Deconstructing “Grown versus Made”: A Derridean Perspective on Cloning

Kelly Oliver
{"title":"Deconstructing “Grown versus Made”: A Derridean Perspective on Cloning","authors":"Kelly Oliver","doi":"10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171615","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Most philosophers discussing genetic engineering, including cloning, assume the \"grown versus made\" opposition. Therefore, their stance on the ethics of both revolves around whether they privilege one side of this binary over the other. Part and parcel of the \"grown versus made\" opposition is the liberal notion of freedom of choice also assumed in these discussions. Most philosophers engaged in debates over genetic engineering and cloning begin with some version of a liberal sovereign individual who has freedom of choice that must be protected, whether we are talking about the parents' freedom (or lack thereof) in considering genetic engineering and embryo selection, or the future persons' freedom (or lack thereof) resulting from such a process. The central question in these debates is whose freedom is most important and thus who gets to exercise their free choice, and why. Although they have different answers to this question--John Harris opts for protecting parents' rights to choose, Jurgen Habermas for protecting the rights of future persons, and some feminists for guaranteeing women's rights to reproductive choice, all of them assume a sovereign individual operating either within a social situation that also makes them interdependent, or on an abstract level preferred by some philosophers to avoid the mess of the real world in favor of moral purity. (1) In this essay, I consider what happens to debates over genetic enhancement when we \"deconstruct\" the opposition between \"grown and made\" and the notion of freedom of choice that comes with it. Along with the binary grown and made comes other such oppositions at the center of these debates: chance and choice, accident and deliberation, nature and culture. By deconstructing the oppositions between grown versus made (chance versus choice, or accident versus deliberate), and free versus determined, alternative routes through these bioethical thickets start to emerge. On both sides of debates over genetic engineering and cloning, we see that philosophers assume a sovereign liberal notion of the individual who is free to choose, who can make decisions, and control the future. For philosophers like John Harris this is a good thing while for Jurgen Habermas and others it is not. Habermas imagines that genetic enhancement would make us masters of our destiny in such a way as to undermine the contingencies that make us free. (2) Yet, for Habermas, it is the authorship of one's own life and the ownership of one's own body that results in human agency, an authorship and ownership already at odds with the contigency he privileges. If we refuse the sovereign author/owner as our starting point, then the contingency of life (and of morality) is not merely the result of an autonomous agent stuck in a contingent world. Rather, the subject itself cannot, contra Habermas, escape the Other and others to which and to whom it is beholden; its existence is a contingency all the way down to the kernel of its subjectivity and agency. It is not that the subject (perhaps ala Sartre) is battling against a hostile or contingent world that threatens its essential and authentic individuality at every turn. Rather, the battle takes place within the subject--or better yet, constitutes the subject--who cannot be unified or reintegrated because its experience is fundamentally fragmented. Ethical responsibility, then, is neither the result of mastery nor of authorship, but rather of a response to the call from the other/Other. Harris, on the other hand, argues for mastery over the future as an ethical imperative, that is to say, we have an ethical responsbility to make better people through genetic technologies including cloning. He assumes that we can use our scientific knowledge to control the future of the human species, which is precisely what Habermas finds abhorent. But, only by starting with a notion of human agency as sovereign, as lording over nature, can we come to either of these conclusions. …","PeriodicalId":288505,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","volume":"64 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2011-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPHILNEPAL201171615","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Most philosophers discussing genetic engineering, including cloning, assume the "grown versus made" opposition. Therefore, their stance on the ethics of both revolves around whether they privilege one side of this binary over the other. Part and parcel of the "grown versus made" opposition is the liberal notion of freedom of choice also assumed in these discussions. Most philosophers engaged in debates over genetic engineering and cloning begin with some version of a liberal sovereign individual who has freedom of choice that must be protected, whether we are talking about the parents' freedom (or lack thereof) in considering genetic engineering and embryo selection, or the future persons' freedom (or lack thereof) resulting from such a process. The central question in these debates is whose freedom is most important and thus who gets to exercise their free choice, and why. Although they have different answers to this question--John Harris opts for protecting parents' rights to choose, Jurgen Habermas for protecting the rights of future persons, and some feminists for guaranteeing women's rights to reproductive choice, all of them assume a sovereign individual operating either within a social situation that also makes them interdependent, or on an abstract level preferred by some philosophers to avoid the mess of the real world in favor of moral purity. (1) In this essay, I consider what happens to debates over genetic enhancement when we "deconstruct" the opposition between "grown and made" and the notion of freedom of choice that comes with it. Along with the binary grown and made comes other such oppositions at the center of these debates: chance and choice, accident and deliberation, nature and culture. By deconstructing the oppositions between grown versus made (chance versus choice, or accident versus deliberate), and free versus determined, alternative routes through these bioethical thickets start to emerge. On both sides of debates over genetic engineering and cloning, we see that philosophers assume a sovereign liberal notion of the individual who is free to choose, who can make decisions, and control the future. For philosophers like John Harris this is a good thing while for Jurgen Habermas and others it is not. Habermas imagines that genetic enhancement would make us masters of our destiny in such a way as to undermine the contingencies that make us free. (2) Yet, for Habermas, it is the authorship of one's own life and the ownership of one's own body that results in human agency, an authorship and ownership already at odds with the contigency he privileges. If we refuse the sovereign author/owner as our starting point, then the contingency of life (and of morality) is not merely the result of an autonomous agent stuck in a contingent world. Rather, the subject itself cannot, contra Habermas, escape the Other and others to which and to whom it is beholden; its existence is a contingency all the way down to the kernel of its subjectivity and agency. It is not that the subject (perhaps ala Sartre) is battling against a hostile or contingent world that threatens its essential and authentic individuality at every turn. Rather, the battle takes place within the subject--or better yet, constitutes the subject--who cannot be unified or reintegrated because its experience is fundamentally fragmented. Ethical responsibility, then, is neither the result of mastery nor of authorship, but rather of a response to the call from the other/Other. Harris, on the other hand, argues for mastery over the future as an ethical imperative, that is to say, we have an ethical responsbility to make better people through genetic technologies including cloning. He assumes that we can use our scientific knowledge to control the future of the human species, which is precisely what Habermas finds abhorent. But, only by starting with a notion of human agency as sovereign, as lording over nature, can we come to either of these conclusions. …
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
解构“成长与制造”:克隆的德里安视角
大多数讨论基因工程的哲学家,包括克隆,都假设“生长vs制造”的对立。因此,他们对两者伦理的立场围绕着他们是否给予这二元对立的一方特权而不是另一方。“成长与制造”对立的重要组成部分是自由选择的自由概念,也在这些讨论中被假设。大多数参与基因工程和克隆辩论的哲学家,都是从某种形式的自由主权个人开始的,他有选择的自由,必须得到保护,无论我们是在谈论父母在考虑基因工程和胚胎选择方面的自由(或缺乏自由),还是在这个过程中产生的未来人的自由(或缺乏自由)。这些争论的核心问题是谁的自由最重要,因此谁可以行使他们的自由选择,以及为什么。尽管他们对这个问题有不同的答案——约翰·哈里斯选择保护父母的选择权,尤尔根·哈贝马斯选择保护未来人的权利,一些女权主义者则选择保障妇女的生育选择权,但他们都假设一个至高无上的个人,要么在一个也使他们相互依存的社会环境中运作,要么在一些哲学家喜欢的抽象层面上运作,以避免现实世界的混乱,支持道德纯洁。(1)在这篇文章中,我考虑了当我们“解构”“生长和制造”之间的对立以及随之而来的选择自由的概念时,关于基因增强的争论会发生什么。伴随着生长和制造的二元对立,这些辩论的中心还出现了其他这样的对立:机会和选择,偶然和深思熟虑,自然和文化。通过解构成长与创造之间的对立(机会与选择,或意外与故意),自由与决定之间的对立,通过这些生物伦理丛林的替代路线开始出现。在关于基因工程和克隆的争论中,我们看到哲学家们都假设了一个至高无上的自由主义概念,即个人可以自由选择,可以做出决定,可以控制未来。对于像约翰·哈里斯这样的哲学家来说,这是一件好事,而对于于尔根·哈贝马斯和其他人来说则不是。哈贝马斯设想,基因增强将使我们成为自己命运的主人,从而削弱使我们自由的偶然性。(2)然而,对哈贝马斯来说,正是对自己生命的所有权和对自己身体的所有权导致了人的能动性,这种所有权和所有权已经与他所享有的偶然性相冲突。如果我们拒绝把至高无上的作者/所有者作为我们的出发点,那么生命(和道德)的偶然性就不仅仅是一个被困在偶然性世界中的自主主体的结果。相反,与哈贝马斯相反,主体本身无法逃避他者和他者,它对他者和他者负有义务;它的存在是一种偶然性,一直到它的主观性和能动性的核心。这并不是说主体(也许像萨特一样)在与一个随时威胁其本质和真实个性的敌对或偶然的世界作斗争。相反,这场战斗发生在主体内部——或者更好地说,构成主体——主体无法统一或重新整合,因为它的经验从根本上是碎片化的。因此,伦理责任既不是掌握的结果,也不是作者的结果,而是对他者/他者召唤的回应。另一方面,哈里斯认为掌握未来是一种道德上的要求,也就是说,我们有道德上的责任通过包括克隆在内的基因技术创造更好的人。他认为我们可以利用科学知识来控制人类的未来,而这正是哈贝马斯所憎恶的。但是,只有从人类能动性作为主宰,作为主宰自然的概念出发,我们才能得出上述结论中的任何一个。...
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
期刊最新文献
Emily Dickinson: What Is Called Thinking at the Edge of Chaos? Relational Selves: Gender and Cultural Differences in Moral Reasoning Late Pound: The Case of Canto CVII The Reproduction of Subjectivity and the Turnover-time of Ideology: Speculating with German Idealism, Marx, and Adorno Toward an Ethics of Speculative Design
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1