《酷刑:当不可思议的事在道德上是允许的

Q3 Arts and Humanities Parameters Pub Date : 2008-12-22 DOI:10.5860/choice.45-2875
M. Cook
{"title":"《酷刑:当不可思议的事在道德上是允许的","authors":"M. Cook","doi":"10.5860/choice.45-2875","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Torture: When the Unthinkable Is Morally Permissible. By Mirko Bagaric and Julie Clarke. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2007. 114 pages. $53.50 ($17.95 paper). This slim volume is essentially an extended commentary that builds on a controversial op-ed piece the authors published in the Australian newspapers The Age and The Sydney Morning Herald in May 2005. In that piece, the authors, both professors of law in Australia, argued \"the belief that torture is always wrong is ... misguided....It is this type of absolutist and shortsighted rhetoric that lies at the core of many distorted moral judgments....\" As the tone and placement of the original article would indicate, this book is more a work of strident advocacy than of cool and dispassionate analysis, although to be sure, it touches on all the relevant legal and philosophical issues that bear on the question. The authors begin by acknowledging the absolute legal prohibition on torture in international law and arguing that this restriction is precisely what should be changed. They argue for carving out a narrow exception that would allow a utilitarian calculus to permit torture in cases where lives are at risk, the potential harm of an attack is immediate, there are no other possible means of obtaining information within the time available, the person to be tortured has committed a significant level of wrongdoing, and there is high likelihood that he or she does possess relevant information that, if obtained, will prevent the loss of life. Bagaric and Clarke note that, despite the prohibitions on torture, it in fact is widely practiced around the world, even by nations that would most stridently condemn it publicly. In light of that reality, the authors argue, it would be better if torture were legalized (in the very narrow range of cases they have in mind). Further, having legalized it, they posit there should be a prior-review legal mechanism for issuing a \"torture warrant\" as a much preferable alternative to retrospective decisions regarding torture already committed. The short chapters that follow review the main counterarguments to the legalization proposal. The first is the \"slippery slope\" objection--allowing practice A, which might be morally acceptable, will eventually lead because of either logic or social acceptance to allowing practice B, which is clearly morally unacceptable. The consequence of a slippery slope argument is that one ought not, therefore, to allow A in the first place. Bagaric and Clarke reject this objection on the grounds that it is inherently speculative. The second objection is that acceptance of torture will lead to a general dehumanization of the society that practices it. This critique the authors dismiss on the grounds that it focuses too narrowly on one relationship---between torturer and tortured--to the neglect of the larger framework of affected parties that include the innocents to be saved as a result of information extracted through the use of torture. Discussion of this objection posits that torture is ineffective and the information so extracted is inherently unreliable. The authors claim to the contrary that for the very narrowly focused type of torture they have in mind--where the tortured person is believed to a high degree of certainty to possess specific and relevant information about a particular event--it is indeed effective. …","PeriodicalId":35242,"journal":{"name":"Parameters","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2008-12-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"18","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Torture: When the Unthinkable Is Morally Permissible\",\"authors\":\"M. Cook\",\"doi\":\"10.5860/choice.45-2875\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"Torture: When the Unthinkable Is Morally Permissible. By Mirko Bagaric and Julie Clarke. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2007. 114 pages. $53.50 ($17.95 paper). This slim volume is essentially an extended commentary that builds on a controversial op-ed piece the authors published in the Australian newspapers The Age and The Sydney Morning Herald in May 2005. In that piece, the authors, both professors of law in Australia, argued \\\"the belief that torture is always wrong is ... misguided....It is this type of absolutist and shortsighted rhetoric that lies at the core of many distorted moral judgments....\\\" As the tone and placement of the original article would indicate, this book is more a work of strident advocacy than of cool and dispassionate analysis, although to be sure, it touches on all the relevant legal and philosophical issues that bear on the question. The authors begin by acknowledging the absolute legal prohibition on torture in international law and arguing that this restriction is precisely what should be changed. They argue for carving out a narrow exception that would allow a utilitarian calculus to permit torture in cases where lives are at risk, the potential harm of an attack is immediate, there are no other possible means of obtaining information within the time available, the person to be tortured has committed a significant level of wrongdoing, and there is high likelihood that he or she does possess relevant information that, if obtained, will prevent the loss of life. Bagaric and Clarke note that, despite the prohibitions on torture, it in fact is widely practiced around the world, even by nations that would most stridently condemn it publicly. In light of that reality, the authors argue, it would be better if torture were legalized (in the very narrow range of cases they have in mind). Further, having legalized it, they posit there should be a prior-review legal mechanism for issuing a \\\"torture warrant\\\" as a much preferable alternative to retrospective decisions regarding torture already committed. The short chapters that follow review the main counterarguments to the legalization proposal. The first is the \\\"slippery slope\\\" objection--allowing practice A, which might be morally acceptable, will eventually lead because of either logic or social acceptance to allowing practice B, which is clearly morally unacceptable. The consequence of a slippery slope argument is that one ought not, therefore, to allow A in the first place. Bagaric and Clarke reject this objection on the grounds that it is inherently speculative. The second objection is that acceptance of torture will lead to a general dehumanization of the society that practices it. This critique the authors dismiss on the grounds that it focuses too narrowly on one relationship---between torturer and tortured--to the neglect of the larger framework of affected parties that include the innocents to be saved as a result of information extracted through the use of torture. Discussion of this objection posits that torture is ineffective and the information so extracted is inherently unreliable. The authors claim to the contrary that for the very narrowly focused type of torture they have in mind--where the tortured person is believed to a high degree of certainty to possess specific and relevant information about a particular event--it is indeed effective. …\",\"PeriodicalId\":35242,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Parameters\",\"volume\":null,\"pages\":null},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.0000,\"publicationDate\":\"2008-12-22\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"18\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Parameters\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.5860/choice.45-2875\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q3\",\"JCRName\":\"Arts and Humanities\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Parameters","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.5860/choice.45-2875","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"Arts and Humanities","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 18

摘要

《酷刑:当不可思议的事在道德上是允许的》米尔科·巴加里奇和朱莉·克拉克著。奥尔巴尼:纽约州立大学出版社,2007。114页。53.50美元(纸本17.95美元)。这本薄薄的书本质上是对作者2005年5月在澳大利亚报纸《时代报》和《悉尼先驱晨报》上发表的一篇有争议的专栏文章的扩展评论。在那篇文章中,两位作者都是澳大利亚的法学教授,他们认为“认为酷刑总是错误的观点……被误导的……正是这种专制主义和短视的言辞,构成了许多扭曲的道德判断的核心....”正如原文的语气和位置所表明的那样,这本书与其说是冷静冷静的分析,不如说是一部尖锐的主张,尽管可以肯定的是,它触及了与这个问题有关的所有相关法律和哲学问题。作者首先承认国际法中对酷刑的绝对法律禁止,并认为这种限制正是应该改变的。他们主张划出一个狭窄的例外允许功利主义的计算允许在生命受到威胁的情况下使用酷刑,攻击的潜在伤害是直接的,在可用的时间内没有其他可能的方法获得信息,被折磨的人犯了严重的错误,而且他或她很有可能确实掌握了相关信息,如果获得这些信息,将防止生命的损失。巴加里克和克拉克指出,尽管禁止酷刑,但事实上,酷刑在世界各地广泛存在,甚至在那些公开强烈谴责酷刑的国家也存在。鉴于这一现实,作者认为,如果酷刑合法化(在他们所考虑的非常狭窄的案例范围内)会更好。此外,在使酷刑合法化之后,他们认为应当有一种预先审查的法律机制来签发“酷刑逮捕证”,作为对已经实施的酷刑作出追溯性决定的更好选择。接下来的简短章节回顾了对合法化提议的主要反对意见。第一个是“滑坡”式的反对意见——允许可能在道德上可以接受的做法A,最终会因为逻辑或社会接受而导致允许显然在道德上不可接受的做法B。滑坡论证的结果是,因此,人们首先不应该允许a存在。巴加里克和克拉克拒绝了这一反对意见,理由是它本质上是推测性的。第二个反对意见是,接受酷刑会导致实施酷刑的社会普遍丧失人性。作者驳斥了这一批评,理由是它过于狭隘地关注一种关系——折磨者和被折磨者之间的关系——而忽视了受影响各方的更大框架,其中包括通过使用酷刑获取信息而被拯救的无辜者。对这一反对意见的讨论假设酷刑是无效的,这样提取的信息本质上是不可靠的。与此相反,作者声称,对于他们所考虑的非常狭隘的酷刑类型——即被酷刑者被认为高度肯定地掌握有关某一特定事件的具体和相关信息——它确实有效。…
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
Torture: When the Unthinkable Is Morally Permissible
Torture: When the Unthinkable Is Morally Permissible. By Mirko Bagaric and Julie Clarke. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2007. 114 pages. $53.50 ($17.95 paper). This slim volume is essentially an extended commentary that builds on a controversial op-ed piece the authors published in the Australian newspapers The Age and The Sydney Morning Herald in May 2005. In that piece, the authors, both professors of law in Australia, argued "the belief that torture is always wrong is ... misguided....It is this type of absolutist and shortsighted rhetoric that lies at the core of many distorted moral judgments...." As the tone and placement of the original article would indicate, this book is more a work of strident advocacy than of cool and dispassionate analysis, although to be sure, it touches on all the relevant legal and philosophical issues that bear on the question. The authors begin by acknowledging the absolute legal prohibition on torture in international law and arguing that this restriction is precisely what should be changed. They argue for carving out a narrow exception that would allow a utilitarian calculus to permit torture in cases where lives are at risk, the potential harm of an attack is immediate, there are no other possible means of obtaining information within the time available, the person to be tortured has committed a significant level of wrongdoing, and there is high likelihood that he or she does possess relevant information that, if obtained, will prevent the loss of life. Bagaric and Clarke note that, despite the prohibitions on torture, it in fact is widely practiced around the world, even by nations that would most stridently condemn it publicly. In light of that reality, the authors argue, it would be better if torture were legalized (in the very narrow range of cases they have in mind). Further, having legalized it, they posit there should be a prior-review legal mechanism for issuing a "torture warrant" as a much preferable alternative to retrospective decisions regarding torture already committed. The short chapters that follow review the main counterarguments to the legalization proposal. The first is the "slippery slope" objection--allowing practice A, which might be morally acceptable, will eventually lead because of either logic or social acceptance to allowing practice B, which is clearly morally unacceptable. The consequence of a slippery slope argument is that one ought not, therefore, to allow A in the first place. Bagaric and Clarke reject this objection on the grounds that it is inherently speculative. The second objection is that acceptance of torture will lead to a general dehumanization of the society that practices it. This critique the authors dismiss on the grounds that it focuses too narrowly on one relationship---between torturer and tortured--to the neglect of the larger framework of affected parties that include the innocents to be saved as a result of information extracted through the use of torture. Discussion of this objection posits that torture is ineffective and the information so extracted is inherently unreliable. The authors claim to the contrary that for the very narrowly focused type of torture they have in mind--where the tortured person is believed to a high degree of certainty to possess specific and relevant information about a particular event--it is indeed effective. …
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
Parameters
Parameters Social Sciences-Social Sciences (miscellaneous)
CiteScore
0.60
自引率
0.00%
发文量
55
期刊最新文献
Was the Russian Invasion of Ukraine a Failure of Western Deterrence? Contributor's Guidelines From the Editor in Chief Ukraine’s Lessons for Future Combat: Unmanned Aerial Systems and Deep Strike Parameters 2023-24 Winter Demi-Issue
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1