对火力说真话:第一修正案如何动摇第二修正案

IF 2.2 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Texas Law Review Pub Date : 2012-02-21 DOI:10.2139/SSRN.2009125
Gregory P. Magarian
{"title":"对火力说真话:第一修正案如何动摇第二修正案","authors":"Gregory P. Magarian","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2009125","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"When the Supreme Court in District of Columbia v. Heller declared that the Second Amendment protects an individual right to keep and bear arms, it set atop the federal judicial agenda the critical task of elaborating the new right’s scope, limits, and content. Following Heller, commentators routinely draw upon the First Amendment’s protections for expressive freedom to support their proposals for Second Amendment doctrine. In this article, Professor Magarian advocates a very different role for the First Amendment in explicating the Second, and he contends that our best understanding of First Amendment theory and doctrine severely diminishes the Second Amendment’s legal potency. Professor Magarian first criticizes efforts to draw direct analogies between the First and Second Amendments, because the two amendments and their objects of protection diverge along critical descriptive, normative, and functional lines. He then contends that the longstanding debate about whether constitutional speech protections primarily serve collectivist or individualist purposes models a useful approach for interpreting the Second Amendment. Under that approach, the language of the Second Amendment’s preamble, which Heller all but erased from the text, compels a collectivist reading of the Second Amendment. The individual right to keep and bear arms, contrary to the Heller Court’s fixation on individual self-defense, must serve some collective interest. Many gun rights advocates urge that the Second Amendment serves a collective interest in deterring – and, if necessary, violently deposing – a tyrannical federal government. That theory of Second Amendment insurrectionism marks another point of contact with the First Amendment, because constitutional expressive freedom serves the conceptually similar function of protecting public debate in order to enable dynamic political change. Professor Magarian contends, however, that we should prefer debate to violence as a means of political change and that, in fact, the historical disparity in our legal culture’s attention to the First and Second Amendments reflects a longstanding choice of debate over insurrection. Moreover, embracing Second Amendment insurrectionism would endanger our commitment to protecting dissident political speech under the First Amendment. The article concludes that our insights about the First Amendment leave little space for the Second Amendment to develop as a meaningful constraint on government action.","PeriodicalId":47670,"journal":{"name":"Texas Law Review","volume":"91 1","pages":"49-99"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2000,"publicationDate":"2012-02-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"4","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Speaking Truth to Firepower: How the First Amendment Destabilizes the Second\",\"authors\":\"Gregory P. Magarian\",\"doi\":\"10.2139/SSRN.2009125\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"When the Supreme Court in District of Columbia v. Heller declared that the Second Amendment protects an individual right to keep and bear arms, it set atop the federal judicial agenda the critical task of elaborating the new right’s scope, limits, and content. Following Heller, commentators routinely draw upon the First Amendment’s protections for expressive freedom to support their proposals for Second Amendment doctrine. In this article, Professor Magarian advocates a very different role for the First Amendment in explicating the Second, and he contends that our best understanding of First Amendment theory and doctrine severely diminishes the Second Amendment’s legal potency. Professor Magarian first criticizes efforts to draw direct analogies between the First and Second Amendments, because the two amendments and their objects of protection diverge along critical descriptive, normative, and functional lines. He then contends that the longstanding debate about whether constitutional speech protections primarily serve collectivist or individualist purposes models a useful approach for interpreting the Second Amendment. Under that approach, the language of the Second Amendment’s preamble, which Heller all but erased from the text, compels a collectivist reading of the Second Amendment. The individual right to keep and bear arms, contrary to the Heller Court’s fixation on individual self-defense, must serve some collective interest. Many gun rights advocates urge that the Second Amendment serves a collective interest in deterring – and, if necessary, violently deposing – a tyrannical federal government. That theory of Second Amendment insurrectionism marks another point of contact with the First Amendment, because constitutional expressive freedom serves the conceptually similar function of protecting public debate in order to enable dynamic political change. Professor Magarian contends, however, that we should prefer debate to violence as a means of political change and that, in fact, the historical disparity in our legal culture’s attention to the First and Second Amendments reflects a longstanding choice of debate over insurrection. Moreover, embracing Second Amendment insurrectionism would endanger our commitment to protecting dissident political speech under the First Amendment. The article concludes that our insights about the First Amendment leave little space for the Second Amendment to develop as a meaningful constraint on government action.\",\"PeriodicalId\":47670,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Texas Law Review\",\"volume\":\"91 1\",\"pages\":\"49-99\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":2.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"2012-02-21\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"4\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Texas Law Review\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"90\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2009125\",\"RegionNum\":2,\"RegionCategory\":\"社会学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q1\",\"JCRName\":\"LAW\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Texas Law Review","FirstCategoryId":"90","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2009125","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"LAW","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4

摘要

当最高法院在哥伦比亚特区诉海勒案中宣布第二修正案保护个人持有和携带武器的权利时,它将详细阐述这项新权利的范围、限制和内容的关键任务置于联邦司法议程的首位。继海勒之后,评论家们经常引用第一修正案对表达自由的保护来支持他们对第二修正案原则的建议。在这篇文章中,Magarian教授主张第一修正案在解释第二修正案时扮演一个非常不同的角色,他认为我们对第一修正案理论和原则的最佳理解严重削弱了第二修正案的法律效力。Magarian教授首先批评了在第一修正案和第二修正案之间进行直接类比的做法,因为这两项修正案及其保护对象在关键的描述性、规范性和功能性方面存在分歧。他接着认为,关于宪法言论保护主要是为集体主义还是个人主义服务的长期争论,为解释第二修正案提供了一个有用的方法。在这种方法下,第二修正案序言的语言(海勒几乎从文本中删除)迫使人们对第二修正案进行集体主义解读。与海勒法院对个人自卫的执着相反,个人持有和携带武器的权利必须服务于某种集体利益。许多枪支权利倡导者敦促说,第二修正案是为了集体利益而服务的,它可以威慑——如果有必要的话,还可以暴力推翻——一个暴戾的联邦政府。第二修正案造反的理论标志着与第一修正案的另一个接触点,因为宪法表达自由在概念上与保护公众辩论以实现动态政治变革的功能相似。然而,Magarian教授认为,作为政治变革的一种手段,我们应该更喜欢辩论而不是暴力。事实上,我们的法律文化对第一和第二修正案的关注的历史差异反映了长期以来对辩论而不是起义的选择。此外,拥护第二修正案的叛乱主义将危及我们根据第一修正案保护持不同政见的政治言论的承诺。文章的结论是,我们对第一修正案的理解给第二修正案发展成为对政府行为有意义的约束留下了很少的空间。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Speaking Truth to Firepower: How the First Amendment Destabilizes the Second
When the Supreme Court in District of Columbia v. Heller declared that the Second Amendment protects an individual right to keep and bear arms, it set atop the federal judicial agenda the critical task of elaborating the new right’s scope, limits, and content. Following Heller, commentators routinely draw upon the First Amendment’s protections for expressive freedom to support their proposals for Second Amendment doctrine. In this article, Professor Magarian advocates a very different role for the First Amendment in explicating the Second, and he contends that our best understanding of First Amendment theory and doctrine severely diminishes the Second Amendment’s legal potency. Professor Magarian first criticizes efforts to draw direct analogies between the First and Second Amendments, because the two amendments and their objects of protection diverge along critical descriptive, normative, and functional lines. He then contends that the longstanding debate about whether constitutional speech protections primarily serve collectivist or individualist purposes models a useful approach for interpreting the Second Amendment. Under that approach, the language of the Second Amendment’s preamble, which Heller all but erased from the text, compels a collectivist reading of the Second Amendment. The individual right to keep and bear arms, contrary to the Heller Court’s fixation on individual self-defense, must serve some collective interest. Many gun rights advocates urge that the Second Amendment serves a collective interest in deterring – and, if necessary, violently deposing – a tyrannical federal government. That theory of Second Amendment insurrectionism marks another point of contact with the First Amendment, because constitutional expressive freedom serves the conceptually similar function of protecting public debate in order to enable dynamic political change. Professor Magarian contends, however, that we should prefer debate to violence as a means of political change and that, in fact, the historical disparity in our legal culture’s attention to the First and Second Amendments reflects a longstanding choice of debate over insurrection. Moreover, embracing Second Amendment insurrectionism would endanger our commitment to protecting dissident political speech under the First Amendment. The article concludes that our insights about the First Amendment leave little space for the Second Amendment to develop as a meaningful constraint on government action.
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
1.40
自引率
6.20%
发文量
0
期刊介绍: The Texas Law Review is a national and international leader in legal scholarship. Texas Law Review is an independent journal, edited and published entirely by students at the University of Texas School of Law. Our seven issues per year contain articles by professors, judges, and practitioners; reviews of important recent books from recognized experts, essays, commentaries; and student written notes. Texas Law Review is currently the ninth most cited legal periodical in federal and state cases in the United States and the thirteenth most cited by legal journals.
期刊最新文献
Guarantor of Last Resort Demystifying Nationwide Injunctions Feminism and the Tournament Tracing Equity: Realizing and Allocating Value in Chapter 11 State Public-Law Litigation in an Age of Polarization
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1