{"title":"非授权:事后分析","authors":"E. Posner, Adrian Vermeule","doi":"10.2307/1600576","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"In an earlier article, Interring the Nondelegation Doctrine,' we advanced the following account of the constitutional law bearing on delegation of federal legislative power. A statutory grant of authority to the executive branch or other agents can never amount to a delegation of legislative power. Agents acting within the terms of such a statutory grant are exercising executive power, not legislative power. The standard nondelegation doctrine, which holds that statutory grants of authority \"amount to\" or \"effect\" a delegation of legislative power if they are too broad or confer excessive discretion, is no more than a vague and ultimately uncashable metaphor. As it turns out, the standard nondelegation doctrine has no real pedigree in constitutional text and structure, in originalist understandings, or in judicial precedent; nor can plausible arguments from democratic theory or social welfare be marshaled to support it. Larry Alexander and Saikrishna Prakash have written a response that criticizes our account.2 (Although Alexander and Prakash criticize our view, they are noticeably ambivalent about the conventional doctrine.' As we shall see, their arguments commit them to defending a different, radically restrictive account of delegation, one in which any issuance of rules and regulations by the executive branch represents an unconstitutional exercise of legislative power.) Alexander and Prakash make three principal points. First, focusing on one implication of our account -that a delegation of legislative power would occur if federal legislators ceded their de jure legislative powers, such as voting rights, to nonlegislators-they say that our account \"elevates form over substance\" by permitting \"equivalent\" results to be produced","PeriodicalId":51436,"journal":{"name":"University of Chicago Law Review","volume":"8 1","pages":"1331-1344"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9000,"publicationDate":"2003-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"5","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Nondelegation: A Post-Mortem\",\"authors\":\"E. Posner, Adrian Vermeule\",\"doi\":\"10.2307/1600576\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"In an earlier article, Interring the Nondelegation Doctrine,' we advanced the following account of the constitutional law bearing on delegation of federal legislative power. A statutory grant of authority to the executive branch or other agents can never amount to a delegation of legislative power. Agents acting within the terms of such a statutory grant are exercising executive power, not legislative power. The standard nondelegation doctrine, which holds that statutory grants of authority \\\"amount to\\\" or \\\"effect\\\" a delegation of legislative power if they are too broad or confer excessive discretion, is no more than a vague and ultimately uncashable metaphor. As it turns out, the standard nondelegation doctrine has no real pedigree in constitutional text and structure, in originalist understandings, or in judicial precedent; nor can plausible arguments from democratic theory or social welfare be marshaled to support it. Larry Alexander and Saikrishna Prakash have written a response that criticizes our account.2 (Although Alexander and Prakash criticize our view, they are noticeably ambivalent about the conventional doctrine.' As we shall see, their arguments commit them to defending a different, radically restrictive account of delegation, one in which any issuance of rules and regulations by the executive branch represents an unconstitutional exercise of legislative power.) Alexander and Prakash make three principal points. First, focusing on one implication of our account -that a delegation of legislative power would occur if federal legislators ceded their de jure legislative powers, such as voting rights, to nonlegislators-they say that our account \\\"elevates form over substance\\\" by permitting \\\"equivalent\\\" results to be produced\",\"PeriodicalId\":51436,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"University of Chicago Law Review\",\"volume\":\"8 1\",\"pages\":\"1331-1344\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":1.9000,\"publicationDate\":\"2003-01-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"5\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"University of Chicago Law Review\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"90\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.2307/1600576\",\"RegionNum\":2,\"RegionCategory\":\"社会学\",\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"Q1\",\"JCRName\":\"LAW\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"University of Chicago Law Review","FirstCategoryId":"90","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2307/1600576","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"LAW","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
摘要
在之前的一篇文章《探究非授权主义》(Interring the Nondelegation Doctrine)中,我们对宪法对联邦立法权授权的影响提出了以下解释。对行政部门或其他代理人的法定授权绝不能等同于立法权的授权。在这种法定授权范围内行事的代理人行使的是行政权,而不是立法权。标准的非授权原则认为,如果法定授权过于宽泛或授予过多的自由裁量权,就“等于”或“实际上”是立法权的授权,这只不过是一个模糊的、最终无法兑现的隐喻。事实证明,标准的非授权原则在宪法文本和结构、原旨主义的理解或司法先例中都没有真正的渊源;也不能从民主理论或社会福利中找到合理的论据来支持它。Larry Alexander和Saikrishna Prakash写了一篇回应,批评了我们的说法(虽然亚历山大和普拉卡什批评了我们的观点,但他们明显对传统学说持矛盾态度。)正如我们将看到的那样,他们的论点使他们捍卫了一种不同的、从根本上限制授权的解释,在这种解释中,行政部门发布的任何规则和条例都代表了对立法权的违宪行使。亚历山大和普拉卡什提出了三个主要观点。首先,关注我们的解释的一个含义——如果联邦立法者将其法律上的立法权(如投票权)让与非立法者,就会出现立法权的委托——他们说我们的解释通过允许产生“等同”的结果而“将形式提升到实质之上”
In an earlier article, Interring the Nondelegation Doctrine,' we advanced the following account of the constitutional law bearing on delegation of federal legislative power. A statutory grant of authority to the executive branch or other agents can never amount to a delegation of legislative power. Agents acting within the terms of such a statutory grant are exercising executive power, not legislative power. The standard nondelegation doctrine, which holds that statutory grants of authority "amount to" or "effect" a delegation of legislative power if they are too broad or confer excessive discretion, is no more than a vague and ultimately uncashable metaphor. As it turns out, the standard nondelegation doctrine has no real pedigree in constitutional text and structure, in originalist understandings, or in judicial precedent; nor can plausible arguments from democratic theory or social welfare be marshaled to support it. Larry Alexander and Saikrishna Prakash have written a response that criticizes our account.2 (Although Alexander and Prakash criticize our view, they are noticeably ambivalent about the conventional doctrine.' As we shall see, their arguments commit them to defending a different, radically restrictive account of delegation, one in which any issuance of rules and regulations by the executive branch represents an unconstitutional exercise of legislative power.) Alexander and Prakash make three principal points. First, focusing on one implication of our account -that a delegation of legislative power would occur if federal legislators ceded their de jure legislative powers, such as voting rights, to nonlegislators-they say that our account "elevates form over substance" by permitting "equivalent" results to be produced
期刊介绍:
The University of Chicago Law Review is a quarterly journal of legal scholarship. Often cited in Supreme Court and other court opinions, as well as in other scholarly works, it is among the most influential journals in the field. Students have full responsibility for editing and publishing the Law Review; they also contribute original scholarship of their own. The Law Review"s editorial board selects all pieces for publication and, with the assistance of staff members, performs substantive and technical edits on each of these pieces prior to publication.