Iconoclastic Images

Gregory Schufreider
{"title":"Iconoclastic Images","authors":"Gregory Schufreider","doi":"10.1353/cgl.2010.0005","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"painting). Palace its modern figure has been established. Virtually every painting in the Palatine Gallery is a rectangle. By the time we get back on the bus, even a tourist in the field of art history like me cannot fail to be struck by the question: What determined this modern figure of painting as the historical shape that has dominated it until the present day?8 We know that painting created the modern picture plane by stretching linen over a wooden frame, no longer working on the more sculptural wooden panel but, instead, on the flat surface of a lightweight material, creating portable paintings that, while still attached to the wall, were free to move from one wall to another. Not only was the compositional structure of linear perspective enhanced by the rectangular framework of modern painting (as is clear in Alberti’s visual pyramid) but its own three-dimensionality was kept out of the picture by a second frame: a “picture frame” that is designed to conceal the edge of the material apparatus that is the new (and true) “frame” of painting, namely, the stretcher.9 The aim is to create the appearance of the picture plane as a two-dimensional surface whose flatness is retained by maintaining the tension of the canvas through an adjustable framework whose material outline is effaced by the picture frame. It is on this virtual plane that painting will be free to claim its birth right as a visual art. To do so, however, requires the operation of a double frame in which the edge of the apparatus that creates the picture plane is concealed by the edge of the rabbet frame, such that the painting is free to create a limit that would appear to be set by the picture plane itself, not imposed upon it from the outside as a boundary. At the same time, its material structure will raise the question of the nature of painting in its modern condition: the metaphysical question of its existence as an autonomous creation in so far as painting is free to project a visual space of its own on the picture plane. As Hegel would see, this threedimensional virtual space is not simply a matter of drawing, but operates as IconoclastIc Images 29 a kind of apparition (Schein) or what we would like to think of as a spectral image, and not just (as it was for him) in the “magic” that takes place in oil painting in its “pure appearance” as a chromatic creation (“coloration”).10 Not only was the compositional structure of linear perspective enhanced by the rectangle in the creation of the virtual space of the picture plane, but the real three-dimensionality of the painting was kept out of the picture by a second frame that was designed to present the picture plane as a two-dimensional surface without an outline that would define it as a material form. In this respect, a spectral rectangle was created, and one that was designed to provide a format that saved the painting itself from operating as a “plastic” image. Instead, strictly “visual” images would take place on the picture plane, while the painting will present itself as a figure that does not have a concrete shape, ironically, thanks to the material structure of its new framework. In effect, painting will recreate itself as a modern art by seeking recognition of its absolute right to the virtual realm of the picture plane as a visual space that is proper to it, claiming the right to rule this metaphysical plane as its sovereign domain. In that case, we would trace the modern attraction to the rectangle in painting to a certain reversal of fortunes in the Renaissance, as its rebirth in the “form” of the picture plane or, indeed, its breech birth. For a topological transformation occurred in the breach between the medieval and the modern period, when painting sought its justification, not in its service to theology but in a representational painting that prides itself on its accuracy as an optical science.11 To appreciate how this conversion works, we would stress the character of the rectangle—or lack thereof—as a neutral form: a spectral figure that is designed to neutralize the material shape of painting through the standardization of a format that effectively becomes pro forma and, as such, (dis)appears as a pure formality. Suffice it to say that the modern spectator no longer desires a painting that assumes a physical form but would prefer a picture plane that aspires to become a formless figure, described by the twodimensional surface of a flat plane that conceals its real three-dimensionality behind a rabbet frame. “Spatial” forms now occur in the painting as a threedimensional virtual space created on the picture plane, thanks, in part, to a sculptural drawing. The painting itself, however, no longer has a concrete shape or, for that matter, appears to take place in a real space or time. Instead, in the form(at) of a spectral figure, the pictorial image operates as a specter or, indeed, a speculum of our visual field: a mirror as well as a compendium, 10 See Hegel’s Aesthetics, vol. II (trans. T.M. Knox, Oxford University Press, 1979) 797ff. We may speak of a “specter” here even though we know that, technically speaking, Hegel has a “tonal” and not a “spectral” account of color. 11 As Leonardo famously argued in his Paragone (translated by Claire J. Farago, E.J. Brill, 1992). 30 The Yearbook of Comparative Literature, Vol. 56 12 Norman Bryson has detailed certain aspects of this operation in the development of linear perspective in his Vision and Painting: The Logic of the Gaze (Yale University Press, 1986). 13 While standing on the steps of Santa Maria de Fiore (or, to be precise, in its central portal) and facing the Baptistery, Brunelleschi’s contraption presents the viewer with a painting of the latter which is seen through its image in a mirror. By peering through a hole that has been drilled in the painting, which is viewed from the backside of the picture plane, the viewer sees the painted image in a mirror, such that the mirror image can be compared to the actual Baptistery, confirming their visual identity in a verisimilitude whose linear perspective is enhanced, if not magnified, by viewing the image (painted in geometrical perspective) in a mirror. In peeking through a (single) keyhole from the backside of the picture plane, the eye is isolated from the other senses (not to mention from the other eye), while the body is placed, if not entirely out of commission, then literally backstage, as it is upstaged by a virtual displacement: not just placed behind the scene but, as such, displaced from the space in which the painted image is taking place. whose physical shape does not have a well-defined outline but may be said to represent the open form of the spectator’s field of vision. In this respect, the double frame is designed to erase the material outline of the picture plane in order to create a virtual opening without a clear-cut boundary, in an aesthetic speculation in which the limit will appear to be strictly visual: set by vision itself, not imposed from the outside. As such, a virtual autonomy reigns in the self-determination of a visual domain in which painting would appear to be free to set the rules in the creation of a space that is entirely its own. To accomplish this convincingly, the eye must not only be segregated from the other senses but must be separated from the body, if painting is to be rendered as a strictly visual art.12 An optical epoché must take place in the initiation of a visual epoch in which painting will become the model for an aesthetic experience that is not kinesthetic. There is, perhaps, no more telling indication of this than Brunelleschi’s famous demonstration on the steps of a cathedral in Florence, which effects the isolation of the eye from the body, by embodying it in an apparatus that is designed to demonstrate a complex visualization that takes place in the invention, or as Edgerton insists, the “rediscovery” of linear perspective in modern painting. For Brunelleschi’s set-up is designed to make a display of vision itself in an optical array that is framed through a rather complicated operation in the creation of a double image.13 In looking through what turns out to be a metaphysical apparatus, what we see is the visualization of reality in the virtual image: not just the virtual image that is created in a three-dimensional projection on the picture plane, but in so far as what is assumed to be the first painting in the Renaissance to be painted in geometrical perspective is viewed through its virtual image in a mirror. In this respect, the space of modern painting is reflected in an image whose virtuality is doubled in so far as the painted image appears in its image in a mirror. At the same time, not only has the painting become a virtual image—and not just in its pictorial representation, but in so far as it IconoclastIc Images 31 has been reduced to its visual dimension when viewed in a mirror—but the reality that it represents is similarly “visualized” when the mirror is lowered and the painted image of the Baptistery is compared to the reality that the viewer now can see. For Brunelleschi’s aim is to assert a claim to truth when he inserts the picture plane into an apparatus that is designed to create a specific visual outlook in which the painting operates (albeit from behind) as a kind of viewfinder that directs the viewer to focus on the structure of reality as a visual event, however illusory the virtual image may appear to be. In its modern operation, the true image is no longer thought, as it was in the Middle Ages, to be the “perfect likeness” of reality, appearing in the flesh of a physical Incarnation.14 Instead, as Hegel will insist, painting is a perfect illusion—like a magic trick—that, he claims, has reached its apex (and, therefore, its end) in the chromatic rendering of human skin (“carnation”) as a sign of subjectivity, and not in a duplication, or even as a representation of reality, but as a free cr","PeriodicalId":342699,"journal":{"name":"The Yearbook of Comparative Literature","volume":"23 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2012-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"The Yearbook of Comparative Literature","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1353/cgl.2010.0005","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

painting). Palace its modern figure has been established. Virtually every painting in the Palatine Gallery is a rectangle. By the time we get back on the bus, even a tourist in the field of art history like me cannot fail to be struck by the question: What determined this modern figure of painting as the historical shape that has dominated it until the present day?8 We know that painting created the modern picture plane by stretching linen over a wooden frame, no longer working on the more sculptural wooden panel but, instead, on the flat surface of a lightweight material, creating portable paintings that, while still attached to the wall, were free to move from one wall to another. Not only was the compositional structure of linear perspective enhanced by the rectangular framework of modern painting (as is clear in Alberti’s visual pyramid) but its own three-dimensionality was kept out of the picture by a second frame: a “picture frame” that is designed to conceal the edge of the material apparatus that is the new (and true) “frame” of painting, namely, the stretcher.9 The aim is to create the appearance of the picture plane as a two-dimensional surface whose flatness is retained by maintaining the tension of the canvas through an adjustable framework whose material outline is effaced by the picture frame. It is on this virtual plane that painting will be free to claim its birth right as a visual art. To do so, however, requires the operation of a double frame in which the edge of the apparatus that creates the picture plane is concealed by the edge of the rabbet frame, such that the painting is free to create a limit that would appear to be set by the picture plane itself, not imposed upon it from the outside as a boundary. At the same time, its material structure will raise the question of the nature of painting in its modern condition: the metaphysical question of its existence as an autonomous creation in so far as painting is free to project a visual space of its own on the picture plane. As Hegel would see, this threedimensional virtual space is not simply a matter of drawing, but operates as IconoclastIc Images 29 a kind of apparition (Schein) or what we would like to think of as a spectral image, and not just (as it was for him) in the “magic” that takes place in oil painting in its “pure appearance” as a chromatic creation (“coloration”).10 Not only was the compositional structure of linear perspective enhanced by the rectangle in the creation of the virtual space of the picture plane, but the real three-dimensionality of the painting was kept out of the picture by a second frame that was designed to present the picture plane as a two-dimensional surface without an outline that would define it as a material form. In this respect, a spectral rectangle was created, and one that was designed to provide a format that saved the painting itself from operating as a “plastic” image. Instead, strictly “visual” images would take place on the picture plane, while the painting will present itself as a figure that does not have a concrete shape, ironically, thanks to the material structure of its new framework. In effect, painting will recreate itself as a modern art by seeking recognition of its absolute right to the virtual realm of the picture plane as a visual space that is proper to it, claiming the right to rule this metaphysical plane as its sovereign domain. In that case, we would trace the modern attraction to the rectangle in painting to a certain reversal of fortunes in the Renaissance, as its rebirth in the “form” of the picture plane or, indeed, its breech birth. For a topological transformation occurred in the breach between the medieval and the modern period, when painting sought its justification, not in its service to theology but in a representational painting that prides itself on its accuracy as an optical science.11 To appreciate how this conversion works, we would stress the character of the rectangle—or lack thereof—as a neutral form: a spectral figure that is designed to neutralize the material shape of painting through the standardization of a format that effectively becomes pro forma and, as such, (dis)appears as a pure formality. Suffice it to say that the modern spectator no longer desires a painting that assumes a physical form but would prefer a picture plane that aspires to become a formless figure, described by the twodimensional surface of a flat plane that conceals its real three-dimensionality behind a rabbet frame. “Spatial” forms now occur in the painting as a threedimensional virtual space created on the picture plane, thanks, in part, to a sculptural drawing. The painting itself, however, no longer has a concrete shape or, for that matter, appears to take place in a real space or time. Instead, in the form(at) of a spectral figure, the pictorial image operates as a specter or, indeed, a speculum of our visual field: a mirror as well as a compendium, 10 See Hegel’s Aesthetics, vol. II (trans. T.M. Knox, Oxford University Press, 1979) 797ff. We may speak of a “specter” here even though we know that, technically speaking, Hegel has a “tonal” and not a “spectral” account of color. 11 As Leonardo famously argued in his Paragone (translated by Claire J. Farago, E.J. Brill, 1992). 30 The Yearbook of Comparative Literature, Vol. 56 12 Norman Bryson has detailed certain aspects of this operation in the development of linear perspective in his Vision and Painting: The Logic of the Gaze (Yale University Press, 1986). 13 While standing on the steps of Santa Maria de Fiore (or, to be precise, in its central portal) and facing the Baptistery, Brunelleschi’s contraption presents the viewer with a painting of the latter which is seen through its image in a mirror. By peering through a hole that has been drilled in the painting, which is viewed from the backside of the picture plane, the viewer sees the painted image in a mirror, such that the mirror image can be compared to the actual Baptistery, confirming their visual identity in a verisimilitude whose linear perspective is enhanced, if not magnified, by viewing the image (painted in geometrical perspective) in a mirror. In peeking through a (single) keyhole from the backside of the picture plane, the eye is isolated from the other senses (not to mention from the other eye), while the body is placed, if not entirely out of commission, then literally backstage, as it is upstaged by a virtual displacement: not just placed behind the scene but, as such, displaced from the space in which the painted image is taking place. whose physical shape does not have a well-defined outline but may be said to represent the open form of the spectator’s field of vision. In this respect, the double frame is designed to erase the material outline of the picture plane in order to create a virtual opening without a clear-cut boundary, in an aesthetic speculation in which the limit will appear to be strictly visual: set by vision itself, not imposed from the outside. As such, a virtual autonomy reigns in the self-determination of a visual domain in which painting would appear to be free to set the rules in the creation of a space that is entirely its own. To accomplish this convincingly, the eye must not only be segregated from the other senses but must be separated from the body, if painting is to be rendered as a strictly visual art.12 An optical epoché must take place in the initiation of a visual epoch in which painting will become the model for an aesthetic experience that is not kinesthetic. There is, perhaps, no more telling indication of this than Brunelleschi’s famous demonstration on the steps of a cathedral in Florence, which effects the isolation of the eye from the body, by embodying it in an apparatus that is designed to demonstrate a complex visualization that takes place in the invention, or as Edgerton insists, the “rediscovery” of linear perspective in modern painting. For Brunelleschi’s set-up is designed to make a display of vision itself in an optical array that is framed through a rather complicated operation in the creation of a double image.13 In looking through what turns out to be a metaphysical apparatus, what we see is the visualization of reality in the virtual image: not just the virtual image that is created in a three-dimensional projection on the picture plane, but in so far as what is assumed to be the first painting in the Renaissance to be painted in geometrical perspective is viewed through its virtual image in a mirror. In this respect, the space of modern painting is reflected in an image whose virtuality is doubled in so far as the painted image appears in its image in a mirror. At the same time, not only has the painting become a virtual image—and not just in its pictorial representation, but in so far as it IconoclastIc Images 31 has been reduced to its visual dimension when viewed in a mirror—but the reality that it represents is similarly “visualized” when the mirror is lowered and the painted image of the Baptistery is compared to the reality that the viewer now can see. For Brunelleschi’s aim is to assert a claim to truth when he inserts the picture plane into an apparatus that is designed to create a specific visual outlook in which the painting operates (albeit from behind) as a kind of viewfinder that directs the viewer to focus on the structure of reality as a visual event, however illusory the virtual image may appear to be. In its modern operation, the true image is no longer thought, as it was in the Middle Ages, to be the “perfect likeness” of reality, appearing in the flesh of a physical Incarnation.14 Instead, as Hegel will insist, painting is a perfect illusion—like a magic trick—that, he claims, has reached its apex (and, therefore, its end) in the chromatic rendering of human skin (“carnation”) as a sign of subjectivity, and not in a duplication, or even as a representation of reality, but as a free cr
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
绘画)。宫殿的现代形象已经确立。实际上,帕拉廷画廊里的每一幅画都是长方形的。当我们回到车上的时候,即使是像我这样一个艺术史领域的游客也不会不被这个问题所打动:是什么决定了这个现代绘画人物的历史形态,直到今天仍然占据主导地位?我们知道,绘画是通过在木框架上拉伸亚麻布来创造现代画面平面的,不再是在更具雕塑感的木板上工作,而是在一种轻质材料的平面上工作,创造出可移动的画作,这些画作仍然附着在墙上,可以自由地从一面墙移动到另一面墙。现代绘画的矩形框架不仅增强了线性透视的构图结构(正如阿尔伯蒂的视觉金字塔所清楚显示的那样),而且它自己的三维性也被第二个框架挡在了画面之外:这个“画框”被设计用来掩盖作为绘画的新(和真正的)“框架”的材料装置的边缘,即担架其目的是创造一个二维平面的外观,通过一个可调节的框架来保持画布的张力,其材料轮廓被画框抹去,从而保持平面的平整度。正是在这个虚拟的层面上,绘画将自由地主张其作为视觉艺术的诞生权。然而,要做到这一点,需要操作一个双画框,在这个双画框中,创造画面的装置的边缘被画框的边缘所掩盖,这样,绘画就可以自由地创造一个界限,这个界限似乎是由画面本身设定的,而不是从外部强加给它作为边界。同时,它的物质结构也提出了绘画在现代状态下的本质问题:绘画作为一种自主创作而存在的形而上学问题,因为绘画可以在画面平面上自由地投射出自己的视觉空间。正如黑格尔所看到的,这个三维的虚拟空间不仅仅是一个绘画的问题,而是作为一种幽灵(沙因)或我们想要想象的光谱图像来运作,而不仅仅是(对他来说)在油画中发生的“魔力”,在它的“纯粹外观”中,作为一种彩色创作(“着色”)在创造画面平面的虚拟空间时,矩形不仅增强了线性透视的构图结构,而且第二帧的设计将画面平面呈现为二维表面,而没有将其定义为物质形式的轮廓,从而使绘画的真正三维性被排除在画面之外。在这方面,创建了一个光谱矩形,一个旨在提供一种格式,使绘画本身免于作为“塑料”图像操作。相反,严格的“视觉”图像将发生在画面平面上,而具有讽刺意味的是,由于其新框架的物质结构,绘画将呈现为一个没有具体形状的人物。实际上,绘画将通过寻求承认其对画面平面的虚拟领域的绝对权利,作为一个适合它的视觉空间,重新创造自己作为一种现代艺术,声称有权统治这个形而上的平面作为它的主权领域。在这种情况下,我们可以将现代绘画中对矩形的吸引力追溯到文艺复兴时期命运的某种逆转,因为它以画面平面的“形式”重生,或者确切地说,它的臀部诞生。因为在中世纪和现代之间的决裂中发生了一种拓扑学上的转变,当绘画寻求其正当性时,它不是在为神学服务,而是在一种表现主义绘画中,这种绘画以其作为一门光学科学的准确性而自豪为了理解这种转换是如何工作的,我们将强调矩形的特征——或缺乏矩形——作为一种中性形式:一个光谱图形,旨在通过一种格式的标准化来中和绘画的物质形状,这种格式有效地成为形式,因此,(dis)看起来像一种纯粹的形式。我只想说,现代观众不再渴望一幅具有物理形式的画作,而是更喜欢一幅渴望成为无形人物的画面,用平面的二维表面来描述,而平面的三维面隐藏在一个兔子框后面。“空间”形式现在出现在绘画中,作为在画面平面上创建的三维虚拟空间,部分归功于雕塑绘画。然而,绘画本身不再具有具体的形状,或者就此而言,似乎发生在真实的空间或时间中。 相反,正如黑格尔所坚持的那样,绘画是一种完美的幻觉——就像一种魔术——他声称,在人类皮肤(“康乃馨”)的彩色渲染中达到了它的顶点(因此,它的终结),作为主体性的标志,而不是复制,甚至不是作为现实的表现,而是作为一种自由的cr
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
“A Stratagem for Self-Oblivion”: Rosselli, Real Talk, and the Abolition of the “I” Foreign Poems Damage and Repair in Environmental Assessment A Seafloor for the Disaster Receding Margins: Black Rice and the Rhythms of Tidal Transfer
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1