{"title":"Muñoz,麦迪逊,权利","authors":"M. Zuckert","doi":"10.1086/725480","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"My colleague Phillip Muñoz has written a book both very excellent and very provocative. Some of my fellow symposiasts have been provoked to dissent firmly from his normative orientation around the idea of natural rights. As someone who has written two books with “natural rights” in their titles, it can be no surprise that I am not provoked in this way. I wish to pursue further the natural rights approach developed by Muñoz. This is valid and desirable no matter what views we may have about natural rights because it is called for by our duty to the “original public meaning” of the Constitution, as Muñoz’s research reveals. The center of his book is an attempt to explain “the foundations” of the founders’ doctrines in their “philosophies and theologies of the natural right of religious liberty” (2022, 68). The chief source for the philosophic foundation is James Madison, whoseMemorial and Remonstrance against Religious Assessments is taken byMuñoz to provide the essential account of the founders’ shared understanding of that natural right (82). Paradoxically, however, Madison held to an “idiosyncratic”—that is, not widely shared—constitutional-legal doctrine of religious noncognizance that he inferred from that shared understanding.My goal in this note is to probe that paradox by,first, reconstructingMadison’s position in a somewhat different and more direct way thanMuñoz does and, second, asking whether Madison is correct in believing that noncognizance is the correct constitutional doctrine following from the natural right of religious liberty. The idea of a natural right to religious liberty was extremely widespread in founding-era America, but philosophic arguments explaining or defending that","PeriodicalId":41928,"journal":{"name":"American Political Thought","volume":"12 1","pages":"413 - 416"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3000,"publicationDate":"2023-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"1","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Muñoz, Madison, Rights\",\"authors\":\"M. Zuckert\",\"doi\":\"10.1086/725480\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"My colleague Phillip Muñoz has written a book both very excellent and very provocative. Some of my fellow symposiasts have been provoked to dissent firmly from his normative orientation around the idea of natural rights. As someone who has written two books with “natural rights” in their titles, it can be no surprise that I am not provoked in this way. I wish to pursue further the natural rights approach developed by Muñoz. This is valid and desirable no matter what views we may have about natural rights because it is called for by our duty to the “original public meaning” of the Constitution, as Muñoz’s research reveals. The center of his book is an attempt to explain “the foundations” of the founders’ doctrines in their “philosophies and theologies of the natural right of religious liberty” (2022, 68). The chief source for the philosophic foundation is James Madison, whoseMemorial and Remonstrance against Religious Assessments is taken byMuñoz to provide the essential account of the founders’ shared understanding of that natural right (82). Paradoxically, however, Madison held to an “idiosyncratic”—that is, not widely shared—constitutional-legal doctrine of religious noncognizance that he inferred from that shared understanding.My goal in this note is to probe that paradox by,first, reconstructingMadison’s position in a somewhat different and more direct way thanMuñoz does and, second, asking whether Madison is correct in believing that noncognizance is the correct constitutional doctrine following from the natural right of religious liberty. The idea of a natural right to religious liberty was extremely widespread in founding-era America, but philosophic arguments explaining or defending that\",\"PeriodicalId\":41928,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"American Political Thought\",\"volume\":\"12 1\",\"pages\":\"413 - 416\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.3000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-06-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"1\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"American Political Thought\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1086/725480\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q4\",\"JCRName\":\"POLITICAL SCIENCE\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"American Political Thought","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1086/725480","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q4","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
摘要
我的同事菲利普·穆尼奥斯写了一本书,既非常优秀,又极具煽动性。我的一些专题讨论会同事强烈反对他围绕自然权利理念的规范取向。作为一个已经写了两本书名中带有“自然权利”的书的人,我没有被这种方式激怒也就不足为奇了。我希望进一步推行穆尼奥斯提出的自然权利办法。无论我们对自然权利有什么看法,这都是有效和可取的,因为正如穆尼奥斯的研究所揭示的那样,这是我们对宪法“原始公共意义”的义务所要求的。他的书的中心是试图解释创始人在“宗教自由的自然权利的哲学和神学”中的教义的“基础”(2022,68)。哲学基础的主要来源是詹姆斯·麦迪逊(James Madison),穆尼奥斯(Muñoz)认为他的《对宗教评估的纪念和抗议》(Memorial and Remonstance against Religious Assessment)对创始人对这一自然权利的共同理解提供了重要的解释(82)。然而,矛盾的是,麦迪逊坚持一种“特殊”的——也就是说,没有被广泛认同的——宪法法律原则,即他从这种共同的理解中推断出的宗教不承认。我在这篇文章中的目标是通过以下方式来探究这一悖论:首先,以一种与穆尼奥斯有所不同、更直接的方式重建麦迪逊的立场;其次,询问麦迪逊是否正确地认为,不承认是源自宗教自由的自然权利的正确宪法学说。宗教自由的自然权利在建国时代的美国非常普遍,但哲学论点解释或捍卫了这一点
My colleague Phillip Muñoz has written a book both very excellent and very provocative. Some of my fellow symposiasts have been provoked to dissent firmly from his normative orientation around the idea of natural rights. As someone who has written two books with “natural rights” in their titles, it can be no surprise that I am not provoked in this way. I wish to pursue further the natural rights approach developed by Muñoz. This is valid and desirable no matter what views we may have about natural rights because it is called for by our duty to the “original public meaning” of the Constitution, as Muñoz’s research reveals. The center of his book is an attempt to explain “the foundations” of the founders’ doctrines in their “philosophies and theologies of the natural right of religious liberty” (2022, 68). The chief source for the philosophic foundation is James Madison, whoseMemorial and Remonstrance against Religious Assessments is taken byMuñoz to provide the essential account of the founders’ shared understanding of that natural right (82). Paradoxically, however, Madison held to an “idiosyncratic”—that is, not widely shared—constitutional-legal doctrine of religious noncognizance that he inferred from that shared understanding.My goal in this note is to probe that paradox by,first, reconstructingMadison’s position in a somewhat different and more direct way thanMuñoz does and, second, asking whether Madison is correct in believing that noncognizance is the correct constitutional doctrine following from the natural right of religious liberty. The idea of a natural right to religious liberty was extremely widespread in founding-era America, but philosophic arguments explaining or defending that