原罪与司法独立:法官问责制

Paul D. Carrington, R. C. Cramton
{"title":"原罪与司法独立:法官问责制","authors":"Paul D. Carrington, R. C. Cramton","doi":"10.31228/osf.io/ut8je","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"TABLE OF CONTENTS I. A DEFINING CHALLENGE A. The Founding Vision 1. The Federalists' \"Ark of Safety\" B. Removing a Disabled Judge: The Pickering Case C. The Impeachment of Justice Chase: Are Justices Different? 1. How To Remove a Justice CONCLUSION I. A DEFINING CHALLENGE The independence of the judiciary is an enduring and defining objective of the legal profession. We lawyers, of all citizens, have the greatest stake in shielding judges from intimidation or reward. And that task of protecting judicial independence stands today at the very top of the agenda of the American legal profession. (1) The integrity of law and legal institutions requires more than just the protection of judges. It is equally dependent on the willingness and ability of judges to maintain virtuous disinterest in their work. (2) Some might explain their occasional failings as manifestations of the original sin inherited from Adam; (3) whatever their source, the proclivities of judges to indulge or celebrate themselves are perpetual temptations and judicial self-restraint is a perpetual challenge. As Cardozo explained: \"The great tides and currents which engulf the rest of men do not turn aside in their course and pass the judges by.\" (4) A primary and indispensable constraint on those who judge is the moral constraint imposed by the professional community to which they belong. The primary function of transparency in proceedings at trials and arguments, and of published decisions and opinions explicating judges' rulings, is to manifest their disinterest not only to the parties whose contentions they judge, but also to their lawyers, who share responsibility for imposing moral judgment on the professionalism of judges. (5) Judicial disinterest may have been made increasingly difficult in the twentieth century by the replacement of legal formalism with a legal realism that commissions judges to be less constrained by preexisting texts and more attentive to the social consequences of their judgments. (6) A secondary effect may be to inflate the collective vanity of the judiciary. The greater freedom judges assert in taking account of the social consequences of their decisions, the harder it may be for them to lay aside their personal political preferences, the related interests of their friends and allies, and the adoration or hostility of a public that either celebrates or attacks them, depending on the reaction to the policy consequences of their decisions. There is, to be sure, no empirical evidence of this effect, but it is reasonable to suspect that it occurs and contributes to public concerns about possible excesses of judicial independence. As judicial virtue has become more difficult to practice, it has become more in need. The present and rising mistrust of the American judiciary is not a direct consequence of the change in legal philosophy, but there is an obvious connection. As judges have increasingly and openly presumed to shape our polity, citizens who disagree with their politics have felt justified in mistrusting their disinterest and challenging their independence. (7) It is also increasingly difficult for citizen-lawyers performing their duty to judge the judges to maintain their own disinterest. One form of widely shared human weakness is that which inclines citizen-lawyers to link their respect and support of judges to their own preferences about the outcomes of the cases and political issues judges decide. But another is uncritical fidelity to the judiciary. A failure by the profession to criticize judicial misdeeds deprives judges of the sense of moral accountability to their peers that is sometimes needed to reinforce their capacity to know and restrain themselves. Judging judges wisely, like judging cases wisely, requires self-knowledge, self-discipline, and moral courage on the part of citizen-lawyers and their professional organizations. …","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2009-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Original Sin and Judicial Independence: Providing Accountability for Justices\",\"authors\":\"Paul D. Carrington, R. C. Cramton\",\"doi\":\"10.31228/osf.io/ut8je\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"TABLE OF CONTENTS I. A DEFINING CHALLENGE A. The Founding Vision 1. The Federalists' \\\"Ark of Safety\\\" B. Removing a Disabled Judge: The Pickering Case C. The Impeachment of Justice Chase: Are Justices Different? 1. How To Remove a Justice CONCLUSION I. A DEFINING CHALLENGE The independence of the judiciary is an enduring and defining objective of the legal profession. We lawyers, of all citizens, have the greatest stake in shielding judges from intimidation or reward. And that task of protecting judicial independence stands today at the very top of the agenda of the American legal profession. (1) The integrity of law and legal institutions requires more than just the protection of judges. It is equally dependent on the willingness and ability of judges to maintain virtuous disinterest in their work. (2) Some might explain their occasional failings as manifestations of the original sin inherited from Adam; (3) whatever their source, the proclivities of judges to indulge or celebrate themselves are perpetual temptations and judicial self-restraint is a perpetual challenge. As Cardozo explained: \\\"The great tides and currents which engulf the rest of men do not turn aside in their course and pass the judges by.\\\" (4) A primary and indispensable constraint on those who judge is the moral constraint imposed by the professional community to which they belong. The primary function of transparency in proceedings at trials and arguments, and of published decisions and opinions explicating judges' rulings, is to manifest their disinterest not only to the parties whose contentions they judge, but also to their lawyers, who share responsibility for imposing moral judgment on the professionalism of judges. (5) Judicial disinterest may have been made increasingly difficult in the twentieth century by the replacement of legal formalism with a legal realism that commissions judges to be less constrained by preexisting texts and more attentive to the social consequences of their judgments. (6) A secondary effect may be to inflate the collective vanity of the judiciary. The greater freedom judges assert in taking account of the social consequences of their decisions, the harder it may be for them to lay aside their personal political preferences, the related interests of their friends and allies, and the adoration or hostility of a public that either celebrates or attacks them, depending on the reaction to the policy consequences of their decisions. There is, to be sure, no empirical evidence of this effect, but it is reasonable to suspect that it occurs and contributes to public concerns about possible excesses of judicial independence. As judicial virtue has become more difficult to practice, it has become more in need. The present and rising mistrust of the American judiciary is not a direct consequence of the change in legal philosophy, but there is an obvious connection. As judges have increasingly and openly presumed to shape our polity, citizens who disagree with their politics have felt justified in mistrusting their disinterest and challenging their independence. (7) It is also increasingly difficult for citizen-lawyers performing their duty to judge the judges to maintain their own disinterest. One form of widely shared human weakness is that which inclines citizen-lawyers to link their respect and support of judges to their own preferences about the outcomes of the cases and political issues judges decide. But another is uncritical fidelity to the judiciary. A failure by the profession to criticize judicial misdeeds deprives judges of the sense of moral accountability to their peers that is sometimes needed to reinforce their capacity to know and restrain themselves. Judging judges wisely, like judging cases wisely, requires self-knowledge, self-discipline, and moral courage on the part of citizen-lawyers and their professional organizations. …\",\"PeriodicalId\":75324,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"William and Mary law review\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2009-03-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"William and Mary law review\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.31228/osf.io/ut8je\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"\",\"JCRName\":\"\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"William and Mary law review","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.31228/osf.io/ut8je","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

目录1.一个决定性的挑战A.创始愿景1。联邦党人的“安全方舟”b罢免残疾法官:皮克林案c弹劾法官蔡斯:法官不同吗?1. 司法独立是法律职业的一个持久和明确的目标。在所有公民中,保护法官不受恐吓或奖励对我们律师最为重要。今天,保护司法独立的任务是美国法律职业议程的重中之重。(1)法律和法律制度的健全需要的不仅仅是对法官的保护。这同样取决于法官是否有意愿和能力在工作中保持无私的美德。有些人可能会把他们偶尔的失败解释为从亚当那里继承来的原罪的表现;(3)无论其来源如何,法官放纵或自我陶醉的倾向是永恒的诱惑,司法自我约束是永恒的挑战。正如卡多佐所解释的那样:“吞没其他人的伟大潮流和潮流不会在他们的过程中转过身来,而忽略了法官。”(4)对法官的主要和必不可少的约束是他们所属的专业团体施加的道德约束。审判和辩论程序的透明度,以及公布的解释法官裁决的决定和意见的透明度,其主要功能是表明他们不仅对他们所评判的当事人不感兴趣,而且对他们的律师也不感兴趣,因为他们有责任对法官的专业精神进行道德判断。(5)在20世纪,由于法律形式主义被法律现实主义所取代,司法公正可能变得越来越困难,因为法律现实主义使法官较少受到先前存在的文本的约束,而更加注意其判决的社会后果。(6)第二个影响可能是使司法机构的集体虚荣心膨胀。法官在考虑其决定的社会后果时主张的自由越大,他们就越难以抛开个人的政治偏好、朋友和盟友的相关利益,以及公众对他们的崇拜或敌意(取决于对其决定的政策后果的反应)。当然,没有经验证据证明这种影响,但有理由怀疑它的发生,并助长了公众对司法独立可能过度的担忧。随着司法德性实践难度的加大,司法德性也变得更加需要。目前对美国司法机构日益增长的不信任并不是法律哲学变化的直接后果,但两者之间存在明显的联系。随着法官越来越公开地认为自己塑造了我们的政治,不同意他们政治立场的公民认为有理由不信任他们的冷漠,并挑战他们的独立性。(7)公民律师在履行审判法官的职责时,也越来越难以保持自己的无私。人类普遍存在的一种弱点是,公民律师倾向于将他们对法官的尊重和支持与他们自己对案件结果和法官决定的政治问题的偏好联系起来。但另一个是对司法不加批判的忠诚。如果这个职业不能批评司法上的不当行为,就会使法官丧失对同行的道德责任感,而这种责任感有时是加强他们了解和约束自己的能力所必需的。明智地审判法官,就像明智地审判案件一样,需要公民律师及其专业组织的自我认识、自律和道德勇气。…
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Original Sin and Judicial Independence: Providing Accountability for Justices
TABLE OF CONTENTS I. A DEFINING CHALLENGE A. The Founding Vision 1. The Federalists' "Ark of Safety" B. Removing a Disabled Judge: The Pickering Case C. The Impeachment of Justice Chase: Are Justices Different? 1. How To Remove a Justice CONCLUSION I. A DEFINING CHALLENGE The independence of the judiciary is an enduring and defining objective of the legal profession. We lawyers, of all citizens, have the greatest stake in shielding judges from intimidation or reward. And that task of protecting judicial independence stands today at the very top of the agenda of the American legal profession. (1) The integrity of law and legal institutions requires more than just the protection of judges. It is equally dependent on the willingness and ability of judges to maintain virtuous disinterest in their work. (2) Some might explain their occasional failings as manifestations of the original sin inherited from Adam; (3) whatever their source, the proclivities of judges to indulge or celebrate themselves are perpetual temptations and judicial self-restraint is a perpetual challenge. As Cardozo explained: "The great tides and currents which engulf the rest of men do not turn aside in their course and pass the judges by." (4) A primary and indispensable constraint on those who judge is the moral constraint imposed by the professional community to which they belong. The primary function of transparency in proceedings at trials and arguments, and of published decisions and opinions explicating judges' rulings, is to manifest their disinterest not only to the parties whose contentions they judge, but also to their lawyers, who share responsibility for imposing moral judgment on the professionalism of judges. (5) Judicial disinterest may have been made increasingly difficult in the twentieth century by the replacement of legal formalism with a legal realism that commissions judges to be less constrained by preexisting texts and more attentive to the social consequences of their judgments. (6) A secondary effect may be to inflate the collective vanity of the judiciary. The greater freedom judges assert in taking account of the social consequences of their decisions, the harder it may be for them to lay aside their personal political preferences, the related interests of their friends and allies, and the adoration or hostility of a public that either celebrates or attacks them, depending on the reaction to the policy consequences of their decisions. There is, to be sure, no empirical evidence of this effect, but it is reasonable to suspect that it occurs and contributes to public concerns about possible excesses of judicial independence. As judicial virtue has become more difficult to practice, it has become more in need. The present and rising mistrust of the American judiciary is not a direct consequence of the change in legal philosophy, but there is an obvious connection. As judges have increasingly and openly presumed to shape our polity, citizens who disagree with their politics have felt justified in mistrusting their disinterest and challenging their independence. (7) It is also increasingly difficult for citizen-lawyers performing their duty to judge the judges to maintain their own disinterest. One form of widely shared human weakness is that which inclines citizen-lawyers to link their respect and support of judges to their own preferences about the outcomes of the cases and political issues judges decide. But another is uncritical fidelity to the judiciary. A failure by the profession to criticize judicial misdeeds deprives judges of the sense of moral accountability to their peers that is sometimes needed to reinforce their capacity to know and restrain themselves. Judging judges wisely, like judging cases wisely, requires self-knowledge, self-discipline, and moral courage on the part of citizen-lawyers and their professional organizations. …
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
GENETIC DUTIES. Functional Corporate Knowledge THE GENETIC INFORMATION NONDISCRIMINATION ACT AT AGE 10: GINA'S CONTROVERSIAL ASSERTION THAT DATA TRANSPARENCY PROTECTS PRIVACY AND CIVIL RIGHTS. Prosecuting Poverty, Criminalizing Care Pereira's Aftershocks
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1