{"title":"混乱中的快乐:内隐偏见的包容性定义和操作","authors":"J. Dovidio, J. Kunst","doi":"10.1080/1047840X.2022.2106756","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Gawronski, Ledgerwood, and Eastwick (this issue) address a timely issue of both theoretical and practical importance in the burgeoning study of implicit bias. The authors “highlight conceptual and empirical problems with the widespread equation of implicit bias and bias on implicit measures” (p. 139). They are not the first to raise and grapple with a question closely related to deciphering the conceptual meaning of implicit bias and its relationship to measures of implicit bias, but they distinguish themselves with their mastery of diverse literatures, sophisticated analyses of core theoretical issues, and original insights. While maintaining a steady focus on their core question, the authors’ review and synthesis of the work that they cover makes this a valuable resource for various audiences. It provides a detailed, yet accessible introduction for those who are interested in but relatively unfamiliar with the topic, as well as a thought-provoking and well-argued contribution for those who have considerable expertise in the area and may already have well-formed perspectives on the questions posed and answers provided. Importantly, in an area in which heated debate has been common, Gawronski et al. navigate through complex issues with logic and data in an even-handed way. This is an impressive piece of scholarship. A common colloquial expression is, “If the shoe fits, wear it.” The article is particularly impressive in the way the authors examine the many ways that scholars have attempted to define implicit bias. They try on many shoes for the term “implicit,” as compared to “explicit.” Gawronski et al. (this issue) consider distinctions in process, such as in differences between “mental levels.” For instance, they discuss how implicit has been treated as reflecting associative processes “involving unqualified mental links between concepts”, whereas explicit processes are propositional “involving the perceived validity of specific relations” (p. 141). Alternative, procedural distinctions are also reviewed. These tend to be instrument-focused. For example, a measure would qualify as implicit to the extent to which the response is automatic—that is, unintentional and difficult to control. By contrast, an explicit measure would be one in which people respond in a deliberative, intentional, and selfreflective way. Indeed, the first author of this commentary falls into this procedural camp, describing implicit as activation that occurs unintentionally (Dovidio, Kawakami, & Beach, 2001), automatically (Dovidio, Hewstone, Glick, & Esses, 2010), and which can operate without people being aware of the “biased associations or of the role those associations play in guiding their judgment and action” (Greenwald, Dsagupta, et al., 2022, p. 8). However, Gawronski et al. (this issue) skillfully argue how and why none of these shoes fit. In the end, we resonate with Gawronski et al.’s critical conclusion that “despite 25 years of extensive research, the current labeling conventions are still based on conceptually ambiguous lists according to which a measure qualifies as implicit if researchers have described it as implicit in the past” (p. 142; see also Gawronski, De Houwer, & Sherman, 2020). While we agree with Gawronski, Ledgerwood, and Eastwick’s analysis of current problems in the way implicit bias is conceived and studied, where we diverge is in the proposed solution. We deliberately use the word “diverge” rather than “disagree,” because the perspective that brings us here is quite different. Different perspectives carry different assumptions and dictate different priorities. Gawronski et al. (this issue) focus on implicit bias as a behavioral phenomenon that can be distinguished from the bias that is assessed by implicit measures. They write that “bias can be defined as the effect of social category cues (e.g., cues related to race, gender, etc.) on behavioral responses” and “to classify a person’s behavioral response toward a target as an instance of IB [implicit bias], one has to demonstrate that (1) the behavioral response is influenced by social category cues and (2) the person is unaware of the effect of the relevant social category cues on their behavioral response” (p. 5). As clear and as elegant in its directness that this set of definitions is, we are not convinced that this shoe fits, either. At first glance, Gawronski et al.’s (this issue) definition may seem quite similar to the definition recently used by Greenwald, Dsagupta, et al. (2022, p. 8) as a bias that","PeriodicalId":48327,"journal":{"name":"Psychological Inquiry","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":7.2000,"publicationDate":"2022-07-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"1","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Delight in Disorder: Inclusively Defining and Operationalizing Implicit Bias\",\"authors\":\"J. Dovidio, J. Kunst\",\"doi\":\"10.1080/1047840X.2022.2106756\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Gawronski, Ledgerwood, and Eastwick (this issue) address a timely issue of both theoretical and practical importance in the burgeoning study of implicit bias. The authors “highlight conceptual and empirical problems with the widespread equation of implicit bias and bias on implicit measures” (p. 139). They are not the first to raise and grapple with a question closely related to deciphering the conceptual meaning of implicit bias and its relationship to measures of implicit bias, but they distinguish themselves with their mastery of diverse literatures, sophisticated analyses of core theoretical issues, and original insights. While maintaining a steady focus on their core question, the authors’ review and synthesis of the work that they cover makes this a valuable resource for various audiences. It provides a detailed, yet accessible introduction for those who are interested in but relatively unfamiliar with the topic, as well as a thought-provoking and well-argued contribution for those who have considerable expertise in the area and may already have well-formed perspectives on the questions posed and answers provided. Importantly, in an area in which heated debate has been common, Gawronski et al. navigate through complex issues with logic and data in an even-handed way. This is an impressive piece of scholarship. A common colloquial expression is, “If the shoe fits, wear it.” The article is particularly impressive in the way the authors examine the many ways that scholars have attempted to define implicit bias. They try on many shoes for the term “implicit,” as compared to “explicit.” Gawronski et al. (this issue) consider distinctions in process, such as in differences between “mental levels.” For instance, they discuss how implicit has been treated as reflecting associative processes “involving unqualified mental links between concepts”, whereas explicit processes are propositional “involving the perceived validity of specific relations” (p. 141). Alternative, procedural distinctions are also reviewed. These tend to be instrument-focused. For example, a measure would qualify as implicit to the extent to which the response is automatic—that is, unintentional and difficult to control. By contrast, an explicit measure would be one in which people respond in a deliberative, intentional, and selfreflective way. Indeed, the first author of this commentary falls into this procedural camp, describing implicit as activation that occurs unintentionally (Dovidio, Kawakami, & Beach, 2001), automatically (Dovidio, Hewstone, Glick, & Esses, 2010), and which can operate without people being aware of the “biased associations or of the role those associations play in guiding their judgment and action” (Greenwald, Dsagupta, et al., 2022, p. 8). However, Gawronski et al. (this issue) skillfully argue how and why none of these shoes fit. In the end, we resonate with Gawronski et al.’s critical conclusion that “despite 25 years of extensive research, the current labeling conventions are still based on conceptually ambiguous lists according to which a measure qualifies as implicit if researchers have described it as implicit in the past” (p. 142; see also Gawronski, De Houwer, & Sherman, 2020). While we agree with Gawronski, Ledgerwood, and Eastwick’s analysis of current problems in the way implicit bias is conceived and studied, where we diverge is in the proposed solution. We deliberately use the word “diverge” rather than “disagree,” because the perspective that brings us here is quite different. Different perspectives carry different assumptions and dictate different priorities. Gawronski et al. (this issue) focus on implicit bias as a behavioral phenomenon that can be distinguished from the bias that is assessed by implicit measures. They write that “bias can be defined as the effect of social category cues (e.g., cues related to race, gender, etc.) on behavioral responses” and “to classify a person’s behavioral response toward a target as an instance of IB [implicit bias], one has to demonstrate that (1) the behavioral response is influenced by social category cues and (2) the person is unaware of the effect of the relevant social category cues on their behavioral response” (p. 5). As clear and as elegant in its directness that this set of definitions is, we are not convinced that this shoe fits, either. At first glance, Gawronski et al.’s (this issue) definition may seem quite similar to the definition recently used by Greenwald, Dsagupta, et al. (2022, p. 8) as a bias that\",\"PeriodicalId\":48327,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Psychological Inquiry\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":7.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"2022-07-03\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"1\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Psychological Inquiry\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"102\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1080/1047840X.2022.2106756\",\"RegionNum\":2,\"RegionCategory\":\"心理学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q1\",\"JCRName\":\"PSYCHOLOGY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Psychological Inquiry","FirstCategoryId":"102","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1047840X.2022.2106756","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"心理学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"PSYCHOLOGY, MULTIDISCIPLINARY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
摘要
Gawronski, Ledgerwood和Eastwick(本期)在新兴的内隐偏见研究中提出了一个具有理论和实践重要性的及时问题。作者“强调了关于内隐偏差和内隐测量偏差的广泛等式的概念和经验问题”(第139页)。他们并不是第一个提出并解决与解读内隐偏见的概念意义及其与内隐偏见测量的关系密切相关的问题的人,但他们以对各种文献的掌握、对核心理论问题的复杂分析和原创性见解而脱颖而出。在保持对其核心问题的稳定关注的同时,作者对他们所涵盖的工作的回顾和综合使其成为各种受众的宝贵资源。它为那些对该主题感兴趣但相对不熟悉的人提供了一个详细的,但易于理解的介绍,也为那些在该领域有相当专业知识并且可能已经对所提出的问题和所提供的答案有良好形成的观点的人提供了一个发人深省和充分论证的贡献。重要的是,在一个激烈争论已经司空见惯的领域,Gawronski等人以一种不偏不倚的方式用逻辑和数据来解决复杂的问题。这是一项令人印象深刻的学术研究。一个常见的口语表达是,“如果鞋子合脚,就穿它。”这篇文章特别令人印象深刻的是,作者对学者们试图定义隐性偏见的许多方式进行了研究。他们试了很多鞋子,是为了“隐性”,而不是“显性”。Gawronski等人(本期)考虑了过程中的差异,例如“心理水平”之间的差异。例如,他们讨论了内隐过程如何被视为反映“涉及概念之间不确定的心理联系”的联想过程,而外显过程是“涉及特定关系的感知有效性”的命题过程(第141页)。还审查了其他程序上的区别。这些倾向于以工具为中心。例如,一种测量方法被认为是隐含的,因为它的反应是自动的,也就是说,是无意的,难以控制的。相比之下,明确的衡量标准是人们以深思熟虑、有意识和自我反思的方式做出反应。事实上,这篇评论的第一作者属于程序性阵营,将隐性激活描述为无意识地(Dovidio, Kawakami, & Beach, 2001)、自动地(Dovidio, Hewstone, Glick, & ess, 2010)发生的激活,并且可以在人们没有意识到“有偏见的联想或这些联想在指导他们的判断和行动中所起的作用”的情况下运行(Greenwald, Dsagupta, et al., 2022, p. 8)。Gawronski等人(本期)巧妙地论证了这些鞋子不合脚的原因和原因。最后,我们与Gawronski等人的关键结论产生共鸣,即“尽管经过了25年的广泛研究,目前的标签惯例仍然基于概念模糊的列表,根据该列表,如果研究人员过去将其描述为隐含的,则该测量具有隐含的资格”(第142页;另见Gawronski, De Houwer, & Sherman, 2020)。虽然我们同意Gawronski, Ledgerwood和Eastwick对当前问题的分析,即内隐偏见的设想和研究方式,但我们的分歧在于提出的解决方案。我们故意使用“分歧”这个词,而不是“不同意”,因为把我们带到这里的观点是完全不同的。不同的观点有不同的假设,决定了不同的优先顺序。Gawronski等人(本期)将内隐偏见视为一种行为现象,可以与内隐测量评估的偏见区分开来。他们写道,“偏见可以定义为社会类别线索(例如,与种族、性别等有关的线索)对行为反应的影响”,“将一个人对目标的行为反应归类为IB[内隐偏见]的实例,一个人必须证明(1)行为反应受到社会类别线索的影响,(2)这个人没有意识到相关的社会类别线索对他们的行为反应的影响”(第5页)。尽管这组定义清晰而直接,但我们也不相信这是正确的。乍一看,Gawronski等人(本期)的定义似乎与Greenwald, Dsagupta等人(2022,p. 8)最近使用的定义非常相似,这是一种偏见
Delight in Disorder: Inclusively Defining and Operationalizing Implicit Bias
Gawronski, Ledgerwood, and Eastwick (this issue) address a timely issue of both theoretical and practical importance in the burgeoning study of implicit bias. The authors “highlight conceptual and empirical problems with the widespread equation of implicit bias and bias on implicit measures” (p. 139). They are not the first to raise and grapple with a question closely related to deciphering the conceptual meaning of implicit bias and its relationship to measures of implicit bias, but they distinguish themselves with their mastery of diverse literatures, sophisticated analyses of core theoretical issues, and original insights. While maintaining a steady focus on their core question, the authors’ review and synthesis of the work that they cover makes this a valuable resource for various audiences. It provides a detailed, yet accessible introduction for those who are interested in but relatively unfamiliar with the topic, as well as a thought-provoking and well-argued contribution for those who have considerable expertise in the area and may already have well-formed perspectives on the questions posed and answers provided. Importantly, in an area in which heated debate has been common, Gawronski et al. navigate through complex issues with logic and data in an even-handed way. This is an impressive piece of scholarship. A common colloquial expression is, “If the shoe fits, wear it.” The article is particularly impressive in the way the authors examine the many ways that scholars have attempted to define implicit bias. They try on many shoes for the term “implicit,” as compared to “explicit.” Gawronski et al. (this issue) consider distinctions in process, such as in differences between “mental levels.” For instance, they discuss how implicit has been treated as reflecting associative processes “involving unqualified mental links between concepts”, whereas explicit processes are propositional “involving the perceived validity of specific relations” (p. 141). Alternative, procedural distinctions are also reviewed. These tend to be instrument-focused. For example, a measure would qualify as implicit to the extent to which the response is automatic—that is, unintentional and difficult to control. By contrast, an explicit measure would be one in which people respond in a deliberative, intentional, and selfreflective way. Indeed, the first author of this commentary falls into this procedural camp, describing implicit as activation that occurs unintentionally (Dovidio, Kawakami, & Beach, 2001), automatically (Dovidio, Hewstone, Glick, & Esses, 2010), and which can operate without people being aware of the “biased associations or of the role those associations play in guiding their judgment and action” (Greenwald, Dsagupta, et al., 2022, p. 8). However, Gawronski et al. (this issue) skillfully argue how and why none of these shoes fit. In the end, we resonate with Gawronski et al.’s critical conclusion that “despite 25 years of extensive research, the current labeling conventions are still based on conceptually ambiguous lists according to which a measure qualifies as implicit if researchers have described it as implicit in the past” (p. 142; see also Gawronski, De Houwer, & Sherman, 2020). While we agree with Gawronski, Ledgerwood, and Eastwick’s analysis of current problems in the way implicit bias is conceived and studied, where we diverge is in the proposed solution. We deliberately use the word “diverge” rather than “disagree,” because the perspective that brings us here is quite different. Different perspectives carry different assumptions and dictate different priorities. Gawronski et al. (this issue) focus on implicit bias as a behavioral phenomenon that can be distinguished from the bias that is assessed by implicit measures. They write that “bias can be defined as the effect of social category cues (e.g., cues related to race, gender, etc.) on behavioral responses” and “to classify a person’s behavioral response toward a target as an instance of IB [implicit bias], one has to demonstrate that (1) the behavioral response is influenced by social category cues and (2) the person is unaware of the effect of the relevant social category cues on their behavioral response” (p. 5). As clear and as elegant in its directness that this set of definitions is, we are not convinced that this shoe fits, either. At first glance, Gawronski et al.’s (this issue) definition may seem quite similar to the definition recently used by Greenwald, Dsagupta, et al. (2022, p. 8) as a bias that
期刊介绍:
Psychological Inquiry serves as an international journal dedicated to the advancement of psychological theory. Each edition features an extensive target article exploring a controversial or provocative topic, accompanied by peer commentaries and a response from the target author(s). Proposals for target articles must be submitted using the Target Article Proposal Form, and only approved proposals undergo peer review by at least three reviewers. Authors are invited to submit their full articles after the proposal has received approval from the Editor.