为什么未来偏差不能合理评估

Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI:10.11612/resphil.2143
Callie K. Phillips
{"title":"为什么未来偏差不能合理评估","authors":"Callie K. Phillips","doi":"10.11612/resphil.2143","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Future-bias is preferring some lesser future good to a greater past good because it is in the future, or preferring some greater past pain to some lesser future pain because it is in the past. Most of us think that this bias is rational. I argue that no agents have futurebiased preferences that are rationally evaluable—that is, evaluable as rational or irrational. Given certain plausible assumptions about rational evaluability, either we must find a new conception of future-bias that avoids the difficulties I raise, or we must conclude that future-biased preferences are not subject to rational evaluation. Future-bias is typically thought to be rational, often obviously rational.1 Parfit (1984) offers this now familiar example. I am in some hospital to have some kind of surgery. Since this is completely safe, and always successful, I have no fears about the effects. The surgery may be brief, or it may instead take a long time. Because I have to cooperate with the surgeon, I cannot have anesthetics. I have had this surgery once before, and I can remember how painful it is. Under a new policy, because the operation is so painful, patients are now afterwards made to forget it. Some drug removes their memories of the last few hours. I have just woken up. I cannot remember going to sleep. I ask my nurse if it has been decided when my operation is to be, and how long it must take. She says that she knows the facts about both me and another patient, but that she cannot remember which facts apply to whom. She can tell me only that the following is true. I may be the patient who had his operation yesterday. In that case, my operation was the longest ever performed, lasting ten hours. I may instead be the patient who is to have a short operation later today. It is either true that I did suffer for ten hours, or true that I shall suffer for one hour. 1 Others have called this ‘bias against the past’ or ‘past discounting.’ Res Philosophica, Vol. 98, No. 4, October 2021, pp. 573–596 https://doi.org/10.11612/resphil.2143 © 2021 Callie K. Phillips • © 2021 Res Philosophica 574 Callie K. Phillips I ask the nurse to find out which is true. While she is away, it is clear to me which I prefer to be true. If I learn that the first is true, I shall be greatly relieved. (165–166) It seems rational to prefer to be in the first situation in such cases despite the fact that this preference involves preferring to be in a situation that has a greater total amount of pain for you in the overall course of your life. In fact, many philosophers take it to be obvious that this preference is rational and without need of defense. Prior (1959), Craig (1999), Zimmerman (2005), Heathwood (2008), Hare (2007, 2009), and Kauppinen (2018) all claim that this bias is at least rationally permissible, if not rationally required. However, a handful of philosophers—including Moller (2002), Brink (2011), Sullivan and Greene (2015), Dougherty (2015)—raise difficulties for defending the rationality of this kind of bias. In this article I present an argument that would mean that all these authors have got it wrong. Future-biased preferences are not even rationally evaluable—that is, evaluable as rational or irrational. In determining whether an agent is future-biased, I will make use of the definitions offered by Sullivan and Greene (2015). An agent S is [future-biased] with respect to pleasure iff for two exclusive experiences, E1 and E2, where E1 is at least as pleasurable as E2, S prefers E2 because it is a present or future pleasure rather than a past one. . . . An agent S is [future-biased] with respect to pain iff for two exclusive experiences, E1 and E2, where E2 is at most as painful as E1, S prefers E1 because it is a past pain rather than a present or future one. (949) I will call agents “future-biased” if they are future-biased with respect to pleasure, pain, or both. I will say that a preference is a future-biased preference if it is a preference that meets the description on the right-hand side of one those biconditionals. In this article I argue that we must reject a plausible assumption about rational evaluability, find a new conception of future-bias that avoids the difficulties I raise, or conclude that future-biased preferences are not subject to rational evaluation. The conclusion that there are no rationally evaluable future-biased preferences is surprising and counterintuitive, but it has a substantial theoretical advantage that makes this neglected view worthy of our attention. One who is willing to accept the conclusion that future-biased preferences are not rationally evaluable will be freed from the burden to explain the widely assumed irrationality of another very common sort of time-bias—namely, near-bias. How to discharge this burden has eluded philosophers since Parfit first made the case for the tension between these biases in Reasons and Persons (1984). Near-bias, roughly, is preferring less pleasurable experiences because they are nearer in temporal proximity, or, conversely, Why Future-Bias Isn’t Rationally Evaluable 575 preferring more painful experiences to less painful ones because those more painful experiences are further in temporal proximity. A popular putative example of near-bias is found in the well-known Stanford marshmallow experiment. This study sought to measure the selfcontrol of children through an experiment in which some children were told they could eat one marshmallow now or wait fifteen minutes and receive two marshmallows. The kids who didn’t wait the fifteen minutes to receive the two marshmallows are said to be near-biased—they prefer a lesser good now to a greater good in the future.2 The claim that near-bias is irrational seems to hardly warrant defense.3 But Parfit (1984) argues convincingly that it is very difficult to defensibly claim both that near-bias is irrational and that future-bias is rational. In brief, the argument is that the way to argue that near-bias is irrational is to claim that a mere difference in when something occurs does not affect its value. But if we make this claim we should also think that future-bias is irrational. The fact that some experience is past shouldn’t affect its value for us. Parfit considers possible replies to this argument, but none of them seem to withstand scrutiny. For example, you might think that future-bias is importantly different from near-bias because we can’t change the past. If we can’t change the past, it is reasonable for us to be less concerned about it.4 However, we still seem to exhibit future-bias even if the future experience in question cannot be changed. If it were certain that you were going to be tortured later this afternoon, you would still be more concerned about this future painful experience than you would be if it were already in the past. Parfit considers and dismisses other possible defenses of an asymmetry in the rationality of near-bias and future-bias. In my view, these arguments have yet to be challenged successfully. Thus, it’s important to find a way to explain or 2 Mischel et al. 1972. It is worth noting that there is now doubt that the children in the study were near-biased in the sense that interests us (i.e., there’s doubt that they had preferred the temporally nearer marshmallow eating experience simply because it was temporally nearer). Delaying gratification, waiting to receive two marshmallows had a lot to do with economic and social disadvantages (Watts et al. 2018). It seems children who didn’t wait, often from resource poor environments, doubted that there would be marshmallows in the future, or at least assigned it lower probability. If a later outcome is lower probability than the nearer outcome, it will often be rational to choose the nearer. This highlights one difficulty with empirical investigation of near-bias and future-bias. It is difficult to create conditions that would clearly demonstrate a preference for one experience over the other based simply on the temporal location of those events (near or far, past or future) since it is difficult to create conditions where the likelihood of those experiences is the same. 3 For philosophers and the casual observer at least. The irrationality of near-bias is more controversial among economists and psychologists who are more likely to hold that only structural constraints on preferences are relevant for whether preferences are rational. 4 This strategy for explaining how future-bias is rational while near-bias is irrational has been pursued by Suhler and Callender (2012) and Dyke and Maclaurin (2002). Latham et al. (2021) investigate empirically the reasons for future-biased preferences and find that the belief that the past is practically irrelevant plays a role, but also find that even if agents supposed that they could causally affect the past, they still exhibit future-bias. 576 Callie K. Phillips avoid the asymmetry of the rationality of these time-biases. If one accepts my argument that future-biased preferences are not rationally evaluable, there is no asymmetry to explain; this major obstacle for defending the irrationality of near-bias falls to the wayside. In Section 6, I discuss this theoretical advantage and the implications of my argument in connection to near-bias in more depth. The argument of this article shows that the position that there are no rationally evaluable future-biased preferences can be motivated and is more attractive than it initially appears. Even if the best response to my argument is to reject one of the premises, we’ll learn that we must eschew plausible claims about preferences and rational evaluability—a lesson that has gone unappreciated. 1 Representation and Rational Criticism Our definitions of future-bias say that being future-biased is a matter of having certain preferences. So if we criticize the rationality of future-bias, we criticize having certain preferences. Whether it makes sense to criticize particular preference","PeriodicalId":0,"journal":{"name":"","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"4","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Why Future-Bias Isn’t Rationally Evaluable\",\"authors\":\"Callie K. Phillips\",\"doi\":\"10.11612/resphil.2143\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Future-bias is preferring some lesser future good to a greater past good because it is in the future, or preferring some greater past pain to some lesser future pain because it is in the past. Most of us think that this bias is rational. I argue that no agents have futurebiased preferences that are rationally evaluable—that is, evaluable as rational or irrational. Given certain plausible assumptions about rational evaluability, either we must find a new conception of future-bias that avoids the difficulties I raise, or we must conclude that future-biased preferences are not subject to rational evaluation. Future-bias is typically thought to be rational, often obviously rational.1 Parfit (1984) offers this now familiar example. I am in some hospital to have some kind of surgery. Since this is completely safe, and always successful, I have no fears about the effects. The surgery may be brief, or it may instead take a long time. Because I have to cooperate with the surgeon, I cannot have anesthetics. I have had this surgery once before, and I can remember how painful it is. Under a new policy, because the operation is so painful, patients are now afterwards made to forget it. Some drug removes their memories of the last few hours. I have just woken up. I cannot remember going to sleep. I ask my nurse if it has been decided when my operation is to be, and how long it must take. She says that she knows the facts about both me and another patient, but that she cannot remember which facts apply to whom. She can tell me only that the following is true. I may be the patient who had his operation yesterday. In that case, my operation was the longest ever performed, lasting ten hours. I may instead be the patient who is to have a short operation later today. It is either true that I did suffer for ten hours, or true that I shall suffer for one hour. 1 Others have called this ‘bias against the past’ or ‘past discounting.’ Res Philosophica, Vol. 98, No. 4, October 2021, pp. 573–596 https://doi.org/10.11612/resphil.2143 © 2021 Callie K. Phillips • © 2021 Res Philosophica 574 Callie K. Phillips I ask the nurse to find out which is true. While she is away, it is clear to me which I prefer to be true. If I learn that the first is true, I shall be greatly relieved. (165–166) It seems rational to prefer to be in the first situation in such cases despite the fact that this preference involves preferring to be in a situation that has a greater total amount of pain for you in the overall course of your life. In fact, many philosophers take it to be obvious that this preference is rational and without need of defense. Prior (1959), Craig (1999), Zimmerman (2005), Heathwood (2008), Hare (2007, 2009), and Kauppinen (2018) all claim that this bias is at least rationally permissible, if not rationally required. However, a handful of philosophers—including Moller (2002), Brink (2011), Sullivan and Greene (2015), Dougherty (2015)—raise difficulties for defending the rationality of this kind of bias. In this article I present an argument that would mean that all these authors have got it wrong. Future-biased preferences are not even rationally evaluable—that is, evaluable as rational or irrational. In determining whether an agent is future-biased, I will make use of the definitions offered by Sullivan and Greene (2015). An agent S is [future-biased] with respect to pleasure iff for two exclusive experiences, E1 and E2, where E1 is at least as pleasurable as E2, S prefers E2 because it is a present or future pleasure rather than a past one. . . . An agent S is [future-biased] with respect to pain iff for two exclusive experiences, E1 and E2, where E2 is at most as painful as E1, S prefers E1 because it is a past pain rather than a present or future one. (949) I will call agents “future-biased” if they are future-biased with respect to pleasure, pain, or both. I will say that a preference is a future-biased preference if it is a preference that meets the description on the right-hand side of one those biconditionals. In this article I argue that we must reject a plausible assumption about rational evaluability, find a new conception of future-bias that avoids the difficulties I raise, or conclude that future-biased preferences are not subject to rational evaluation. The conclusion that there are no rationally evaluable future-biased preferences is surprising and counterintuitive, but it has a substantial theoretical advantage that makes this neglected view worthy of our attention. One who is willing to accept the conclusion that future-biased preferences are not rationally evaluable will be freed from the burden to explain the widely assumed irrationality of another very common sort of time-bias—namely, near-bias. How to discharge this burden has eluded philosophers since Parfit first made the case for the tension between these biases in Reasons and Persons (1984). Near-bias, roughly, is preferring less pleasurable experiences because they are nearer in temporal proximity, or, conversely, Why Future-Bias Isn’t Rationally Evaluable 575 preferring more painful experiences to less painful ones because those more painful experiences are further in temporal proximity. A popular putative example of near-bias is found in the well-known Stanford marshmallow experiment. This study sought to measure the selfcontrol of children through an experiment in which some children were told they could eat one marshmallow now or wait fifteen minutes and receive two marshmallows. The kids who didn’t wait the fifteen minutes to receive the two marshmallows are said to be near-biased—they prefer a lesser good now to a greater good in the future.2 The claim that near-bias is irrational seems to hardly warrant defense.3 But Parfit (1984) argues convincingly that it is very difficult to defensibly claim both that near-bias is irrational and that future-bias is rational. In brief, the argument is that the way to argue that near-bias is irrational is to claim that a mere difference in when something occurs does not affect its value. But if we make this claim we should also think that future-bias is irrational. The fact that some experience is past shouldn’t affect its value for us. Parfit considers possible replies to this argument, but none of them seem to withstand scrutiny. For example, you might think that future-bias is importantly different from near-bias because we can’t change the past. If we can’t change the past, it is reasonable for us to be less concerned about it.4 However, we still seem to exhibit future-bias even if the future experience in question cannot be changed. If it were certain that you were going to be tortured later this afternoon, you would still be more concerned about this future painful experience than you would be if it were already in the past. Parfit considers and dismisses other possible defenses of an asymmetry in the rationality of near-bias and future-bias. In my view, these arguments have yet to be challenged successfully. Thus, it’s important to find a way to explain or 2 Mischel et al. 1972. It is worth noting that there is now doubt that the children in the study were near-biased in the sense that interests us (i.e., there’s doubt that they had preferred the temporally nearer marshmallow eating experience simply because it was temporally nearer). Delaying gratification, waiting to receive two marshmallows had a lot to do with economic and social disadvantages (Watts et al. 2018). It seems children who didn’t wait, often from resource poor environments, doubted that there would be marshmallows in the future, or at least assigned it lower probability. If a later outcome is lower probability than the nearer outcome, it will often be rational to choose the nearer. This highlights one difficulty with empirical investigation of near-bias and future-bias. It is difficult to create conditions that would clearly demonstrate a preference for one experience over the other based simply on the temporal location of those events (near or far, past or future) since it is difficult to create conditions where the likelihood of those experiences is the same. 3 For philosophers and the casual observer at least. The irrationality of near-bias is more controversial among economists and psychologists who are more likely to hold that only structural constraints on preferences are relevant for whether preferences are rational. 4 This strategy for explaining how future-bias is rational while near-bias is irrational has been pursued by Suhler and Callender (2012) and Dyke and Maclaurin (2002). Latham et al. (2021) investigate empirically the reasons for future-biased preferences and find that the belief that the past is practically irrelevant plays a role, but also find that even if agents supposed that they could causally affect the past, they still exhibit future-bias. 576 Callie K. Phillips avoid the asymmetry of the rationality of these time-biases. If one accepts my argument that future-biased preferences are not rationally evaluable, there is no asymmetry to explain; this major obstacle for defending the irrationality of near-bias falls to the wayside. In Section 6, I discuss this theoretical advantage and the implications of my argument in connection to near-bias in more depth. The argument of this article shows that the position that there are no rationally evaluable future-biased preferences can be motivated and is more attractive than it initially appears. Even if the best response to my argument is to reject one of the premises, we’ll learn that we must eschew plausible claims about preferences and rational evaluability—a lesson that has gone unappreciated. 1 Representation and Rational Criticism Our definitions of future-bias say that being future-biased is a matter of having certain preferences. So if we criticize the rationality of future-bias, we criticize having certain preferences. Whether it makes sense to criticize particular preference\",\"PeriodicalId\":0,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0,\"publicationDate\":\"2021-01-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"4\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.11612/resphil.2143\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.11612/resphil.2143","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4

摘要

未来偏见是指人们更喜欢未来较小的好处而不是过去较大的好处,因为它是未来的,或者更喜欢过去较大的痛苦而不是未来较小的痛苦,因为它是过去的。我们大多数人认为这种偏见是理性的。我认为,没有任何行为体具有可理性评估的未来偏好,也就是说,可理性或非理性评估。考虑到关于理性可评估性的某些貌似合理的假设,我们要么必须找到一个新的未来偏见概念,以避免我提出的困难,要么我们必须得出结论,未来偏见偏好不受理性评估的影响。对未来的偏见通常被认为是理性的,而且往往是明显理性的帕菲特(Parfit, 1984)提供了这个我们现在熟悉的例子。我在医院做手术。因为这是完全安全的,而且总是成功的,所以我不担心它的影响。手术可能很短,也可能需要很长时间。因为我必须配合外科医生,所以我不能使用麻醉剂。我以前做过一次这样的手术,我还记得有多痛。在一项新政策下,由于手术非常痛苦,病人现在被要求在手术后忘记它。某种药物能消除他们过去几个小时的记忆。我刚醒。我不记得是怎么睡着的。我问护士我的手术时间是否已经决定了,手术需要多长时间。她说她知道我和另一个病人的情况,但她不记得哪些情况适用于谁。她只能告诉我以下是真实的。我可能就是昨天做手术的那个病人。在这种情况下,我的手术是有史以来最长的,持续了10个小时。我可能是今天晚些时候要做一个简短手术的病人。要么我确实挨了十个小时的苦,要么我还将挨一个小时的苦。另一些人称之为“对过去的偏见”或“对过去的贴现”。《Res Philosophica》,第98卷,第4期,2021年10月,第573-596页https://doi.org/10.11612/resphil.2143©2021 Callie K. Phillips•©2021 Res Philosophica 574 Callie K. Phillips我请护士找出哪个是真的。她不在的时候,我很清楚我更愿意诚实。如果我知道第一个是真的,我就放心了。(165-166)在这种情况下,宁愿处于第一种情况似乎是理性的,尽管事实上,这种偏好涉及到在你的整个生命过程中更愿意处于一种总痛苦更大的情况。事实上,许多哲学家认为,这种偏好显然是理性的,无需为之辩护。Prior(1959年)、Craig(1999年)、Zimmerman(2005年)、Heathwood(2008年)、Hare(2007年、2009年)和Kauppinen(2018年)都声称,这种偏见即使不是理性需要,至少也是理性允许的。然而,少数哲学家——包括Moller(2002)、Brink(2011)、Sullivan and Greene(2015)、Dougherty(2015)——为捍卫这种偏见的合理性提出了困难。在这篇文章中,我提出了一个论点,这意味着所有这些作者都错了。对未来有偏见的偏好甚至不能被理性地评估——也就是说,不能被理性或非理性地评估。在确定代理人是否具有未来偏见时,我将使用Sullivan和Greene(2015)提供的定义。对于两种独特的体验,E1和E2, agent S对快乐有[未来偏见],E1至少和E2一样快乐,S更喜欢E2,因为它是现在或未来的快乐,而不是过去的. . . .对于两种不同的经历,E1和E2, agent S对痛苦有[未来偏见],其中E2最多和E1一样痛苦,S更喜欢E1,因为它是过去的痛苦,而不是现在或未来的痛苦。(949)如果行为体对快乐、痛苦或两者都有未来偏见,我就称其为“未来偏见”。如果一个偏好符合其中一个双条件条件右边的描述,我就说这个偏好是未来偏向偏好。在这篇文章中,我认为我们必须拒绝一个关于理性可评估性的貌似合理的假设,找到一个避免我提出的困难的未来偏见的新概念,或者得出未来偏见偏好不受理性评估影响的结论。不存在可理性评估的未来偏好的结论令人惊讶,也违反直觉,但它有一个实质性的理论优势,使这个被忽视的观点值得我们关注。如果一个人愿意接受“未来偏向偏好无法理性评估”这一结论,那么他就不必再去解释另一种普遍存在的时间偏向——即“近似偏向”——的非理性。自从帕菲特在《理性与人格》(1984)一书中首次提出这些偏见之间的紧张关系以来,哲学家们就一直在逃避这种负担。 粗略地说,“近偏倚”是指更喜欢不太愉快的经历,因为它们在时间上更接近,或者反过来说,“为什么未来偏倚不是理性可评估的”。575更喜欢更痛苦的经历,而不是不那么痛苦的经历,因为那些更痛苦的经历在时间上更接近。在著名的斯坦福棉花糖实验中发现了一个流行的近似偏差的例子。这项研究试图通过一个实验来衡量孩子们的自我控制能力,在这个实验中,一些孩子被告知他们可以现在吃一个棉花糖,或者等15分钟再吃两个棉花糖。那些没有等15分钟就得到两个棉花糖的孩子被认为是近乎偏见的——他们更喜欢现在的小好处,而不是未来的大好处“近似偏见”是非理性的说法似乎很难站得住脚但帕菲特(1984)令人信服地指出,很难有理由宣称近期偏见是非理性的,而未来偏见是理性的。简而言之,论证“近似偏差”是不合理的方式,就是声称事情发生的时间差异并不影响其价值。但如果我们这么说,我们也应该认为未来偏见是非理性的。过去的经历不应该影响它对我们的价值。帕菲特考虑了对这一论点可能的回答,但似乎没有一个经得起推敲。例如,你可能会认为未来偏见与近期偏见有很大不同,因为我们无法改变过去。如果我们不能改变过去,那么我们就不那么关注它是有道理的然而,即使未来的经历无法改变,我们似乎仍然表现出对未来的偏见。如果你确定今天下午晚些时候会受到折磨,你仍然会更关心未来的痛苦经历,而不是过去已经发生的痛苦经历。帕菲特考虑并驳回了近期偏见和未来偏见的合理性中不对称的其他可能的辩护。在我看来,这些论点还没有被成功地挑战。因此,重要的是找到一种方法来解释或2米歇尔等人。1972。值得注意的是,在我们感兴趣的意义上,现在有疑问的是,研究中的孩子们在接近偏见的意义上(也就是说,有疑问的是,他们更喜欢暂时更近的棉花糖吃体验,只是因为它暂时更近)。延迟满足,等待收到两个棉花糖与经济和社会劣势有很大关系(Watts et al. 2018)。似乎没有等待的孩子,通常来自资源贫乏的环境,怀疑未来是否会有棉花糖,或者至少认为它的概率较低。如果较晚的结果比较近的结果的概率更低,那么选择较近的结果往往是理性的。这突出了对近偏差和未来偏差进行实证调查的一个困难。仅仅基于事件发生的时间位置(近或远,过去或未来),我们很难创造出能够清楚地证明一种体验优于另一种体验的条件,因为我们很难创造出这些体验发生的可能性相同的条件。至少对哲学家和普通的观察者来说是这样。在经济学家和心理学家中,“近似偏差”的非理性更具争议性,他们更倾向于认为,只有偏好的结构性约束与偏好是否理性有关。Suhler和Callender(2012)以及Dyke和Maclaurin(2002)都采用了这种策略来解释为什么未来偏见是理性的,而近期偏见是非理性的。Latham等人(2021)从经验上调查了未来偏见偏好的原因,发现过去实际上是无关紧要的信念发挥了作用,但也发现即使代理人认为他们可以因果影响过去,他们仍然表现出未来偏见。Callie K. Phillips避免了这些时间偏差的合理性的不对称性。如果一个人接受我的观点,即对未来有偏见的偏好是无法理性评估的,那么就没有不对称可以解释;这个为“近似偏差”的非理性辩护的主要障碍被抛到了一边。在第6节中,我将更深入地讨论这一理论优势以及我的论点与近偏倚相关的含义。这篇文章的论点表明,没有理性可评估的未来偏向偏好的立场是可以被激发的,而且比它最初看起来更有吸引力。即使对我的论点的最佳回应是拒绝其中一个前提,我们也会学到,我们必须避免关于偏好和理性可评估性的貌似合理的主张——这是一个没有得到重视的教训。我们对未来偏见的定义是,对未来偏见是有某种偏好的问题。 所以如果我们批评未来偏见的合理性,我们就是在批评拥有某些偏好。批评特定偏好是否有意义
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
Why Future-Bias Isn’t Rationally Evaluable
Future-bias is preferring some lesser future good to a greater past good because it is in the future, or preferring some greater past pain to some lesser future pain because it is in the past. Most of us think that this bias is rational. I argue that no agents have futurebiased preferences that are rationally evaluable—that is, evaluable as rational or irrational. Given certain plausible assumptions about rational evaluability, either we must find a new conception of future-bias that avoids the difficulties I raise, or we must conclude that future-biased preferences are not subject to rational evaluation. Future-bias is typically thought to be rational, often obviously rational.1 Parfit (1984) offers this now familiar example. I am in some hospital to have some kind of surgery. Since this is completely safe, and always successful, I have no fears about the effects. The surgery may be brief, or it may instead take a long time. Because I have to cooperate with the surgeon, I cannot have anesthetics. I have had this surgery once before, and I can remember how painful it is. Under a new policy, because the operation is so painful, patients are now afterwards made to forget it. Some drug removes their memories of the last few hours. I have just woken up. I cannot remember going to sleep. I ask my nurse if it has been decided when my operation is to be, and how long it must take. She says that she knows the facts about both me and another patient, but that she cannot remember which facts apply to whom. She can tell me only that the following is true. I may be the patient who had his operation yesterday. In that case, my operation was the longest ever performed, lasting ten hours. I may instead be the patient who is to have a short operation later today. It is either true that I did suffer for ten hours, or true that I shall suffer for one hour. 1 Others have called this ‘bias against the past’ or ‘past discounting.’ Res Philosophica, Vol. 98, No. 4, October 2021, pp. 573–596 https://doi.org/10.11612/resphil.2143 © 2021 Callie K. Phillips • © 2021 Res Philosophica 574 Callie K. Phillips I ask the nurse to find out which is true. While she is away, it is clear to me which I prefer to be true. If I learn that the first is true, I shall be greatly relieved. (165–166) It seems rational to prefer to be in the first situation in such cases despite the fact that this preference involves preferring to be in a situation that has a greater total amount of pain for you in the overall course of your life. In fact, many philosophers take it to be obvious that this preference is rational and without need of defense. Prior (1959), Craig (1999), Zimmerman (2005), Heathwood (2008), Hare (2007, 2009), and Kauppinen (2018) all claim that this bias is at least rationally permissible, if not rationally required. However, a handful of philosophers—including Moller (2002), Brink (2011), Sullivan and Greene (2015), Dougherty (2015)—raise difficulties for defending the rationality of this kind of bias. In this article I present an argument that would mean that all these authors have got it wrong. Future-biased preferences are not even rationally evaluable—that is, evaluable as rational or irrational. In determining whether an agent is future-biased, I will make use of the definitions offered by Sullivan and Greene (2015). An agent S is [future-biased] with respect to pleasure iff for two exclusive experiences, E1 and E2, where E1 is at least as pleasurable as E2, S prefers E2 because it is a present or future pleasure rather than a past one. . . . An agent S is [future-biased] with respect to pain iff for two exclusive experiences, E1 and E2, where E2 is at most as painful as E1, S prefers E1 because it is a past pain rather than a present or future one. (949) I will call agents “future-biased” if they are future-biased with respect to pleasure, pain, or both. I will say that a preference is a future-biased preference if it is a preference that meets the description on the right-hand side of one those biconditionals. In this article I argue that we must reject a plausible assumption about rational evaluability, find a new conception of future-bias that avoids the difficulties I raise, or conclude that future-biased preferences are not subject to rational evaluation. The conclusion that there are no rationally evaluable future-biased preferences is surprising and counterintuitive, but it has a substantial theoretical advantage that makes this neglected view worthy of our attention. One who is willing to accept the conclusion that future-biased preferences are not rationally evaluable will be freed from the burden to explain the widely assumed irrationality of another very common sort of time-bias—namely, near-bias. How to discharge this burden has eluded philosophers since Parfit first made the case for the tension between these biases in Reasons and Persons (1984). Near-bias, roughly, is preferring less pleasurable experiences because they are nearer in temporal proximity, or, conversely, Why Future-Bias Isn’t Rationally Evaluable 575 preferring more painful experiences to less painful ones because those more painful experiences are further in temporal proximity. A popular putative example of near-bias is found in the well-known Stanford marshmallow experiment. This study sought to measure the selfcontrol of children through an experiment in which some children were told they could eat one marshmallow now or wait fifteen minutes and receive two marshmallows. The kids who didn’t wait the fifteen minutes to receive the two marshmallows are said to be near-biased—they prefer a lesser good now to a greater good in the future.2 The claim that near-bias is irrational seems to hardly warrant defense.3 But Parfit (1984) argues convincingly that it is very difficult to defensibly claim both that near-bias is irrational and that future-bias is rational. In brief, the argument is that the way to argue that near-bias is irrational is to claim that a mere difference in when something occurs does not affect its value. But if we make this claim we should also think that future-bias is irrational. The fact that some experience is past shouldn’t affect its value for us. Parfit considers possible replies to this argument, but none of them seem to withstand scrutiny. For example, you might think that future-bias is importantly different from near-bias because we can’t change the past. If we can’t change the past, it is reasonable for us to be less concerned about it.4 However, we still seem to exhibit future-bias even if the future experience in question cannot be changed. If it were certain that you were going to be tortured later this afternoon, you would still be more concerned about this future painful experience than you would be if it were already in the past. Parfit considers and dismisses other possible defenses of an asymmetry in the rationality of near-bias and future-bias. In my view, these arguments have yet to be challenged successfully. Thus, it’s important to find a way to explain or 2 Mischel et al. 1972. It is worth noting that there is now doubt that the children in the study were near-biased in the sense that interests us (i.e., there’s doubt that they had preferred the temporally nearer marshmallow eating experience simply because it was temporally nearer). Delaying gratification, waiting to receive two marshmallows had a lot to do with economic and social disadvantages (Watts et al. 2018). It seems children who didn’t wait, often from resource poor environments, doubted that there would be marshmallows in the future, or at least assigned it lower probability. If a later outcome is lower probability than the nearer outcome, it will often be rational to choose the nearer. This highlights one difficulty with empirical investigation of near-bias and future-bias. It is difficult to create conditions that would clearly demonstrate a preference for one experience over the other based simply on the temporal location of those events (near or far, past or future) since it is difficult to create conditions where the likelihood of those experiences is the same. 3 For philosophers and the casual observer at least. The irrationality of near-bias is more controversial among economists and psychologists who are more likely to hold that only structural constraints on preferences are relevant for whether preferences are rational. 4 This strategy for explaining how future-bias is rational while near-bias is irrational has been pursued by Suhler and Callender (2012) and Dyke and Maclaurin (2002). Latham et al. (2021) investigate empirically the reasons for future-biased preferences and find that the belief that the past is practically irrelevant plays a role, but also find that even if agents supposed that they could causally affect the past, they still exhibit future-bias. 576 Callie K. Phillips avoid the asymmetry of the rationality of these time-biases. If one accepts my argument that future-biased preferences are not rationally evaluable, there is no asymmetry to explain; this major obstacle for defending the irrationality of near-bias falls to the wayside. In Section 6, I discuss this theoretical advantage and the implications of my argument in connection to near-bias in more depth. The argument of this article shows that the position that there are no rationally evaluable future-biased preferences can be motivated and is more attractive than it initially appears. Even if the best response to my argument is to reject one of the premises, we’ll learn that we must eschew plausible claims about preferences and rational evaluability—a lesson that has gone unappreciated. 1 Representation and Rational Criticism Our definitions of future-bias say that being future-biased is a matter of having certain preferences. So if we criticize the rationality of future-bias, we criticize having certain preferences. Whether it makes sense to criticize particular preference
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1