重新思考法律现实主义:走向自然法理学

IF 2.2 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Texas Law Review Pub Date : 1997-12-01 DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199206490.003.0003
B. Leiter
{"title":"重新思考法律现实主义:走向自然法理学","authors":"B. Leiter","doi":"10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199206490.003.0003","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"I. Introduction Considering the enormous influence Legal Realism has exercised upon American law and legal education over the last sixty years, and considering, too, as the cliche has it, that \"we are all realists now,\" it remains surprising how inadequate-indeed inaccurate-most descriptions of Realism turn out to be. Ronald Dworkin, for example, claims that according to Realism, \"judges actually decide cases according to their own political or moral tastes, and then choose an appropriate legal rule as a rationalization.\"1 Dworkin is echoed by Judge Jon Newman of the Second Circuit who asserts that Realists believe that \"the judge simply selects the result that best comports with personal values and then enlists, sometimes brutally, whatever doctrines arguably support the result.\"2 John Hart Ely says the Realists \"'discovered' that judges were human and therefore were likely in a variety of legal contexts consciously or unconsciously to slip their personal values into their legal reasoning. \"3 Steven Burton remarks that it is often \"claimed, in legal realist fashion, that judges decide whatever they want to decide when the law is unclear (and it is often or always unclear).\"4 Fred Schauer describes Realists as holding \"that legal decision-makers are largely unconstrained by forces external to their own decision-making preferences. \"5 And Robert Satter, a Connecticut trial judge, says in a recent popular work that Realists \"assert that a judge exercises unbridled discretion in making decisions; he works backward from conclusion to principles and uses principles only to rationalize his conclusions. [Realists] consider the judge's values all-important. \"6 Glosses on Realism like these are surely familiar to every student of the literature. But it may help to recast them in a slightly more systematic form to understand precisely what picture of Realism so powerfully grips the legal imagination. According to what I will call the \"Received View,\" Legal Realism is fundamentally: (1) a descriptive theory about the nature of judicial decision, according to which, (2) judges exercise unfettered discretion, in order (3) to reach results based on their personal tastes and values, which (4) they then rationalize after-the-fact with appropriate legal rules and reasons. Like much \"conventional wisdom,\" the Received View of Realism has an element of truth: the core of Realism is, indeed, a certain sort of descriptive claim about how judges decide cases, according to which judges rationalize, after the fact, decisions reached on other grounds. But it is, or so I shall argue, quite misleading to think of Realism as committed to the claim that judges exercise \"unfettered\" discretion7 or that they make choices based on \"personal\" values and tastes. That Realism has been saddled with these claims-what I shall call the claims of \"Judicial Volition\" and \"Judicial Idiosyncrasy\"-has contributed in no small measure to the frequent reduction of Realism to a whipping boy for legal common sense.8 As a preliminary matter, however, any talk about the core of \"Realism\"-or even of \"Realism\" simpliciter-invites the objection that there simply is no such thing: there is no doctrine of \"Realism\" as apart from the views of individual writers.9 This sort of familiar skepticism is, I think, largely false. For everyone commonly thought to be a RealistKarl Llewellyn, Jerome Frank, Underhill Moore, Felix Cohen, Leon Green, Herman Oliphant, Walter Wheeler Cook, and Max Radin, among others-endorses the following descriptive claim about adjudication: in deciding cases, judges respond primarily to the stimulus of the facts. The Received View can then be seen as simply one interpretation of certain aspects of what I shall call this \"Core Claim\" of Realism, to which I return below.10 Indeed, I will suggest something further: that the misleading presentation of the Received View as the essence of Realism really represents what we may call the \"Frankification\" of Realism, i. …","PeriodicalId":47670,"journal":{"name":"Texas Law Review","volume":"76 1","pages":"267"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2000,"publicationDate":"1997-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"91","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Rethinking Legal Realism: Toward a Naturalized Jurisprudence\",\"authors\":\"B. Leiter\",\"doi\":\"10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199206490.003.0003\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"I. Introduction Considering the enormous influence Legal Realism has exercised upon American law and legal education over the last sixty years, and considering, too, as the cliche has it, that \\\"we are all realists now,\\\" it remains surprising how inadequate-indeed inaccurate-most descriptions of Realism turn out to be. Ronald Dworkin, for example, claims that according to Realism, \\\"judges actually decide cases according to their own political or moral tastes, and then choose an appropriate legal rule as a rationalization.\\\"1 Dworkin is echoed by Judge Jon Newman of the Second Circuit who asserts that Realists believe that \\\"the judge simply selects the result that best comports with personal values and then enlists, sometimes brutally, whatever doctrines arguably support the result.\\\"2 John Hart Ely says the Realists \\\"'discovered' that judges were human and therefore were likely in a variety of legal contexts consciously or unconsciously to slip their personal values into their legal reasoning. \\\"3 Steven Burton remarks that it is often \\\"claimed, in legal realist fashion, that judges decide whatever they want to decide when the law is unclear (and it is often or always unclear).\\\"4 Fred Schauer describes Realists as holding \\\"that legal decision-makers are largely unconstrained by forces external to their own decision-making preferences. \\\"5 And Robert Satter, a Connecticut trial judge, says in a recent popular work that Realists \\\"assert that a judge exercises unbridled discretion in making decisions; he works backward from conclusion to principles and uses principles only to rationalize his conclusions. [Realists] consider the judge's values all-important. \\\"6 Glosses on Realism like these are surely familiar to every student of the literature. But it may help to recast them in a slightly more systematic form to understand precisely what picture of Realism so powerfully grips the legal imagination. According to what I will call the \\\"Received View,\\\" Legal Realism is fundamentally: (1) a descriptive theory about the nature of judicial decision, according to which, (2) judges exercise unfettered discretion, in order (3) to reach results based on their personal tastes and values, which (4) they then rationalize after-the-fact with appropriate legal rules and reasons. Like much \\\"conventional wisdom,\\\" the Received View of Realism has an element of truth: the core of Realism is, indeed, a certain sort of descriptive claim about how judges decide cases, according to which judges rationalize, after the fact, decisions reached on other grounds. But it is, or so I shall argue, quite misleading to think of Realism as committed to the claim that judges exercise \\\"unfettered\\\" discretion7 or that they make choices based on \\\"personal\\\" values and tastes. That Realism has been saddled with these claims-what I shall call the claims of \\\"Judicial Volition\\\" and \\\"Judicial Idiosyncrasy\\\"-has contributed in no small measure to the frequent reduction of Realism to a whipping boy for legal common sense.8 As a preliminary matter, however, any talk about the core of \\\"Realism\\\"-or even of \\\"Realism\\\" simpliciter-invites the objection that there simply is no such thing: there is no doctrine of \\\"Realism\\\" as apart from the views of individual writers.9 This sort of familiar skepticism is, I think, largely false. For everyone commonly thought to be a RealistKarl Llewellyn, Jerome Frank, Underhill Moore, Felix Cohen, Leon Green, Herman Oliphant, Walter Wheeler Cook, and Max Radin, among others-endorses the following descriptive claim about adjudication: in deciding cases, judges respond primarily to the stimulus of the facts. The Received View can then be seen as simply one interpretation of certain aspects of what I shall call this \\\"Core Claim\\\" of Realism, to which I return below.10 Indeed, I will suggest something further: that the misleading presentation of the Received View as the essence of Realism really represents what we may call the \\\"Frankification\\\" of Realism, i. …\",\"PeriodicalId\":47670,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Texas Law Review\",\"volume\":\"76 1\",\"pages\":\"267\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":2.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"1997-12-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"91\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Texas Law Review\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"90\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199206490.003.0003\",\"RegionNum\":2,\"RegionCategory\":\"社会学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q1\",\"JCRName\":\"LAW\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Texas Law Review","FirstCategoryId":"90","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199206490.003.0003","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"LAW","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 91

摘要

一、引言考虑到法律现实主义在过去六十年中对美国法律和法律教育的巨大影响,再考虑到“我们现在都是现实主义者”这句陈词滥调,大多数对现实主义的描述竟然是如此不充分——实际上是不准确,这仍然令人惊讶。例如,罗纳德·德沃金(Ronald Dworkin)声称,根据现实主义,“法官实际上是根据自己的政治或道德品味来裁决案件,然后选择适当的法律规则作为合理化。”第二巡回法院的乔恩·纽曼(Jon Newman)法官也赞同德沃金的观点,他断言,现实主义者相信“法官只是选择最符合个人价值观的结果,然后采用(有时是残酷地)任何可能支持该结果的理论。”约翰·哈特·伊利(John Hart Ely)说,现实主义者“‘发现’法官也是人,因此在各种法律语境中,他们很可能有意或无意地将自己的个人价值观融入到他们的法律推理中。”3史蒂文·伯顿评论说,人们常常“以法律现实主义的方式宣称,法官在法律不明确的情况下决定他们想做的任何事情(法律经常或总是不明确)。”4弗雷德·肖尔将现实主义者描述为“法律决策者在很大程度上不受他们自己的决策偏好之外的力量的约束。”康涅狄格州的一位初审法官罗伯特·萨特(Robert Satter)在最近一部颇受欢迎的著作中说,现实主义者“主张法官在作出决定时行使不受约束的自由裁量权;他从结论回溯到原则,并且只使用原则来合理化他的结论。[现实主义者]认为法官的价值观至关重要。像这样的关于现实主义的注解,想必每个学文学的学生都很熟悉。但是,以一种稍微更系统的形式来重新塑造它们,以准确地理解现实主义是怎样一幅图景如此有力地抓住了法律的想象力,可能会有所帮助。根据我将称之为“公认观点”的观点,法律现实主义基本上是:(1)一种关于司法决定性质的描述性理论,根据该理论,(2)法官行使不受约束的自由裁量权,以便(3)根据他们的个人品味和价值观得出结果,(4)然后他们在事后用适当的法律规则和理由将其合理化。像许多“传统智慧”一样,现实主义的公认观点有一个真理的元素:现实主义的核心确实是关于法官如何判决案件的某种描述性主张,根据这种主张,法官在事实发生后,根据其他理由做出的决定进行合理化。但是,我认为,如果认为现实主义坚持认为法官行使“不受约束的”自由裁量权,或者他们根据“个人”的价值观和品味做出选择,那就很容易引起误解。现实主义背负着这些主张——我将称之为“司法意志”和“司法特质”的主张——这在很大程度上导致现实主义经常沦为法律常识的替罪羊然而,作为一个初步的问题,任何关于“现实主义”的核心——甚至是“现实主义”的简单化——的讨论都会引起这样的反对意见:根本就没有这样的东西:除了个别作家的观点之外,没有“现实主义”的学说我认为,这种熟悉的怀疑在很大程度上是错误的。对于每个通常被认为是现实主义者的人来说,卡尔·卢埃林、杰罗姆·弗兰克、昂德希尔·摩尔、菲利克斯·科恩、莱昂·格林、赫尔曼·奥列芬特、沃尔特·惠勒·库克和马克斯·雷丁等人都赞同以下关于裁决的描述:在判决案件时,法官主要是对事实的刺激作出反应。因此,“接受观点”可以被简单地看作是对我将称之为现实主义“核心主张”的某些方面的一种解释,我将在下面回到这一点事实上,我将进一步提出一些建议:将“接受的观点”作为现实主义的本质的误导性陈述,实际上代表了我们可以称之为现实主义的“Frankification”,. ...
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Rethinking Legal Realism: Toward a Naturalized Jurisprudence
I. Introduction Considering the enormous influence Legal Realism has exercised upon American law and legal education over the last sixty years, and considering, too, as the cliche has it, that "we are all realists now," it remains surprising how inadequate-indeed inaccurate-most descriptions of Realism turn out to be. Ronald Dworkin, for example, claims that according to Realism, "judges actually decide cases according to their own political or moral tastes, and then choose an appropriate legal rule as a rationalization."1 Dworkin is echoed by Judge Jon Newman of the Second Circuit who asserts that Realists believe that "the judge simply selects the result that best comports with personal values and then enlists, sometimes brutally, whatever doctrines arguably support the result."2 John Hart Ely says the Realists "'discovered' that judges were human and therefore were likely in a variety of legal contexts consciously or unconsciously to slip their personal values into their legal reasoning. "3 Steven Burton remarks that it is often "claimed, in legal realist fashion, that judges decide whatever they want to decide when the law is unclear (and it is often or always unclear)."4 Fred Schauer describes Realists as holding "that legal decision-makers are largely unconstrained by forces external to their own decision-making preferences. "5 And Robert Satter, a Connecticut trial judge, says in a recent popular work that Realists "assert that a judge exercises unbridled discretion in making decisions; he works backward from conclusion to principles and uses principles only to rationalize his conclusions. [Realists] consider the judge's values all-important. "6 Glosses on Realism like these are surely familiar to every student of the literature. But it may help to recast them in a slightly more systematic form to understand precisely what picture of Realism so powerfully grips the legal imagination. According to what I will call the "Received View," Legal Realism is fundamentally: (1) a descriptive theory about the nature of judicial decision, according to which, (2) judges exercise unfettered discretion, in order (3) to reach results based on their personal tastes and values, which (4) they then rationalize after-the-fact with appropriate legal rules and reasons. Like much "conventional wisdom," the Received View of Realism has an element of truth: the core of Realism is, indeed, a certain sort of descriptive claim about how judges decide cases, according to which judges rationalize, after the fact, decisions reached on other grounds. But it is, or so I shall argue, quite misleading to think of Realism as committed to the claim that judges exercise "unfettered" discretion7 or that they make choices based on "personal" values and tastes. That Realism has been saddled with these claims-what I shall call the claims of "Judicial Volition" and "Judicial Idiosyncrasy"-has contributed in no small measure to the frequent reduction of Realism to a whipping boy for legal common sense.8 As a preliminary matter, however, any talk about the core of "Realism"-or even of "Realism" simpliciter-invites the objection that there simply is no such thing: there is no doctrine of "Realism" as apart from the views of individual writers.9 This sort of familiar skepticism is, I think, largely false. For everyone commonly thought to be a RealistKarl Llewellyn, Jerome Frank, Underhill Moore, Felix Cohen, Leon Green, Herman Oliphant, Walter Wheeler Cook, and Max Radin, among others-endorses the following descriptive claim about adjudication: in deciding cases, judges respond primarily to the stimulus of the facts. The Received View can then be seen as simply one interpretation of certain aspects of what I shall call this "Core Claim" of Realism, to which I return below.10 Indeed, I will suggest something further: that the misleading presentation of the Received View as the essence of Realism really represents what we may call the "Frankification" of Realism, i. …
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
1.40
自引率
6.20%
发文量
0
期刊介绍: The Texas Law Review is a national and international leader in legal scholarship. Texas Law Review is an independent journal, edited and published entirely by students at the University of Texas School of Law. Our seven issues per year contain articles by professors, judges, and practitioners; reviews of important recent books from recognized experts, essays, commentaries; and student written notes. Texas Law Review is currently the ninth most cited legal periodical in federal and state cases in the United States and the thirteenth most cited by legal journals.
期刊最新文献
Guarantor of Last Resort Demystifying Nationwide Injunctions Feminism and the Tournament Tracing Equity: Realizing and Allocating Value in Chapter 11 State Public-Law Litigation in an Age of Polarization
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1