On the elusiveness of higher-order risk attitudes.

IF 3.3 2区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS Journal of Medical Ethics Pub Date : 2023-11-01 Epub Date: 2023-08-09 DOI:10.1136/jme-2023-109331
Jasper Debrabander
{"title":"On the elusiveness of higher-order risk attitudes.","authors":"Jasper Debrabander","doi":"10.1136/jme-2023-109331","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Makins formulates a deference principle which states that patients’ attitudes towards the health outcomes associated with different treatment options should drive decisionmaking and not physicians’ attitudes towards these health outcomes. Although this deference principle is widely agreed on, it is less obvious which role patients’ risk attitudes should play. Makins takes patients’ attitudes towards health outcomes to be sufficiently analogous to patients’ risk attitudes in order to extend his deference principle. His extended deference principle states that patients’ attitudes towards the health outcomes and risks associated with different treatment options should drive decisionmaking and not physicians’ attitudes towards these health outcomes and risks. This extension is not only taken to be ethically preferable, but also practically realisable as one can reliably trace patients’ (risk) attitudes. Problematic situations arise when patients exhibit risk attitudes they do not reflexively endorse. For instance, patients might systematically make more risky choices than they think they should make. In response to these kinds of situations, Makins proposes to revise his deference principle. His revised deference principle states that patients’ reflexively endorsed attitudes towards the health outcomes and risks associated with different treatment options should drive decisionmaking and not physicians’ reflexively endorsed attitudes towards these health outcomes and risks. That is, only the (risk) attitudes that are endorsed by patients’ higherorder (risk) attitudes should drive decisionmaking. This view is reminiscent of what are often called ‘Frankfurtian’ accounts of authenticity even if Frankfurt himself did not explicitly discuss authenticity. 3 Makins, however, does not discuss the literature that is critical towards these Frankfurtian accounts of authenticity while formulating his revised deference principle. The main theoretical problem Frankfurtian accounts of authenticity face is the following. Firstorder attitudes are authentic if and only if they are reflexively endorsed by secondorder attitudes. However, the question can be raised whether these secondorder attitudes need to be authentic as well. If secondorder attitudes need not be authentic, then what Christman (p7) calls the ‘ab initio problem’ arises. For if secondorder attitudes need not be endorsed by higherorder attitudes in order to be authentic, why does authenticity require firstorder attitudes to be endorsed by secondorder attitudes in the first place? If secondorder attitudes need to be authentic in order for them to be able to convey authenticity on firstorder attitudes, a regression looms. For the authenticity of secondorder attitudes can only be established by thirdorder attitudes, etc. Frankfurt 3 tried to stop this regression nonarbitrarily by stating that a decisive identification could end it. We do not need to decide here whether Frankfurt successfully avoided the regression as practical problems remain regardless of its success. For as Jesper Marceta points out, no reliable methods exist to empirically trace patients’ higherorder attitudes nor to establish whether patients’ firstorder attitudes are properly endorsed by these higherorder attitudes. So although it seemed possible to determine whether the conditions of the extended deference principle were fulfilled by tracing patients’ (risk) attitudes, it seems to be practically impossible to determine whether the conditions of the revised deference principle are fulfilled as one cannot reliably determine whether these (risk) attitudes have been endorsed by higherorder (risk) attitudes. In order to circumvent these problems, one might consider other accounts of authenticity. Marceta develops a taxonomy of accounts of authenticity that consists of three categories. The first are sanctionist—or Frankfurtian—accounts of authenticity. The second are coherentist accounts of authenticity. In order for an attitude to be authentic, a coherentist theory of authenticity would require that this attitude coheres with the other attitudes of that person. The third are originist accounts of authenticity. An attitude is authentic, according to originist accounts of authenticity, if it came about under appropriate, for example, nonconstraining circumstances. Although I cannot engage with the theoretical merits of each of these accounts of authenticity here, it seems to be sheer impossible, practically speaking, to operationalise any of them. For it is very difficult to determine which attitudes characterise a person, let alone to judge whether a particular attitude coheres with these attitudes. And it seems equally difficult to reconstruct the circumstances under which patients formed their attitudes and judge whether they substantially impaired the process of attitude formation. To conclude, although I agree with Makins that his deference principle should be extended to include patients’ risk attitudes, his revised deference principle is literally of no use. For there seems to be no way to differentiate reliably between (risk) attitudes that have been endorsed by higherorder (risk) attitudes and those that have not. More generally, it seems to be practically impossible to operationalise any account of authenticity. By consequence, the revised deference principle cannot be saved by plugging in another account of authenticity. Therefore, Makins might have to bite the bullet and accept that every now and then a patient’s seemingly inauthentic (risk) attitudes will drive decisionmaking.","PeriodicalId":16317,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Medical Ethics","volume":" ","pages":"748"},"PeriodicalIF":3.3000,"publicationDate":"2023-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"1","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Medical Ethics","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1136/jme-2023-109331","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"2023/8/9 0:00:00","PubModel":"Epub","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1

Abstract

Makins formulates a deference principle which states that patients’ attitudes towards the health outcomes associated with different treatment options should drive decisionmaking and not physicians’ attitudes towards these health outcomes. Although this deference principle is widely agreed on, it is less obvious which role patients’ risk attitudes should play. Makins takes patients’ attitudes towards health outcomes to be sufficiently analogous to patients’ risk attitudes in order to extend his deference principle. His extended deference principle states that patients’ attitudes towards the health outcomes and risks associated with different treatment options should drive decisionmaking and not physicians’ attitudes towards these health outcomes and risks. This extension is not only taken to be ethically preferable, but also practically realisable as one can reliably trace patients’ (risk) attitudes. Problematic situations arise when patients exhibit risk attitudes they do not reflexively endorse. For instance, patients might systematically make more risky choices than they think they should make. In response to these kinds of situations, Makins proposes to revise his deference principle. His revised deference principle states that patients’ reflexively endorsed attitudes towards the health outcomes and risks associated with different treatment options should drive decisionmaking and not physicians’ reflexively endorsed attitudes towards these health outcomes and risks. That is, only the (risk) attitudes that are endorsed by patients’ higherorder (risk) attitudes should drive decisionmaking. This view is reminiscent of what are often called ‘Frankfurtian’ accounts of authenticity even if Frankfurt himself did not explicitly discuss authenticity. 3 Makins, however, does not discuss the literature that is critical towards these Frankfurtian accounts of authenticity while formulating his revised deference principle. The main theoretical problem Frankfurtian accounts of authenticity face is the following. Firstorder attitudes are authentic if and only if they are reflexively endorsed by secondorder attitudes. However, the question can be raised whether these secondorder attitudes need to be authentic as well. If secondorder attitudes need not be authentic, then what Christman (p7) calls the ‘ab initio problem’ arises. For if secondorder attitudes need not be endorsed by higherorder attitudes in order to be authentic, why does authenticity require firstorder attitudes to be endorsed by secondorder attitudes in the first place? If secondorder attitudes need to be authentic in order for them to be able to convey authenticity on firstorder attitudes, a regression looms. For the authenticity of secondorder attitudes can only be established by thirdorder attitudes, etc. Frankfurt 3 tried to stop this regression nonarbitrarily by stating that a decisive identification could end it. We do not need to decide here whether Frankfurt successfully avoided the regression as practical problems remain regardless of its success. For as Jesper Marceta points out, no reliable methods exist to empirically trace patients’ higherorder attitudes nor to establish whether patients’ firstorder attitudes are properly endorsed by these higherorder attitudes. So although it seemed possible to determine whether the conditions of the extended deference principle were fulfilled by tracing patients’ (risk) attitudes, it seems to be practically impossible to determine whether the conditions of the revised deference principle are fulfilled as one cannot reliably determine whether these (risk) attitudes have been endorsed by higherorder (risk) attitudes. In order to circumvent these problems, one might consider other accounts of authenticity. Marceta develops a taxonomy of accounts of authenticity that consists of three categories. The first are sanctionist—or Frankfurtian—accounts of authenticity. The second are coherentist accounts of authenticity. In order for an attitude to be authentic, a coherentist theory of authenticity would require that this attitude coheres with the other attitudes of that person. The third are originist accounts of authenticity. An attitude is authentic, according to originist accounts of authenticity, if it came about under appropriate, for example, nonconstraining circumstances. Although I cannot engage with the theoretical merits of each of these accounts of authenticity here, it seems to be sheer impossible, practically speaking, to operationalise any of them. For it is very difficult to determine which attitudes characterise a person, let alone to judge whether a particular attitude coheres with these attitudes. And it seems equally difficult to reconstruct the circumstances under which patients formed their attitudes and judge whether they substantially impaired the process of attitude formation. To conclude, although I agree with Makins that his deference principle should be extended to include patients’ risk attitudes, his revised deference principle is literally of no use. For there seems to be no way to differentiate reliably between (risk) attitudes that have been endorsed by higherorder (risk) attitudes and those that have not. More generally, it seems to be practically impossible to operationalise any account of authenticity. By consequence, the revised deference principle cannot be saved by plugging in another account of authenticity. Therefore, Makins might have to bite the bullet and accept that every now and then a patient’s seemingly inauthentic (risk) attitudes will drive decisionmaking.
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
关于高阶风险态度的难以捉摸。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
Journal of Medical Ethics
Journal of Medical Ethics 医学-医学:伦理
CiteScore
7.80
自引率
9.80%
发文量
164
审稿时长
4-8 weeks
期刊介绍: Journal of Medical Ethics is a leading international journal that reflects the whole field of medical ethics. The journal seeks to promote ethical reflection and conduct in scientific research and medical practice. It features articles on various ethical aspects of health care relevant to health care professionals, members of clinical ethics committees, medical ethics professionals, researchers and bioscientists, policy makers and patients. Subscribers to the Journal of Medical Ethics also receive Medical Humanities journal at no extra cost. JME is the official journal of the Institute of Medical Ethics.
期刊最新文献
Strengthening harm-theoretic pro-life views. Wish to die trying to live: unwise or incapacitous? The case of University Hospitals Birmingham NHS Foundation Trust versus 'ST'. Pregnant women are often not listened to, but pathologising pregnancy isn't the solution. How ectogestation can impact the gestational versus moral parenthood debate. If not a right to children because of gestation, then not a duty towards them either.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1