbk); £34.99 (pbk) ISBN: 9780367752712; 9780367752699

Internationally, whole life sentences are becoming an increasingly common sanction. They are supported by abolitionists of state executions and ‘tough on crime’ conservatives alike and, as a result, have flourished in recent years. The US has the highest number of persons serving whole life sentences anywhere in the world with an unprecedented 55,945 persons serving life without parole sentences in 2020 (p.94). Kleinstuber et al.’s Life without parole: worse than death? considers the purpose, development and impact of life without parole sentences in the US by focusing upon the increased use of life without parole sentences across the previous three decades. The authors examine the US's increasing dependency upon these sentences by considering arguments in support of their continued use and, in so doing, shine a light on the inhumane ‘pains’ suffered by those serving such sentences.

The book starts by considering the legitimacy of life without parole sentences, questioning whether life without parole sentences are humane and subsequently ‘just’ by considering the experiences of death row prisoners who – by most people's standards – are serving a significantly ‘worse’ sentence. The authors focus on ‘death penalty volunteers’ (p.21) (death row prisoners who purposely refuse to pursue any form of appeal so as to accelerate the execution process) in order to demonstrate the inhumane nature of life without parole sentences. The authors subsequently argue that the increasing number of ‘death penalty volunteers’ calls into question the notion that ‘life’ (without parole) is ‘better’ than death.

The second chapter continues to question the legitimacy of life without parole sentences by considering the experiences of life without parole prisoners. This chapter consolidates and builds upon existing literature on the pains of imprisonment (such as Sykes, 1958) and life without parole (e.g., Hartman, 2016; Johnson & McGunigall-Smith, 2008; Leigey, 2015; Zehr, 1996) further emphasising the cruel and ‘inhuman’ (p.61) nature of life without parole sentences.

In the third chapter, the authors draw upon Van Zyl Smit and Appleton's (2019) Life imprisonment: a global human rights analysis to expose the ‘degrading’ (p.61) nature of life and whole life sentences and argue – in the words of Judge Power-Forde (see Vinter and Others v. The UK [2013] ECHR 645) – that prisoners ‘ought not to be deprived entirely of … hope’ (p.54).

These early chapters collectively present a persuasive argument against the increasing use of life without parole sentences. Nevertheless, many of these arguments have been made by various scholars within recent decades but – due to their predominantly theoretical nature – have failed to have any significant consequence; life without parole has continued to increase in popularity among legislators, judiciaries and society, resulting in a record number of life without parole prisoners in the US.

The fourth chapter subsequently recognises and discusses the limited judicial scrutiny that life without parole (in contrast to the death penalty) has received, despite it being considered the ‘worse’ of the two sentences by death row prisoners and life without parole prisoners alike, thereby contributing to abolitionist perspectives on the issue.

This argument is strengthened by the fifth chapter which considers the financial burden of life without parole sentences. It is traditionally argued that state executions are more costly, primarily as a consequence of the lengthy appeals process that must be fulfilled before a person can be executed; indeed, this argument (that it is cheaper to incarcerate a person for the remainder of their natural life) is often used in support of the abolition of state executions. Kleinstuber et al., however, argue that the cost ratio of state executions to life without parole sentences is outweighed by the greater use of life without parole sentences, determining that the total cost of life without parole sentences is greater than the total cost of state executions. While the author's conclusion inarguably supports their abolitionist perspective, it also risks encouraging state executions as the more cost-effective sanction.

The authors’ final argument in this section focuses on life without parole as a form of a racial control. Kleinstuber et al. argue that life without parole targets the disadvantaged (which in the US overlaps with the racially minoritised) due to the existence of ‘Three Strikes’ laws. The sixth chapter concludes with a brief discussion of the slightly newer notion of juvenile life without parole sentences, drawing upon data which show that 62% of juvenile life without parole prisoners are African American (p.127) further supporting their argument that life without parole sentences constitute a form of racialised control.

In Part Two, Kleinstuber et al. move on to consider the ‘tough on crime’ case for life without parole sentences. The seventh chapter considers whether life without parole has any crime-reducing consequences. The authors argue (having conducted a comprehensive statistical analysis) that life without parole sentences do not reduce the frequency of violent crime, nor do they produce measurably lower crime rates; indeed, the only statistically significant data suggest that the increasing use of life without parole sentences may actually increase crime (p.171).

The eighth chapter considers the utilitarian arguments in support of life without parole sentences, arguments which are frequently made in support of such sanctions. Kleinstuber et al., however, argue that life without parole sentences are imposed too frequently, for too many offences, and against offenders whose crimes do not warrant such a severe penalty. The authors subsequently argue that, if life without parole sentences are to meet the requirements of retribution, they must be reserved solely for offences which are considered to be incredibly severe, namely for offenders who would have received the death penalty.

The ninth chapter, which examines the ‘power of second chances’ (p.196), is, for me, the most poignant in the book. By considering the experiences of six former life without parole prisoners who have since been successfully released from prison, the chapter empirically challenges the idea that life without parole sentences are reserved solely for those whom society deems to be irredeemable. The case studies contained within this chapter demonstrate that life without parole prisoners can mature and make positive contributions to their communities, showing that it is impossible to predict at the time of sentencing what a person can go on to become. Kleinstuber et al. subsequently suggest that life without parole prisoners should be offered some form of review of their sentence in the years that follow and, eventually, parole.

As a PhD student studying whole life orders and whole life imprisonment within England and Wales, I can see that many of the earlier arguments made in the book have been made elsewhere, although the inclusion of the cost breakdown data and statistical analysis in Chapters 5 and 7 represent a true contribution to knowledge. The ninth chapter, however, adds real weight to the abolitionist argument. It is in this chapter that the continued and persistent belief that whole life sentence prisoners are beyond redemption (which drives our increasing use of such sentences) is forcefully refuted. I hope to see this aspect of the authors’ work explored further in future research.

Life without parole: worse than death? is a must-read for fellow death penalty and whole life sentence abolitionists, as well as those concerned with the human rights of incarcerated persons. Nevertheless, I believe that this book would be a thought-provoking read for anyone with an interest in criminology, sociology and/or psychology as a whole and I would recommend Life without parole: worse than death? to students and scholars alike.

求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
2.30
自引率
0.00%
发文量
41
期刊介绍: The Howard Journal of Crime and Justice is an international peer-reviewed journal committed to publishing high quality theory, research and debate on all aspects of the relationship between crime and justice across the globe. It is a leading forum for conversation between academic theory and research and the cultures, policies and practices of the range of institutions concerned with harm, security and justice.
期刊最新文献
Issue Information Being watched: The aftermath of covert policing Observing justice: Digital transparency, openness and accountability in criminal courts By J. Townend, L. Welsh, Bristol: Bristol University Press. 2023. pp. 176. £45.00 (hbk). ISBN: 9781529228670 Children in conflict with the law: Rights, research and progressive youth justice By U. Kilkelly, L. Forde, S. Lambert, K. Swirak, London: Palgrave Macmillan. 2023. pp. 185. £34.99 (hbk). ISBN: 9783031366512; £27.99 (ebk). ISBN: 9783031366529 Trans and gender diverse offenders’ experiences of custody: A systematic review of empirical evidence
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1