{"title":"Not just war by other means: Cross-border engagement as political struggle","authors":"Lucia M. Rafanelli","doi":"10.1111/1467-8675.12719","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<p>I call cases like this—cross-border political engagements including both kinetic and non-kinetic elements—<i>hybrid cases</i>.<sup>1</sup> It is not obvious how to understand the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases. Should we understand them as warfare—conflicts between “enemies” locked in a “radically adversarial relationship” whose main task is to harm each other and whose main normative quandary is how much and what kind of harm they are permitted to inflict (see Walzer, <span>2017</span>, p. xiii)? Or should we understand them as some (other) kind of political struggle?</p><p>The question of which analytic frame to adopt is important, as, I will argue, there are serious democratic costs associated with understanding the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases as warfare. In Counterinsurgency, understanding civilian casualty reports made by journalists, activists, and insurgents as acts of war would mean seeing them as acts meant to cause harm (by debilitating “enemy” forces) and as strategic communications whose purpose and value were, at best, unconnected to their truth. It would mean seeing their authors as potentially liable to attack—as Gross does when he describes journalists as “the foot soldiers of media warfare” (<span>2015</span>, p. 300) and argues they are therefore liable to harms including “capture, incarceration, expulsion, or the destruction or confiscation of their equipment” (<span>2015</span>, p. 269). And it would mean seeing their audiences as pawns to be manipulated by propagandists.</p><p>Understanding civilian casualty reports instead as part of a political struggle would mean seeing them as statements that could inform, inspire critical reflection, and form the basis of democratic deliberation and contestation—which might not be contained within the borders of a single state. It would mean seeing their authors as sources of potentially weighty claims deserving real consideration and seeing their audiences as interlocutors capable of judging and responding in good faith to those claims.</p><p>Existing scholarship does not often explicitly recognize the question of whether to understand the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases as warfare or political struggle—let alone explicitly evaluate the costs and benefits of making one choice or another.<sup>2</sup> Nonetheless, some (e.g., Blank, <span>2017</span>; Gross, <span>2015</span>; Gross & Meisels, <span>2017a</span>; Kittrie, <span>2016</span>; Walzer, <span>2017</span>) tend to treat them more like warfare, and others (e.g., Jurkevics, <span>2019</span>; Miller, <span>2010</span>, pp. 247–57; Miller, <span>2018</span>; Valdez, <span>2019a, 2019b</span>) tend to treat them more like political struggle. Here, I make explicit the implicit assumptions behind these two approaches, argue that adopting the <i>war paradigm</i> (understanding the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases as “warfare”) has significant democratic costs, and argue that adopting an alternate <i>political struggle paradigm</i> could mitigate these costs.</p><p>More specifically, overreliance on the war paradigm undermines the potential for cross-border politics to become—and be recognized as—a site of genuinely <i>democratic</i> politics. It does so in three ways. First, it presents global political actors as enemies enmeshed in “a radically adversarial relationship” (Walzer, <span>2017</span>, p. xiii), dedicated to harming and vanquishing each other. This obscures the possibility that they might develop relationships of reciprocal respect conducive to mutual learning and solidaristic collaboration across borders—precisely the kinds of relationships that best enable democratic politics. Second, adopting the war paradigm encourages the assumption that participants in cross-border politics act only in the service of their war strategy—rather than to advance potentially democratic deliberation or political struggle. The prevalence of this assumption can, in turn, transform the institutions through which people participate in cross-border politics (e.g., the media)—changing them from potential catalysts for democratic politics into vehicles through which belligerents carry out their war efforts. Third, if people believe participants in cross-border politics act only to further a war strategy, they may prematurely discount participants’ legitimate moral arguments, assuming these arguments are advanced purely instrumentally.</p><p>Whereas adopting the war paradigm risks incurring these democratic costs, I argue we could mitigate them by adopting the political struggle paradigm. This alternate paradigm casts participants in cross-border politics as participants in a shared political struggle who do not necessarily seek to harm or destroy their opponents, who may be open to revising their ends in response to pushback from opponents in ways combatants are not, and whose behavior should be governed primarily by principles of political responsibility (rather than, e.g., just war principles or principles of military strategy). Moreover, according to the political struggle paradigm, the border need not cleanly divide opponents from allies.<sup>3</sup></p><p>Below, I more thoroughly define the war paradigm. I then argue that overreliance on it undermines the potential for cross-border politics to become (and be recognized as) a site of genuinely <i>democratic</i> politics in the three ways suggested above. Finally, I outline the alternative political struggle paradigm and argue that adopting it can mitigate the democratic costs associated with the war paradigm.</p><p>I do not claim that we should <i>never</i> use the war paradigm. Perhaps sometimes we should bear its democratic costs. Someone who sees little value in democratizing cross-border politics may judge the democratic costs of the war paradigm as morally insignificant. I will not attempt to defend democracy against its critics here. But understanding the democratic costs of adopting the war paradigm is a prerequisite for making any credible judgment about whether those costs are worth bearing—even a credible judgment that they <i>are</i> worth bearing. I enable this understanding here by illustrating the democratic costs of the war paradigm and how adopting an alternate paradigm could mitigate them. In revealing a new obstacle to the democratization of cross-border politics (overreliance on the war paradigm), my arguments may have added significance for proponents of transnational democracy (e.g., Benhabib, <span>2005</span>, <span>2009</span>; Bohman, <span>2007</span>), but they remain important for anyone interested in honestly assessing the democratic costs and benefits of employing one or another analytic frame to understand cross-border politics.</p><p>The <i>war paradigm</i> is a particular way of conceptualizing and analyzing political activity. It is only plausible to use the war paradigm when such activity involves actors with opposing ends, so I will assume this is true in all the cases I discuss.</p><p>Employing the war paradigm to analyze political activity means treating participants as if they are enmeshed in “a radically adversarial relationship” (Walzer, <span>2017</span>, p. xiii). Writing about conflicts that do not take the form of conventional kinetic warfare (“soft war”), Walzer illustrates how identifying these conflicts as “war” involves assuming this adversarial relationship as a central feature: “‘we’ are trying to harm enemies who are trying to harm ‘us.’ And in this kind of warfare, as in any other, the combatants need to know what harms are permissible and what harms aren't, who can be targeted and who must not be targeted” (Walzer, <span>2017</span>, p. xiii). Walzer writes this in a forward to Gross and Meisels’ (<span>2017a</span>, p. 1) edited volume <i>Soft War</i>, which presents many modes of political engagement, including “all non-kinetic measures, whether persuasive or coercive, including cyber warfare and economic sanctions; media warfare and propaganda, nonviolent resistance and civil disobedience, boycotts and ‘lawfare’” as forms of “war”—albeit of the “soft” variety. In fairness to Walzer, he does not argue that we should always understand these modes of engagement as “war,” but rather articulates (some of) the implications of doing so. He highlights some of the assumptions we make when we categorize an activity as “war.” That is, he articulates some of the implicit assumptions underlying the war paradigm, which I aim to make explicit here. Specifically, Walzer notes that in “war,” the main task of each actor is to harm those on opposing sides until they are defeated. The main normative question facing each actor is: How much and what kind of harm am I justified in causing my enemies (see Walzer, <span>2017</span>, p. xiii)? This does not mean that radically adversarial relationships of this kind must be the <i>only</i> ones present in a political encounter for the war paradigm to be appropriate. Even enemies in war may share friendships, familial relationships, romantic relationships, and acts of mercy. But the choice to analyze their political activity using the war paradigm is a choice to treat their identities as enemies as their <i>central</i> identities, their task of harming their enemies to advance their own ends as their <i>central</i> task, and the normative question of how much and what kind of harm they should cause their enemies as their <i>central</i> normative quandary. The choice to analyze political activity using the war paradigm is a choice to treat political actors’ identities, tasks, and normative quandaries as defined by other (less radically adversarial) relationships as marginal. In other words, analyzing political activity using the war paradigm means analyzing it through an <i>adversarial lens</i>.</p><p>Employing the war paradigm also involves making certain assumptions about the principles that should govern political actors’ behavior, though the specific assumptions it entails vary depending on the role one occupies. For example, for political theorists, employing the war paradigm involves appealing to “just war” principles such as just cause (wars should only be waged for specified reasons), last resort (wars should only be waged after other options have been exhausted), discrimination (warring parties should attack only legitimate targets), necessity (every war campaign should be necessary to achieve a legitimate end), and proportionality (neither the war as a whole nor any individual act of war should cause too much damage compared to the benefits it promises).<sup>4</sup> For legal analysts, adopting the war paradigm means assuming behavior should be governed primarily by the law of armed conflict (LOAC), which “governs the conduct of states, individuals, and non-state actors during armed conflict” and is largely based on just war principles (Blank, <span>2017</span>, pp. 90–91). For military leaders, adopting the war paradigm means assuming behavior should be governed primarily by the principles of military strategy, which may also include or be constrained by just war principles.</p><p>Having clarified what the “war paradigm” is, I can now assess the costs of employing it to analyze the non-kinetic elements in hybrid cases of cross-border politics. In questioning whether we should use the war paradigm to analyze activities that are not literal warfare, I sympathize with advocates of <i>jus ad vim</i>, who argue we should not use just war theory to analyze the use of force-short-of-war (see Brunstetter, <span>2021</span>; Brunstetter & Braun, <span>2013</span>; for a review of the <i>jus ad vim</i> literature, see Galliott, <span>2019</span>). However, <i>jus ad vim</i> theorists are still concerned with the use of <i>force</i>. Indeed, Brunstetter (<span>2021</span>, p. 8) explicitly limits his discussion to acts “that involve kinetic, lethal force.” Conversely, I focus on the non-kinetic elements of cross-border conflict. Thus, my analysis provides a necessary supplement to the <i>jus ad vim</i> literature—exposing another domain (non-kinetic engagement in the context of hybrid conflicts) in which overreliance on the war paradigm has significant disadvantages and, eventually, illustrating how adopting the alternate political struggle paradigm could mitigate them.</p><p>Given that reliance on the war paradigm to analyze cross-border politics can undermine the latter's democratic potential, I propose an alternate paradigm: the political struggle paradigm. By adopting the political struggle paradigm, we could mitigate the democratic costs associated with the war paradigm. While adopting the war paradigm involves analyzing cross-border politics through an <i>adversarial lens</i> that casts people on opposite sides of the border as enemies who must attempt to harm and defeat each other, adopting the political struggle paradigm involves using a <i>co-participant lens</i> that casts people on opposite sides of the border as co-participants in a political struggle. Some are opponents and some are allies, and the border does not necessarily cleanly divide opponents from allies. Moreover, although participants in a paradigmatic political struggle do seek political “victory,” they do not necessarily seek to harm or destroy their opponents as do warring combatants. And they may be open to revising their ends in response to criticism and pushback from their opponents in ways warring combatants are not.</p><p>The political struggle paradigm is ecumenical in that it can be adopted by deliberative/associationist and agonist democratic theorists alike.<sup>7</sup> After all, associationists who emphasize the importance of deliberation aimed at establishing agreement need not deny that opposition can be a part of democratic politics. Indeed, initial disagreement is what makes necessary (and possible) the argumentative give-and-take that theorists like Christiano (<span>2004</span>, pp. 275–276), Blajer de la Garza (<span>n.d</span>., pp. 12–13), and Young (<span>2000</span>, pp. 3, 6) treat as a central feature of democracy. Similarly, agonists who see conflict and contestation as endemic to democrtic politics need not conceptualize this conflict as a form of <i>war</i>. Note Honig's description of her work in <i>Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics</i> (“the book enacted the agonism of <i>virtù</i>, infiltrating and occupying its opponents”), which she directly contrasts with a more war-like approach (“and not (as in the agonism of Homer's epics) nobly destroying or defeating them”) (Maxwell et al., <span>2019</span>, p. 662). And recall Mouffe's (<span>2000</span>, pp. 101–103) distinction between “antagonism” (in which one sees opponents as “enem[ies] to be destroyed” (<span>2000</span>, p. 102)) and her preferred model of democratic politics, “agonism” (in which one sees opponents as legitimate adversaries).</p><p>Another distinguishing feature of the political struggle paradigm is the principles it says should govern actors’ behavior. The war paradigm assumes actors’ behavior should be governed by just war principles, the LOAC, or military strategy. But adopting the political struggle paradigm means assuming actors’ behavior should be governed by principles of political responsibility—principles outlining individuals’ responsibilities for creating and supporting just institutions and social structures, and for contesting existing injustices. A principle telling us to support just institutions where they exist and help create them where they do not, in line with Rawls's natural duty of justice, would be one example (Rawls, <span>1999</span>, p. 99). Young's (<span>2006</span>) principles requiring us to join with others (perhaps across the globe) in collective action to dismantle the unjust social structures we help perpetuate are another.</p><p>When we analyze cross-border politics using the political struggle paradigm, the central moral questions we face are not the ones we would face if we used the war paradigm. The war paradigm prompts us to ask, to paraphrase Walzer (<span>2017</span>, p. xiii): How much and what kind of harm should political actors do to their enemies on the other side of the border? Instead, the political struggle paradigm prompts us to ask: In what ways should political actors join with others in contestation aimed at achieving (what they believe to be) justice? Who (on either side of the border) should they seek out as allies, and who (on either side of the border) should they see as political opponents?</p><p>To illustrate what it would look like for theorists to analyze cross-border politics using the political struggle paradigm, we can turn to Valdez's (<span>2019a, 2019b</span>) examination of transnational political coalitions among opponents of racism in “Western” societies and opponents of colonial oppression outside the West. Miller's (<span>2010</span>, pp. 247–257) account of the “community of outlook” dedicated to what he calls “global social democracy” and who participate in social movements aimed at ending global injustice, inequality, domination, and exploitation is another excellent example. The same goes for Jurkevics’ (<span>2019</span>) account of people engaged in political contestation about and across the multiple, overlapping jurisdictions in which they are subject to political power.</p><p>The salient normative questions regarding actors involved in such political struggles include (for Valdez, <span>2019a, 2019b</span> and Miller, <span>2010</span>, esp. ch. 9) how they ought to cooperate with others to oppose the global injustice, domination, and exploitation brought about by imperial or neo-imperial powers and (for Jurkevics, <span>2019</span>) how they should participate in and safeguard democratic decision-making processes even when this necessitates exercising and holding accountable political power that transcends national borders. In other words, participants’ central behavioral requirements are not determined by just war principles, the LOAC, or military strategy, but instead by principles indicating how they can and should join with others in political action to oppose injustice.</p><p>We can imagine how different Blank's analysis would look if she adopted this outlook instead of the war paradigm. Claims that an attack killed too many civilians and truthful media reporting on such claims would not appear as underhanded attempts to stop legitimate attacks, which must be treated with suspicion because they originate from or seem to serve the interests of “enemies” on the other side of a border. A global public who responded to these reports with anger or opposition to military activity would not be seen as unwitting dupes of a clever insurgency manipulating their emotional responses to turn them against the attacking military. And the media reporting on civilian casualties would not be compelled to become a full-fledged instrument of the attacking state's war effort, because it would not be seen as a tool of war that must be fully co-opted by one belligerent party to avoid its benefiting the “enemy.”</p><p>Thus, moving from the war paradigm to the political struggle paradigm can mitigate the democratic costs of the former. If those engaged in cross-border politics made this transition, they would no longer see each other as enemies who must be vanquished, but as fellow participants in political contestation who may turn out to be opponents or allies, and who may learn something from each other's insights. They would no longer see claims from people beyond their borders as strategically crafted communications designed to accomplish war aims. Instead, they would see these claims as potentially credible and worthy of serious consideration. Finally, if participants recognized institutions like the media as integral parts of democratic political struggle, rather than seeing them as tools of one or another belligerent party, they would be less likely to morph those institutions into pure weapons of war, decimating their democratic potential.</p><p>Du Bois's transnational activism against racism and empire (see Valdez, <span>2019b</span>) illustrates what it could look like for participants in cross-border politics to adopt the political struggle paradigm and how this could enable their political activities to become genuinely democratic—even against a background of frequent violence. Du Bois's activism is only one among many examples. There are myriad other civil society actors throughout history who have arguably rejected the war paradigm in favor of the political struggle paradigm. Consider, for example, feminist activists in Vietnam, the United States, and Canada who collaborated in an international women's movement against the US war in Vietnam (Tzu-Chun Wu, <span>2013</span>, pp. 193–218); the Ugandan pastor and Congolese refugees who co-founded Hope of Children and Women Victims of Violence in Uganda, which provides skills training programs to refugees and Ugandan citizens (Pincock et al., <span>2020</span>, p. 1); or the global network of states and civil society actors that collaborated in recent decades to advocate for a nuclear weapons ban (Gibbons, <span>2018</span>). I make no attempt to discuss the full universe of cases in this article alone. Rather, for the purposes of my argument, I need only discuss an illustrative case to show what cross-border politics can look like when participants reject the war paradigm in favor of the political struggle paradigm—and for this, I turn to Du Bois.</p><p>The activism I discuss below on the part of Du Bois was nonviolent, but we can interpret it as part of a broader anti-imperialist struggle in which both imperialists and their opponents used kinetic and non-kinetic means. We are therefore justified in treating Du Bois's activism as a non-kinetic element of a hybrid case. Indeed, colonization and racial oppression in Du Bois's time were carried out by massive and long-term (kinetic) violence. If anti-imperialist, anti-racist activism in this context can take the form of democratic cross-border politics, surely there is hope that cross-border activism in other violent contexts might take a similar form. At the very least, Du Bois's example shows that democratic political engagement via non-kinetic means is possible, even when it is part of a conflict in which other actors use kinetic force.</p><p>Valdez (<span>2019b</span>, esp. chs. 3–5) describes how Du Bois cultivated a transnational network of activists to challenge imperialist racialized domination, which they saw as intertwined with domestic racial injustice. Excluded from or subordinated within domestic and international political institutions, Du Bois and his allies created new channels for their political activities through which they cultivated solidarity, respect, and constructive dialogue among themselves and harnessed these resources to politically oppose the empire. For example, Du Bois hosted the 1919 Pan-African Congress, bringing together African-Americans and Africans from several countries to discuss the future of people of color around the world and in an attempt to influence Western leaders’ contemporaneous peace talks at Versailles (Valdez, <span>2019b</span>, pp. 1–2). Du Bois also attended transnational political events and cultivated connections and dialogue among opponents of racial oppression around the world—for instance, by covering salient world events and including contributions from international authors in his newspaper, <i>The Crisis—</i>and he drew on these connections to facilitate political action on behalf of colonized people and African-Americans (Valdez, <span>2019b</span>, pp. 161–175).</p><p>Thus, Du Bois approached opposition to imperial oppression as a cross-border political struggle—seeking allyship with potential co-participants from around the world. Someone adopting the war paradigm might understand opposition to imperialism as an adversarial conflict between “colonizers” and “colonized,” assuming that membership in a colonizing or colonized country (or race) was sufficient to place a person in one or the other category. But Du Bois seems to have thought, in line with the political struggle paradigm, that allies could be found among “colonized” peoples and racial groups subordinated by imperialism <i>and</i> within “colonizing” peoples and racial groups privileged by imperialism. After all, he sought political connections with “white European peace activists and black intellectuals and activists from around the world” (Valdez, <span>2019b</span>, p. 165).</p><p>Du Bois cultivated dialogue among his transnational allies and built on this dialogue to spur joint political action. Insofar as <i>The Crisis</i> was a locus of this activity, this case also illustrates how media outlets not beholden to the war paradigm can catalyze democratic politics. Indeed, we are justified in calling Du Bois's activism “democratic” (Valdez (<span>2019b</span>, p. 175) certainly presents it as such) in that it seems to have centrally involved dialogue, relationships of mutual respect, the good-faith evaluation of different actors’ claims and arguments, and an effort to elevate unjustly marginalized voices in political decision-making processes. Many if not all of these features would have been undermined had Du Bois and his allies understood their activities in terms of the war paradigm. This also illustrates how we can meaningfully describe cross-border politics as “democratic” even in the absence of formal transnational democratic institutions: that Du Bois and his allies did not constitute a transnational state-like apparatus with electoral and enforcement capability does not mean their movement was not “democratic.”</p><p>Similarly, Valdez's treatment of Du Bois illustrates how, when theorists transition from the war paradigm to the political struggle paradigm, they avoid inappropriately projecting war-like mentalities and behaviors onto participants in cross-border politics and thereby losing the opportunity to understand and encourage novel forms of cross-border democratic politics. Valdez (<span>2019b</span>, p. 175) explicitly presents DuBois's activity as a “political craft” that inaugurated a “transnational counter-public,” which she suggests we should see as a <i>demos</i>. Alternatively, adopting the war paradigm could have led Valdez to understand struggles over empire as (only) adversarial conflicts between “colonizers” and “colonized,” and in turn to overlook precisely the kind of political alliances and activities Du Bois inaugurated by transcending this binary “us vs. them” framing. Indeed, Valdez (<span>2019a</span>) criticizes contemporary global justice theorists for doing just this, though she does not connect this oversight to the adoption of the war paradigm.</p><p>In sum, adopting the political struggle paradigm to analyze cross-border politics encourages and renders intelligible relationships of reciprocal respect conducive to mutual learning and solidaristic collaboration across borders. It discourages the cooptation or transformation of institutions (e.g., the media) that could otherwise serve as catalysts for democratic politics into cogs in a war machine. It encourages participants to take others’ moral criticism seriously, rather than summarily dismissing it as a part of their “enemy's” war strategy. That is, adopting the political struggle paradigm paves the way for truly democratic cross-border politics. Granted, adopting the political struggle paradigm alone will not guarantee cross-border politics will suddenly become democratic. But whatever <i>else</i> is needed to foster democratic politics, understanding political activity through the political struggle paradigm, rather than the war paradigm, takes us one step in that direction.</p><p>As my analysis has shown, we can find examples of both the war paradigm and the political struggle paradigm in existing literature on cross-border political engagement. However, the scholars who employ these paradigms do not typically present themselves as having chosen one paradigm over the other—or even recognize the two paradigms as alternatives to each other. By drawing attention to the war paradigm and political struggle paradigm as opposed frames, my analysis facilitates a deeper understanding of the scholars who employ these paradigms (often without reflecting on their merits). My analysis may also encourage more conscientious reflection on the choice between the two paradigms, as people may make more deliberate choices about which frames to employ when presented with competing alternatives (Chong & Druckman, <span>2007</span>, pp. 110–111).</p><p>I have also gone beyond existing scholarship by making explicit the often-implicit assumptions behind both the war paradigm and the political struggle paradigm. Often, scholars simply employ their chosen frame, adopting its corresponding assumptions. Those who adopt the war paradigm assume that actors on opposite sides of a border are enemies enmeshed in an adversarial relationship whose behavior should be governed by just war theory, the LOAC, or military strategy. Those who adopt the political struggle paradigm assume that actors are co-participants in a political struggle who may find opponents or allies on either side of the border and whose behavior should be governed by principles of political responsibility. But neither proponents of the war paradigm nor the political struggle paradigm do enough to acknowledge these assumptions or their connection to their chosen paradigms. Identifying the assumptions at the base of each paradigm is a prerequisite to making a conscientious choice between them.</p><p>My examination of the democratic costs of adopting the war paradigm further facilitates such conscientious choice. Perhaps these costs will sometimes be worth bearing. But to make informed judgments about whether they are, we must first have a thorough understanding of <i>what</i> they are. Though there are others who adopt the political struggle paradigm—some for reasons related to their democratic commitments—my analysis has yielded an original (and more detailed) account of the democratic costs adopting the war paradigm generates for transnational politics. This, in turn, has allowed me to illustrate—in conversation with empirical scholarship on framing effects—how rejecting the war paradigm in favor of the political struggle paradigm may facilitate cross-border political spaces becoming sites of genuinely democratic politics.</p><p>Cross-border politics that does not take the form of literal kinetic warfare has the potential to be democratic in ways battle is not. But participants risk squandering this potential when they unreflectively use the war paradigm to understand their circumstances and guide their behavior. Similarly, theorists may miss an opportunity to understand and encourage novel forms of democratic politics if they do the same. This makes exercising care in choosing between the war paradigm and the political struggle paradigm especially important. After all, politics is not just war by other means.</p>","PeriodicalId":51578,"journal":{"name":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","volume":"31 4","pages":"661-677"},"PeriodicalIF":1.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-10-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/1467-8675.12719","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Constellations-An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-8675.12719","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q3","JCRName":"POLITICAL SCIENCE","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Abstract
I call cases like this—cross-border political engagements including both kinetic and non-kinetic elements—hybrid cases.1 It is not obvious how to understand the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases. Should we understand them as warfare—conflicts between “enemies” locked in a “radically adversarial relationship” whose main task is to harm each other and whose main normative quandary is how much and what kind of harm they are permitted to inflict (see Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)? Or should we understand them as some (other) kind of political struggle?
The question of which analytic frame to adopt is important, as, I will argue, there are serious democratic costs associated with understanding the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases as warfare. In Counterinsurgency, understanding civilian casualty reports made by journalists, activists, and insurgents as acts of war would mean seeing them as acts meant to cause harm (by debilitating “enemy” forces) and as strategic communications whose purpose and value were, at best, unconnected to their truth. It would mean seeing their authors as potentially liable to attack—as Gross does when he describes journalists as “the foot soldiers of media warfare” (2015, p. 300) and argues they are therefore liable to harms including “capture, incarceration, expulsion, or the destruction or confiscation of their equipment” (2015, p. 269). And it would mean seeing their audiences as pawns to be manipulated by propagandists.
Understanding civilian casualty reports instead as part of a political struggle would mean seeing them as statements that could inform, inspire critical reflection, and form the basis of democratic deliberation and contestation—which might not be contained within the borders of a single state. It would mean seeing their authors as sources of potentially weighty claims deserving real consideration and seeing their audiences as interlocutors capable of judging and responding in good faith to those claims.
Existing scholarship does not often explicitly recognize the question of whether to understand the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases as warfare or political struggle—let alone explicitly evaluate the costs and benefits of making one choice or another.2 Nonetheless, some (e.g., Blank, 2017; Gross, 2015; Gross & Meisels, 2017a; Kittrie, 2016; Walzer, 2017) tend to treat them more like warfare, and others (e.g., Jurkevics, 2019; Miller, 2010, pp. 247–57; Miller, 2018; Valdez, 2019a, 2019b) tend to treat them more like political struggle. Here, I make explicit the implicit assumptions behind these two approaches, argue that adopting the war paradigm (understanding the non-kinetic elements of hybrid cases as “warfare”) has significant democratic costs, and argue that adopting an alternate political struggle paradigm could mitigate these costs.
More specifically, overreliance on the war paradigm undermines the potential for cross-border politics to become—and be recognized as—a site of genuinely democratic politics. It does so in three ways. First, it presents global political actors as enemies enmeshed in “a radically adversarial relationship” (Walzer, 2017, p. xiii), dedicated to harming and vanquishing each other. This obscures the possibility that they might develop relationships of reciprocal respect conducive to mutual learning and solidaristic collaboration across borders—precisely the kinds of relationships that best enable democratic politics. Second, adopting the war paradigm encourages the assumption that participants in cross-border politics act only in the service of their war strategy—rather than to advance potentially democratic deliberation or political struggle. The prevalence of this assumption can, in turn, transform the institutions through which people participate in cross-border politics (e.g., the media)—changing them from potential catalysts for democratic politics into vehicles through which belligerents carry out their war efforts. Third, if people believe participants in cross-border politics act only to further a war strategy, they may prematurely discount participants’ legitimate moral arguments, assuming these arguments are advanced purely instrumentally.
Whereas adopting the war paradigm risks incurring these democratic costs, I argue we could mitigate them by adopting the political struggle paradigm. This alternate paradigm casts participants in cross-border politics as participants in a shared political struggle who do not necessarily seek to harm or destroy their opponents, who may be open to revising their ends in response to pushback from opponents in ways combatants are not, and whose behavior should be governed primarily by principles of political responsibility (rather than, e.g., just war principles or principles of military strategy). Moreover, according to the political struggle paradigm, the border need not cleanly divide opponents from allies.3
Below, I more thoroughly define the war paradigm. I then argue that overreliance on it undermines the potential for cross-border politics to become (and be recognized as) a site of genuinely democratic politics in the three ways suggested above. Finally, I outline the alternative political struggle paradigm and argue that adopting it can mitigate the democratic costs associated with the war paradigm.
I do not claim that we should never use the war paradigm. Perhaps sometimes we should bear its democratic costs. Someone who sees little value in democratizing cross-border politics may judge the democratic costs of the war paradigm as morally insignificant. I will not attempt to defend democracy against its critics here. But understanding the democratic costs of adopting the war paradigm is a prerequisite for making any credible judgment about whether those costs are worth bearing—even a credible judgment that they are worth bearing. I enable this understanding here by illustrating the democratic costs of the war paradigm and how adopting an alternate paradigm could mitigate them. In revealing a new obstacle to the democratization of cross-border politics (overreliance on the war paradigm), my arguments may have added significance for proponents of transnational democracy (e.g., Benhabib, 2005, 2009; Bohman, 2007), but they remain important for anyone interested in honestly assessing the democratic costs and benefits of employing one or another analytic frame to understand cross-border politics.
The war paradigm is a particular way of conceptualizing and analyzing political activity. It is only plausible to use the war paradigm when such activity involves actors with opposing ends, so I will assume this is true in all the cases I discuss.
Employing the war paradigm to analyze political activity means treating participants as if they are enmeshed in “a radically adversarial relationship” (Walzer, 2017, p. xiii). Writing about conflicts that do not take the form of conventional kinetic warfare (“soft war”), Walzer illustrates how identifying these conflicts as “war” involves assuming this adversarial relationship as a central feature: “‘we’ are trying to harm enemies who are trying to harm ‘us.’ And in this kind of warfare, as in any other, the combatants need to know what harms are permissible and what harms aren't, who can be targeted and who must not be targeted” (Walzer, 2017, p. xiii). Walzer writes this in a forward to Gross and Meisels’ (2017a, p. 1) edited volume Soft War, which presents many modes of political engagement, including “all non-kinetic measures, whether persuasive or coercive, including cyber warfare and economic sanctions; media warfare and propaganda, nonviolent resistance and civil disobedience, boycotts and ‘lawfare’” as forms of “war”—albeit of the “soft” variety. In fairness to Walzer, he does not argue that we should always understand these modes of engagement as “war,” but rather articulates (some of) the implications of doing so. He highlights some of the assumptions we make when we categorize an activity as “war.” That is, he articulates some of the implicit assumptions underlying the war paradigm, which I aim to make explicit here. Specifically, Walzer notes that in “war,” the main task of each actor is to harm those on opposing sides until they are defeated. The main normative question facing each actor is: How much and what kind of harm am I justified in causing my enemies (see Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)? This does not mean that radically adversarial relationships of this kind must be the only ones present in a political encounter for the war paradigm to be appropriate. Even enemies in war may share friendships, familial relationships, romantic relationships, and acts of mercy. But the choice to analyze their political activity using the war paradigm is a choice to treat their identities as enemies as their central identities, their task of harming their enemies to advance their own ends as their central task, and the normative question of how much and what kind of harm they should cause their enemies as their central normative quandary. The choice to analyze political activity using the war paradigm is a choice to treat political actors’ identities, tasks, and normative quandaries as defined by other (less radically adversarial) relationships as marginal. In other words, analyzing political activity using the war paradigm means analyzing it through an adversarial lens.
Employing the war paradigm also involves making certain assumptions about the principles that should govern political actors’ behavior, though the specific assumptions it entails vary depending on the role one occupies. For example, for political theorists, employing the war paradigm involves appealing to “just war” principles such as just cause (wars should only be waged for specified reasons), last resort (wars should only be waged after other options have been exhausted), discrimination (warring parties should attack only legitimate targets), necessity (every war campaign should be necessary to achieve a legitimate end), and proportionality (neither the war as a whole nor any individual act of war should cause too much damage compared to the benefits it promises).4 For legal analysts, adopting the war paradigm means assuming behavior should be governed primarily by the law of armed conflict (LOAC), which “governs the conduct of states, individuals, and non-state actors during armed conflict” and is largely based on just war principles (Blank, 2017, pp. 90–91). For military leaders, adopting the war paradigm means assuming behavior should be governed primarily by the principles of military strategy, which may also include or be constrained by just war principles.
Having clarified what the “war paradigm” is, I can now assess the costs of employing it to analyze the non-kinetic elements in hybrid cases of cross-border politics. In questioning whether we should use the war paradigm to analyze activities that are not literal warfare, I sympathize with advocates of jus ad vim, who argue we should not use just war theory to analyze the use of force-short-of-war (see Brunstetter, 2021; Brunstetter & Braun, 2013; for a review of the jus ad vim literature, see Galliott, 2019). However, jus ad vim theorists are still concerned with the use of force. Indeed, Brunstetter (2021, p. 8) explicitly limits his discussion to acts “that involve kinetic, lethal force.” Conversely, I focus on the non-kinetic elements of cross-border conflict. Thus, my analysis provides a necessary supplement to the jus ad vim literature—exposing another domain (non-kinetic engagement in the context of hybrid conflicts) in which overreliance on the war paradigm has significant disadvantages and, eventually, illustrating how adopting the alternate political struggle paradigm could mitigate them.
Given that reliance on the war paradigm to analyze cross-border politics can undermine the latter's democratic potential, I propose an alternate paradigm: the political struggle paradigm. By adopting the political struggle paradigm, we could mitigate the democratic costs associated with the war paradigm. While adopting the war paradigm involves analyzing cross-border politics through an adversarial lens that casts people on opposite sides of the border as enemies who must attempt to harm and defeat each other, adopting the political struggle paradigm involves using a co-participant lens that casts people on opposite sides of the border as co-participants in a political struggle. Some are opponents and some are allies, and the border does not necessarily cleanly divide opponents from allies. Moreover, although participants in a paradigmatic political struggle do seek political “victory,” they do not necessarily seek to harm or destroy their opponents as do warring combatants. And they may be open to revising their ends in response to criticism and pushback from their opponents in ways warring combatants are not.
The political struggle paradigm is ecumenical in that it can be adopted by deliberative/associationist and agonist democratic theorists alike.7 After all, associationists who emphasize the importance of deliberation aimed at establishing agreement need not deny that opposition can be a part of democratic politics. Indeed, initial disagreement is what makes necessary (and possible) the argumentative give-and-take that theorists like Christiano (2004, pp. 275–276), Blajer de la Garza (n.d., pp. 12–13), and Young (2000, pp. 3, 6) treat as a central feature of democracy. Similarly, agonists who see conflict and contestation as endemic to democrtic politics need not conceptualize this conflict as a form of war. Note Honig's description of her work in Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics (“the book enacted the agonism of virtù, infiltrating and occupying its opponents”), which she directly contrasts with a more war-like approach (“and not (as in the agonism of Homer's epics) nobly destroying or defeating them”) (Maxwell et al., 2019, p. 662). And recall Mouffe's (2000, pp. 101–103) distinction between “antagonism” (in which one sees opponents as “enem[ies] to be destroyed” (2000, p. 102)) and her preferred model of democratic politics, “agonism” (in which one sees opponents as legitimate adversaries).
Another distinguishing feature of the political struggle paradigm is the principles it says should govern actors’ behavior. The war paradigm assumes actors’ behavior should be governed by just war principles, the LOAC, or military strategy. But adopting the political struggle paradigm means assuming actors’ behavior should be governed by principles of political responsibility—principles outlining individuals’ responsibilities for creating and supporting just institutions and social structures, and for contesting existing injustices. A principle telling us to support just institutions where they exist and help create them where they do not, in line with Rawls's natural duty of justice, would be one example (Rawls, 1999, p. 99). Young's (2006) principles requiring us to join with others (perhaps across the globe) in collective action to dismantle the unjust social structures we help perpetuate are another.
When we analyze cross-border politics using the political struggle paradigm, the central moral questions we face are not the ones we would face if we used the war paradigm. The war paradigm prompts us to ask, to paraphrase Walzer (2017, p. xiii): How much and what kind of harm should political actors do to their enemies on the other side of the border? Instead, the political struggle paradigm prompts us to ask: In what ways should political actors join with others in contestation aimed at achieving (what they believe to be) justice? Who (on either side of the border) should they seek out as allies, and who (on either side of the border) should they see as political opponents?
To illustrate what it would look like for theorists to analyze cross-border politics using the political struggle paradigm, we can turn to Valdez's (2019a, 2019b) examination of transnational political coalitions among opponents of racism in “Western” societies and opponents of colonial oppression outside the West. Miller's (2010, pp. 247–257) account of the “community of outlook” dedicated to what he calls “global social democracy” and who participate in social movements aimed at ending global injustice, inequality, domination, and exploitation is another excellent example. The same goes for Jurkevics’ (2019) account of people engaged in political contestation about and across the multiple, overlapping jurisdictions in which they are subject to political power.
The salient normative questions regarding actors involved in such political struggles include (for Valdez, 2019a, 2019b and Miller, 2010, esp. ch. 9) how they ought to cooperate with others to oppose the global injustice, domination, and exploitation brought about by imperial or neo-imperial powers and (for Jurkevics, 2019) how they should participate in and safeguard democratic decision-making processes even when this necessitates exercising and holding accountable political power that transcends national borders. In other words, participants’ central behavioral requirements are not determined by just war principles, the LOAC, or military strategy, but instead by principles indicating how they can and should join with others in political action to oppose injustice.
We can imagine how different Blank's analysis would look if she adopted this outlook instead of the war paradigm. Claims that an attack killed too many civilians and truthful media reporting on such claims would not appear as underhanded attempts to stop legitimate attacks, which must be treated with suspicion because they originate from or seem to serve the interests of “enemies” on the other side of a border. A global public who responded to these reports with anger or opposition to military activity would not be seen as unwitting dupes of a clever insurgency manipulating their emotional responses to turn them against the attacking military. And the media reporting on civilian casualties would not be compelled to become a full-fledged instrument of the attacking state's war effort, because it would not be seen as a tool of war that must be fully co-opted by one belligerent party to avoid its benefiting the “enemy.”
Thus, moving from the war paradigm to the political struggle paradigm can mitigate the democratic costs of the former. If those engaged in cross-border politics made this transition, they would no longer see each other as enemies who must be vanquished, but as fellow participants in political contestation who may turn out to be opponents or allies, and who may learn something from each other's insights. They would no longer see claims from people beyond their borders as strategically crafted communications designed to accomplish war aims. Instead, they would see these claims as potentially credible and worthy of serious consideration. Finally, if participants recognized institutions like the media as integral parts of democratic political struggle, rather than seeing them as tools of one or another belligerent party, they would be less likely to morph those institutions into pure weapons of war, decimating their democratic potential.
Du Bois's transnational activism against racism and empire (see Valdez, 2019b) illustrates what it could look like for participants in cross-border politics to adopt the political struggle paradigm and how this could enable their political activities to become genuinely democratic—even against a background of frequent violence. Du Bois's activism is only one among many examples. There are myriad other civil society actors throughout history who have arguably rejected the war paradigm in favor of the political struggle paradigm. Consider, for example, feminist activists in Vietnam, the United States, and Canada who collaborated in an international women's movement against the US war in Vietnam (Tzu-Chun Wu, 2013, pp. 193–218); the Ugandan pastor and Congolese refugees who co-founded Hope of Children and Women Victims of Violence in Uganda, which provides skills training programs to refugees and Ugandan citizens (Pincock et al., 2020, p. 1); or the global network of states and civil society actors that collaborated in recent decades to advocate for a nuclear weapons ban (Gibbons, 2018). I make no attempt to discuss the full universe of cases in this article alone. Rather, for the purposes of my argument, I need only discuss an illustrative case to show what cross-border politics can look like when participants reject the war paradigm in favor of the political struggle paradigm—and for this, I turn to Du Bois.
The activism I discuss below on the part of Du Bois was nonviolent, but we can interpret it as part of a broader anti-imperialist struggle in which both imperialists and their opponents used kinetic and non-kinetic means. We are therefore justified in treating Du Bois's activism as a non-kinetic element of a hybrid case. Indeed, colonization and racial oppression in Du Bois's time were carried out by massive and long-term (kinetic) violence. If anti-imperialist, anti-racist activism in this context can take the form of democratic cross-border politics, surely there is hope that cross-border activism in other violent contexts might take a similar form. At the very least, Du Bois's example shows that democratic political engagement via non-kinetic means is possible, even when it is part of a conflict in which other actors use kinetic force.
Valdez (2019b, esp. chs. 3–5) describes how Du Bois cultivated a transnational network of activists to challenge imperialist racialized domination, which they saw as intertwined with domestic racial injustice. Excluded from or subordinated within domestic and international political institutions, Du Bois and his allies created new channels for their political activities through which they cultivated solidarity, respect, and constructive dialogue among themselves and harnessed these resources to politically oppose the empire. For example, Du Bois hosted the 1919 Pan-African Congress, bringing together African-Americans and Africans from several countries to discuss the future of people of color around the world and in an attempt to influence Western leaders’ contemporaneous peace talks at Versailles (Valdez, 2019b, pp. 1–2). Du Bois also attended transnational political events and cultivated connections and dialogue among opponents of racial oppression around the world—for instance, by covering salient world events and including contributions from international authors in his newspaper, The Crisis—and he drew on these connections to facilitate political action on behalf of colonized people and African-Americans (Valdez, 2019b, pp. 161–175).
Thus, Du Bois approached opposition to imperial oppression as a cross-border political struggle—seeking allyship with potential co-participants from around the world. Someone adopting the war paradigm might understand opposition to imperialism as an adversarial conflict between “colonizers” and “colonized,” assuming that membership in a colonizing or colonized country (or race) was sufficient to place a person in one or the other category. But Du Bois seems to have thought, in line with the political struggle paradigm, that allies could be found among “colonized” peoples and racial groups subordinated by imperialism and within “colonizing” peoples and racial groups privileged by imperialism. After all, he sought political connections with “white European peace activists and black intellectuals and activists from around the world” (Valdez, 2019b, p. 165).
Du Bois cultivated dialogue among his transnational allies and built on this dialogue to spur joint political action. Insofar as The Crisis was a locus of this activity, this case also illustrates how media outlets not beholden to the war paradigm can catalyze democratic politics. Indeed, we are justified in calling Du Bois's activism “democratic” (Valdez (2019b, p. 175) certainly presents it as such) in that it seems to have centrally involved dialogue, relationships of mutual respect, the good-faith evaluation of different actors’ claims and arguments, and an effort to elevate unjustly marginalized voices in political decision-making processes. Many if not all of these features would have been undermined had Du Bois and his allies understood their activities in terms of the war paradigm. This also illustrates how we can meaningfully describe cross-border politics as “democratic” even in the absence of formal transnational democratic institutions: that Du Bois and his allies did not constitute a transnational state-like apparatus with electoral and enforcement capability does not mean their movement was not “democratic.”
Similarly, Valdez's treatment of Du Bois illustrates how, when theorists transition from the war paradigm to the political struggle paradigm, they avoid inappropriately projecting war-like mentalities and behaviors onto participants in cross-border politics and thereby losing the opportunity to understand and encourage novel forms of cross-border democratic politics. Valdez (2019b, p. 175) explicitly presents DuBois's activity as a “political craft” that inaugurated a “transnational counter-public,” which she suggests we should see as a demos. Alternatively, adopting the war paradigm could have led Valdez to understand struggles over empire as (only) adversarial conflicts between “colonizers” and “colonized,” and in turn to overlook precisely the kind of political alliances and activities Du Bois inaugurated by transcending this binary “us vs. them” framing. Indeed, Valdez (2019a) criticizes contemporary global justice theorists for doing just this, though she does not connect this oversight to the adoption of the war paradigm.
In sum, adopting the political struggle paradigm to analyze cross-border politics encourages and renders intelligible relationships of reciprocal respect conducive to mutual learning and solidaristic collaboration across borders. It discourages the cooptation or transformation of institutions (e.g., the media) that could otherwise serve as catalysts for democratic politics into cogs in a war machine. It encourages participants to take others’ moral criticism seriously, rather than summarily dismissing it as a part of their “enemy's” war strategy. That is, adopting the political struggle paradigm paves the way for truly democratic cross-border politics. Granted, adopting the political struggle paradigm alone will not guarantee cross-border politics will suddenly become democratic. But whatever else is needed to foster democratic politics, understanding political activity through the political struggle paradigm, rather than the war paradigm, takes us one step in that direction.
As my analysis has shown, we can find examples of both the war paradigm and the political struggle paradigm in existing literature on cross-border political engagement. However, the scholars who employ these paradigms do not typically present themselves as having chosen one paradigm over the other—or even recognize the two paradigms as alternatives to each other. By drawing attention to the war paradigm and political struggle paradigm as opposed frames, my analysis facilitates a deeper understanding of the scholars who employ these paradigms (often without reflecting on their merits). My analysis may also encourage more conscientious reflection on the choice between the two paradigms, as people may make more deliberate choices about which frames to employ when presented with competing alternatives (Chong & Druckman, 2007, pp. 110–111).
I have also gone beyond existing scholarship by making explicit the often-implicit assumptions behind both the war paradigm and the political struggle paradigm. Often, scholars simply employ their chosen frame, adopting its corresponding assumptions. Those who adopt the war paradigm assume that actors on opposite sides of a border are enemies enmeshed in an adversarial relationship whose behavior should be governed by just war theory, the LOAC, or military strategy. Those who adopt the political struggle paradigm assume that actors are co-participants in a political struggle who may find opponents or allies on either side of the border and whose behavior should be governed by principles of political responsibility. But neither proponents of the war paradigm nor the political struggle paradigm do enough to acknowledge these assumptions or their connection to their chosen paradigms. Identifying the assumptions at the base of each paradigm is a prerequisite to making a conscientious choice between them.
My examination of the democratic costs of adopting the war paradigm further facilitates such conscientious choice. Perhaps these costs will sometimes be worth bearing. But to make informed judgments about whether they are, we must first have a thorough understanding of what they are. Though there are others who adopt the political struggle paradigm—some for reasons related to their democratic commitments—my analysis has yielded an original (and more detailed) account of the democratic costs adopting the war paradigm generates for transnational politics. This, in turn, has allowed me to illustrate—in conversation with empirical scholarship on framing effects—how rejecting the war paradigm in favor of the political struggle paradigm may facilitate cross-border political spaces becoming sites of genuinely democratic politics.
Cross-border politics that does not take the form of literal kinetic warfare has the potential to be democratic in ways battle is not. But participants risk squandering this potential when they unreflectively use the war paradigm to understand their circumstances and guide their behavior. Similarly, theorists may miss an opportunity to understand and encourage novel forms of democratic politics if they do the same. This makes exercising care in choosing between the war paradigm and the political struggle paradigm especially important. After all, politics is not just war by other means.
我把这样的案例——包括动力因素和非动力因素的跨境政治接触——称为混合案例如何理解混合情况下的非动力因素还不是很明显。我们是否应该将它们理解为战争——“敌人”之间的冲突,这些冲突被锁定在一种“激进的敌对关系”中,其主要任务是相互伤害,其主要的规范性困境是他们被允许造成多大程度的伤害和什么样的伤害(见Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)?或者我们应该把它们理解为某种(其他)政治斗争?采用哪一种分析框架的问题很重要,因为,我认为,理解战争等混合情况的非动力因素会带来严重的民主成本。在《反叛乱》中,将记者、活动家和叛乱分子的平民伤亡报告理解为战争行为,意味着将其视为旨在造成伤害(通过削弱“敌人”力量)的行为,以及其目的和价值充其量与事实无关的战略沟通。这将意味着把他们的作者视为潜在的攻击对象——正如格罗斯所做的那样,他将记者描述为“媒体战争的步兵”(2015年,第300页),并认为他们因此容易受到伤害,包括“被捕、监禁、驱逐或销毁或没收他们的设备”(2015年,第269页)。这将意味着把他们的观众视为宣传者操纵的棋子。将平民伤亡报告理解为政治斗争的一部分,意味着将其视为一种声明,可以提供信息,激发批判性反思,并形成民主审议和竞争的基础——这可能不局限于一个国家的边界内。这将意味着把它们的作者视为值得真正考虑的潜在重大主张的来源,把它们的读者视为能够判断和真诚地回应这些主张的对话者。现有的学术研究通常没有明确认识到是否应该理解战争或政治斗争等混合案例的非动力因素的问题,更不用说明确评估做出一种选择或另一种选择的成本和收益了尽管如此,一些人(例如Blank, 2017;生产总值(gdp), 2015;总,刘振前,2017;Kittrie, 2016;Walzer, 2017)更倾向于将它们视为战争,而其他人(例如,Jurkevics, 2019;Miller, 2010,第247-57页;米勒,2018;Valdez, 2019a, 2019b)倾向于把它们更像是政治斗争。在这里,我明确了这两种方法背后的隐含假设,认为采用战争范式(将混合情况的非动力因素理解为“战争”)具有重大的民主成本,并认为采用替代的政治斗争范式可以减轻这些成本。更具体地说,对战争模式的过度依赖削弱了跨境政治成为——并被公认为——真正民主政治场所的潜力。它通过三种方式做到了这一点。首先,它将全球政治参与者呈现为陷入“一种激进的敌对关系”的敌人(Walzer, 2017, p. xiii),致力于相互伤害和征服。这掩盖了他们发展相互尊重关系的可能性,这种关系有利于相互学习和跨国界的团结合作——正是这种关系最能促进民主政治。其次,采用战争范式鼓励了一种假设,即跨境政治的参与者只是为他们的战争战略服务,而不是推进潜在的民主审议或政治斗争。这种假设的盛行反过来又会改变人们参与跨境政治的机构(如媒体)——将它们从民主政治的潜在催化剂转变为交战各方实施战争努力的工具。第三,如果人们认为跨境政治的参与者只是为了推进战争战略,他们可能会过早地低估参与者的合法道德论点,假设这些论点纯粹是工具性的。虽然采用战争范式有可能招致这些民主成本,但我认为我们可以通过采用政治斗争范式来减轻这些成本。这种替代性范式将跨境政治的参与者视为共同政治斗争的参与者,他们不一定会寻求伤害或摧毁对手,他们可能会以战斗人员不会的方式修改他们的目标,他们的行为应该主要受政治责任原则(而不是正义战争原则或军事战略原则)的支配。此外,根据政治斗争范式,边界不必将对手与盟友明确区分开来。下面,我将更彻底地定义战争范式。 这种替代性范式将跨境政治的参与者视为共同政治斗争的参与者,他们不一定会寻求伤害或摧毁对手,他们可能会以战斗人员不会的方式修改他们的目标,他们的行为应该主要受政治责任原则(而不是正义战争原则或军事战略原则)的支配。此外,根据政治斗争范式,边界不需要将对手与盟友明确区分开来下面,我将更彻底地定义战争范式。然后,我认为,过度依赖它会破坏跨境政治以上述三种方式成为(并被认可为)真正民主政治场所的潜力。最后,我概述了另一种政治斗争范式,并认为采用它可以减轻与战争范式相关的民主成本。我并不是说我们永远不应该使用战争模式。也许有时我们应该承担它的民主代价。一些认为跨境政治民主化没有价值的人可能会认为战争模式的民主成本在道德上是微不足道的。我不会试图在这里为民主辩护,反对它的批评者。但是,理解采用战争模式的民主代价,是对这些代价是否值得承担做出任何可信判断的先决条件——甚至是一个值得承担的可信判断。我在这里通过说明战争范式的民主成本以及如何采用替代范式来减轻这些成本来实现这种理解。在揭示跨境政治民主化的新障碍(过度依赖战争范式)时,我的论点可能对跨国民主的支持者具有重要意义(例如,Benhabib, 2005年,2009年;Bohman, 2007),但对于任何有兴趣诚实地评估民主成本和使用一个或另一个分析框架来理解跨境政治的利益的人来说,它们仍然很重要。战争范式是对政治活动进行概念化和分析的一种特殊方式。只有当这样的活动涉及具有对立目的的行动者时,才有可能使用战争范式,所以我将假设在我讨论的所有情况下都是如此。采用战争范式来分析政治活动意味着将参与者视为陷入“一种彻底的对抗关系”(Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)。Walzer在撰写不采用传统动能战(“软战争”)形式的冲突时,说明了如何将这些冲突识别为“战争”,包括将这种对抗关系作为核心特征:“‘我们’试图伤害那些试图伤害‘我们’的敌人。“在这种战争中,就像在任何其他战争中一样,战斗人员需要知道什么伤害是允许的,什么伤害是不允许的,谁可以成为目标,谁不能成为目标”(Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)。Walzer在格罗斯和梅塞尔斯(2017a, p. 1)编辑的《软战争》一书中写道,该书提出了许多政治参与模式,包括“所有非动态措施,无论是有说服力的还是强制性的,包括网络战和经济制裁;媒体战和宣传,非暴力抵抗和公民不服从,抵制和“法律战”作为“战争”的形式——尽管是“软”的形式。公平地说,沃尔泽并没有主张我们应该总是把这些交战模式理解为“战争”,而是阐明了这样做的(一些)含义。他强调了当我们将一项活动归类为“战争”时所做的一些假设。也就是说,他阐明了一些隐含在战争范式下的假设,我想在这里明确说明。具体来说,沃尔泽指出,在“战争”中,每一个行动者的主要任务是伤害对方,直到他们被击败。每个行为者面临的主要规范性问题是:我给敌人造成多大程度的伤害和什么样的伤害是合理的(见Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)?这并不意味着这种完全对立的关系必须是政治遭遇中唯一合适的战争模式。即使是战争中的敌人也可能分享友谊、家庭关系、浪漫关系和仁慈的行为。但是选择用战争的范式来分析他们的政治活动就是选择把他们作为敌人的身份作为他们的中心身份,他们的任务是伤害他们的敌人来实现他们自己的目的,这是他们的中心任务,他们应该给敌人造成多大程度的伤害和什么样的伤害这是他们的中心规范困境。选择使用战争范式来分析政治活动,就是选择将政治参与者的身份、任务和规范困境(由其他(不太激进的敌对)关系定义)视为边缘。 然后,我认为,过度依赖它会破坏跨境政治以上述三种方式成为(并被认可为)真正民主政治场所的潜力。最后,我概述了另一种政治斗争范式,并认为采用它可以减轻与战争范式相关的民主成本。我并不是说我们永远不应该使用战争模式。也许有时我们应该承担它的民主代价。一些认为跨境政治民主化没有价值的人可能会认为战争模式的民主成本在道德上是微不足道的。我不会试图在这里为民主辩护,反对它的批评者。但是,理解采用战争模式的民主代价,是对这些代价是否值得承担做出任何可信判断的先决条件——甚至是一个值得承担的可信判断。我在这里通过说明战争范式的民主成本以及如何采用替代范式来减轻这些成本来实现这种理解。在揭示跨境政治民主化的新障碍(过度依赖战争范式)时,我的论点可能对跨国民主的支持者具有重要意义(例如,Benhabib, 2005年,2009年;Bohman, 2007),但对于任何有兴趣诚实地评估民主成本和使用一个或另一个分析框架来理解跨境政治的利益的人来说,它们仍然很重要。战争范式是对政治活动进行概念化和分析的一种特殊方式。只有当这样的活动涉及具有对立目的的行动者时,才有可能使用战争范式,所以我将假设在我讨论的所有情况下都是如此。采用战争范式来分析政治活动意味着将参与者视为陷入“一种彻底的对抗关系”(Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)。Walzer在撰写不采用传统动能战(“软战争”)形式的冲突时,说明了如何将这些冲突识别为“战争”,包括将这种对抗关系作为核心特征:“‘我们’试图伤害那些试图伤害‘我们’的敌人。“在这种战争中,就像在任何其他战争中一样,战斗人员需要知道什么伤害是允许的,什么伤害是不允许的,谁可以成为目标,谁不能成为目标”(Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)。Walzer在格罗斯和梅塞尔斯(2017a, p. 1)编辑的《软战争》一书中写道,该书提出了许多政治参与模式,包括“所有非动态措施,无论是有说服力的还是强制性的,包括网络战和经济制裁;媒体战和宣传,非暴力抵抗和公民不服从,抵制和“法律战”作为“战争”的形式——尽管是“软”的形式。公平地说,沃尔泽并没有主张我们应该总是把这些交战模式理解为“战争”,而是阐明了这样做的(一些)含义。他强调了当我们将一项活动归类为“战争”时所做的一些假设。也就是说,他阐明了一些隐含在战争范式下的假设,我想在这里明确说明。具体来说,沃尔泽指出,在“战争”中,每一个行动者的主要任务是伤害对方,直到他们被击败。每个行为者面临的主要规范性问题是:我给敌人造成多大程度的伤害和什么样的伤害是合理的(见Walzer, 2017, p. xiii)?这并不意味着这种完全对立的关系必须是政治遭遇中唯一合适的战争模式。即使是战争中的敌人也可能分享友谊、家庭关系、浪漫关系和仁慈的行为。但是选择用战争的范式来分析他们的政治活动就是选择把他们作为敌人的身份作为他们的中心身份,他们的任务是伤害他们的敌人来实现他们自己的目的,这是他们的中心任务,他们应该给敌人造成多大程度的伤害和什么样的伤害这是他们的中心规范困境。选择使用战争范式来分析政治活动,就是选择将政治参与者的身份、任务和规范困境(由其他(不太激进的敌对)关系定义)视为边缘。换句话说,用战争范式来分析政治活动意味着从对抗的角度来分析。运用战争范式还涉及对应该支配政治行为者行为的原则做出某些假设,尽管它所需要的具体假设因其所扮演的角色而异。 换句话说,用战争范式来分析政治活动意味着从对抗的角度来分析。运用战争范式还涉及对应该支配政治行为者行为的原则做出某些假设,尽管它所需要的具体假设因其所扮演的角色而异。例如,对于政治理论家来说,使用战争范式涉及诉诸“正义战争”原则,如正当理由(战争应仅出于特定原因发动),最后手段(战争应仅在其他选择已用尽后发动),歧视(交战各方应仅攻击合法目标),必要性(每一场战争都应是实现合法目的所必需的),3、相称性(无论战争作为一个整体还是任何单独的战争行为,都不应造成与其所承诺的利益相比过大的损害)对于法律分析师来说,采用战争范式意味着假设行为应主要受武装冲突法(LOAC)的支配,该法“支配武装冲突期间国家、个人和非国家行为体的行为”,并且主要基于正义战争原则(Blank, 2017, pp. 90-91)。对于军事领导人来说,采用战争范式意味着假设行为应该主要受军事战略原则的支配,这也可能包括或受到正义战争原则的约束。澄清了什么是“战争范式”之后,我现在可以评估使用它来分析跨境政治混合情况下的非动力因素的成本。在质疑我们是否应该使用战争范式来分析不是字面上的战争的活动时,我同情正义的倡导者,他们认为我们不应该使用正义战争理论来分析短期战争武力的使用(见Brunstetter, 2021;Brunstetter & Braun, 2013;有关唯命是文献的回顾,请参阅Galliott, 2019)。然而,依法治罪的理论家仍然关注武力的使用。事实上,Brunstetter(2021,第8页)明确地将他的讨论局限于“涉及动能、致命力量”的行为。相反,我关注的是跨境冲突的非动力因素。因此,我的分析提供了对唯法文献的必要补充——揭示了另一个领域(混合冲突背景下的非动态交战),在这个领域中,过度依赖战争范式具有显著的缺点,并最终说明了采用替代的政治斗争范式如何减轻这些缺点。首先,运用战争范式来分析混合案例的非动态因素,包括采用——或鼓励他人采用——一种对抗性的观点,这种观点将边界两侧的参与者视为陷入彻底对抗关系的“敌人”。这反过来又破坏了民主,因为它阻碍了有利于相互学习的尊重关系的形成和承认,并关闭了跨国界团结合作的可能性。我的论点的这一部分类似于Mouffe(2000,第101-104页)的观点,即当政治对手将彼此视为“要被摧毁的敌人”(2000,第102页)时,多元民主就会受到阻碍,而当他们将彼此视为有权在政治舞台上推广自己观点的合法对手时,多元民主就会得以实现。然而,我的观点在关键方面与墨菲的不同——最重要的是,它对国际背景的关注。此外,当Mouffe(2009)考虑到她的民主理论对国际关系的影响时,她得出结论,我们应该努力建立一个“多极”世界,将其划分为不同的地区,每个地区根据自己的文化和价值观进行治理,每个地区制定自己的民主形式,所有这些都被认为是合法的。但这并没有告诉我们,超越墨菲的地区边界的政治活动是民主的,需要什么条件。这就是我在这里提出的问题。墨菲(2009,第553页)接受将世界划分为不同的“集团”,并设想当这些集团中没有一个试图将其价值观强加给其他集团时,民主是最好的。相反,我探索社会之间的间隙空间(在许多情况下是地区或“集团”之间的空间)本身如何成为民主政治的场所,以及什么可能破坏其民主潜力。同样值得注意的是,我的论点(不像墨菲的)应该被广泛的民主理论家所接受,而不仅仅是激动论者。我的论点并不依赖于任何一种民主概念——只依赖于民主存在的几个先决条件,这些条件得到了广泛的民主理论家的认可,他们主张不同的民主概念。除了使我的观点更加普世化之外,这意味着我避免了Mouffe(2009)与一些自由主义民主理论认同的陷阱——他们只承认一种民主模式是合法的。 例如,对于政治理论家来说,使用战争范式涉及诉诸“正义战争”原则,如正当理由(战争应仅出于特定原因发动),最后手段(战争应仅在其他选择已用尽后发动),歧视(交战各方应仅攻击合法目标),必要性(每一场战争都应是实现合法目的所必需的),3、相称性(无论战争作为一个整体还是任何单独的战争行为,都不应造成与其所承诺的利益相比过大的损害)对于法律分析师来说,采用战争范式意味着假设行为应主要受武装冲突法(LOAC)的支配,该法“支配武装冲突期间国家、个人和非国家行为体的行为”,并且主要基于正义战争原则(Blank, 2017, pp. 90-91)。对于军事领导人来说,采用战争范式意味着假设行为应该主要受军事战略原则的支配,这也可能包括或受到正义战争原则的约束。澄清了什么是“战争范式”之后,我现在可以评估使用它来分析跨境政治混合情况下的非动力因素的成本。在质疑我们是否应该使用战争范式来分析不是字面上的战争的活动时,我同情正义的倡导者,他们认为我们不应该使用正义战争理论来分析短期战争武力的使用(见Brunstetter, 2021;Brunstetter,布劳恩,2013;有关唯命是文献的回顾,请参阅Galliott, 2019)。然而,依法治罪的理论家仍然关注武力的使用。事实上,Brunstetter(2021,第8页)明确地将他的讨论局限于“涉及动能、致命力量”的行为。相反,我关注的是跨境冲突的非动力因素。因此,我的分析提供了对唯法文献的必要补充——揭示了另一个领域(混合冲突背景下的非动态交战),在这个领域中,过度依赖战争范式具有显著的缺点,并最终说明了采用替代的政治斗争范式如何减轻这些缺点。鉴于依赖战争范式来分析跨境政治可能会破坏后者的民主潜力,我提出了另一种范式:政治斗争范式。通过采用政治斗争范式,我们可以减轻与战争范式相关的民主成本。采用战争范式涉及到通过对抗性的视角来分析跨境政治,这种视角将边界对面的人视为必须试图伤害和击败对方的敌人,而采用政治斗争范式涉及到使用共同参与者的视角,将边界对面的人视为政治斗争的共同参与者。有些是对手,有些是盟友,边界并不一定能将对手和盟友明确区分开来。此外,虽然典型政治斗争的参与者确实寻求政治“胜利”,但他们并不一定像交战人员那样寻求伤害或摧毁他们的对手。而且,面对来自对手的批评和反击,他们可能愿意修改自己的目标,而交战的战士则不会这么做。政治斗争范式是普世的,因为它可以被协商/联合主义者和斗争主义民主理论家所采用毕竟,强调旨在达成共识的审议重要性的联合主义者不必否认反对可以成为民主政治的一部分。事实上,最初的分歧使得争论性的妥协成为必要(和可能),像克里斯蒂亚诺(2004,第275-276页)、布拉杰·德·拉·加尔萨(n.d,第12-13页)和杨(2000,第3,6页)这样的理论家将其视为民主的核心特征。同样,将冲突和争论视为民主政治特有的斗争论者也不需要将这种冲突概念化为战争的一种形式。请注意霍尼格在《政治理论与政治置换》(Political Theory and Displacement of Politics)一书中对她的作品的描述(“这本书制定了virtù的斗争,渗透和占领对手”),她直接将其与一种更像战争的方法(“而不是(像荷马史诗中的斗争一样)高贵地摧毁或击败他们”)进行了对比(Maxwell et al., 2019, p. 662)。回想一下墨菲(2000年,第101-103页)对“对抗”(将对手视为“要消灭的敌人”(2000年,第102页)和她更喜欢的民主政治模式“对抗主义”(将对手视为合法的对手)的区分。政治斗争范式的另一个显著特征是它所说的应该支配行动者行为的原则。战争范式假定行为者的行为应受正义战争原则、LOAC或军事战略的支配。 但是,采用政治斗争范式意味着假设行为者的行为应该受到政治责任原则的约束——这些原则概述了个人在创造和支持公正的制度和社会结构以及反对现有不公正方面的责任。一个例子是,一个原则告诉我们,在存在公正制度的地方支持它们,在没有公正制度的地方帮助创建它们,这与罗尔斯的自然正义义务是一致的(罗尔斯,1999,第99页)。杨(2006)的原则要求我们与他人(也许是在全球范围内)一起采取集体行动,拆除我们帮助延续的不公正的社会结构,这是另一个原则。当我们使用政治斗争范式分析跨境政治时,我们面临的核心道德问题与我们使用战争范式时面临的问题不同。用Walzer (2017, p. xiii)的话来说,战争范式促使我们提出这样的问题:政治行为者应该对边境另一边的敌人造成多大程度的伤害和什么样的伤害?相反,政治斗争范式促使我们提出这样的问题:政治行动者应该以何种方式与他人一起参与旨在实现(他们所认为的)正义的斗争?他们应该寻求谁(在边界的两边)作为盟友,又应该将谁(在边界的两边)视为政治对手?为了说明理论家使用政治斗争范式分析跨境政治会是什么样子,我们可以转向Valdez (2019a, 2019b)对“西方”社会种族主义反对者和西方以外殖民压迫反对者之间跨国政治联盟的研究。米勒(2010,第247-257页)对“前景共同体”的描述致力于他所谓的“全球社会民主主义”,并参与旨在结束全球不公正、不平等、统治和剥削的社会运动,这是另一个很好的例子。Jurkevics(2019)对参与政治争论的人的描述也是如此,这些争论涉及多个重叠的司法管辖区,他们受到政治权力的约束。关于参与这种政治斗争的行动者的突出的规范性问题包括(对于Valdez, 20119a, 20119b和Miller, 2010,特别是第9条)他们应该如何与他人合作,以反对帝国主义或新帝国主义列强带来的全球不公正、统治和剥削,以及(对于Jurkevics,2019年)他们应该如何参与和维护民主决策过程,即使这需要行使和追究超越国界的政治权力。换句话说,参与者的核心行为要求不是由正义战争原则、LOAC或军事战略决定的,而是由表明他们如何能够和应该与他人一起采取政治行动来反对不公正的原则决定的。我们可以想象,如果布兰克采用这种观点而不是战争范式,她的分析将会有多么不同。声称一次袭击造成太多平民死亡和媒体对这种说法的真实报道不会被认为是阻止合法袭击的卑鄙企图,因为这些袭击来自边界另一边的“敌人”,或似乎是为他们的利益服务,因此必须加以怀疑。对这些报道表示愤怒或反对军事活动的全球公众不会被视为不知情的被聪明的叛乱分子愚弄,操纵他们的情绪反应,使他们反对进攻的军队。媒体对平民伤亡的报道也不会被迫成为攻击国战争努力的全面工具,因为它不会被视为一种战争工具,必须被交战一方完全利用,以避免对“敌人”有利。因此,从战争范式转向政治斗争范式可以减轻前者的民主成本。如果那些参与跨境政治的人实现了这种转变,他们将不再把对方视为必须被征服的敌人,而是将对方视为政治斗争的共同参与者,他们可能成为对手,也可能成为盟友,并可能从彼此的见解中吸取教训。他们将不再把域外国家的主权要求视为为实现战争目标而精心设计的战略通信。相反,他们会认为这些说法可能是可信的,值得认真考虑。最后,如果参与者认识到像媒体这样的机构是民主政治斗争的组成部分,而不是将它们视为一个或另一个交战政党的工具,他们就不太可能将这些机构变成纯粹的战争武器,从而摧毁他们的民主潜力。 杜波依斯反对种族主义和帝国的跨国行动主义(见Valdez, 2019b)说明了跨境政治参与者采用政治斗争范式的情况,以及这如何使他们的政治活动变得真正民主——即使是在暴力频发的背景下。杜波依斯的行动主义只是众多例子中的一个。历史上还有无数其他的公民社会行动者,他们可以说是拒绝了战争范式,而支持政治斗争范式。例如,越南、美国和加拿大的女权主义者在反对美国在越南战争的国际妇女运动中合作(zzu - chun Wu, 2013, pp. 193-218);乌干达牧师和刚果难民共同创立了“乌干达暴力受害儿童和妇女的希望”组织,该组织为难民和乌干达公民提供技能培训项目(Pincock et al., 2020, p. 1);或近几十年来合作倡导禁止核武器的国家和民间社会行动者的全球网络(Gibbons, 2018)。我不打算在本文中单独讨论所有的案例。相反,为了我的论点的目的,我只需要讨论一个说明性的案例来展示当参与者拒绝战争范式而支持政治斗争范式时,跨境政治会是什么样子——为此,我转向杜波依斯。我在下面讨论的杜波依斯的行动主义是非暴力的,但我们可以把它解释为反帝国主义斗争的一部分,帝国主义者和他们的对手都使用了动力和非动力的手段。因此,我们有理由将杜波依斯的行动主义视为混合案例的非动力因素。事实上,杜波依斯时代的殖民和种族压迫是通过大规模和长期的(动态的)暴力来实现的。如果反帝国主义、反种族主义行动在这种背景下可以采取民主跨境政治的形式,那么在其他暴力背景下的跨境行动当然也有希望采取类似的形式。至少,杜波依斯的例子表明,通过非动力手段进行民主政治参与是可能的,即使它是其他行动者使用动力的冲突的一部分。瓦尔迪兹(2019b)3-5)描述了杜波依斯如何培养一个跨国活动家网络来挑战帝国主义的种族化统治,他们认为这与国内的种族不公正交织在一起。杜波依斯和他的盟友们被排除在国内和国际政治机构之外或从属于国内和国际政治机构,他们为自己的政治活动创造了新的渠道,通过这些渠道,他们在彼此之间培养了团结、尊重和建设性的对话,并利用这些资源在政治上反对帝国。例如,杜波依斯主持了1919年的泛非大会,将非洲裔美国人和来自几个国家的非洲人聚集在一起,讨论世界各地有色人种的未来,并试图影响西方领导人同期在凡尔赛举行的和平谈判(瓦尔迪兹,2019b,第1-2页)。杜波依斯还参加了跨国政治活动,并在世界各地的种族压迫反对者之间建立了联系和对话——例如,通过报道重要的世界事件,并在他的报纸《危机》中纳入国际作家的贡献——他利用这些联系来促进代表殖民地人民和非裔美国人的政治行动(瓦尔迪兹,2019b,第161-175页)。因此,杜波依斯将反对帝国压迫视为与来自世界各地的潜在共同参与者寻求跨境政治斗争的盟友。一些采用战争范式的人可能会把反对帝国主义理解为“殖民者”和“被殖民者”之间的对抗冲突,他们认为,作为一个殖民者或被殖民者国家(或种族)的成员,就足以将一个人置于其中一个类别中。但杜波依斯似乎认为,根据政治斗争范式,可以在帝国主义从属的“被殖民”人民和种族群体中,以及在帝国主义享有特权的“殖民”人民和种族群体中找到盟友。毕竟,他寻求与“来自世界各地的欧洲白人和平活动家和黑人知识分子和活动家”建立政治联系(Valdez, 2019b,第165页)。杜波依斯在他的跨国盟友之间培养对话,并在这种对话的基础上推动联合政治行动。就《危机》是这种活动的中心而言,这个案例也说明了不受战争范式影响的媒体是如何催化民主政治的。事实上,我们有理由称杜波依斯的行动主义是“民主的”(瓦尔迪兹(Valdez, 2019b)。 (175)当然是这样呈现的),因为它似乎主要涉及对话、相互尊重的关系、对不同行动者的主张和论点的真诚评估,以及在政治决策过程中提升不公正的边缘化声音的努力。如果杜波依斯和他的盟友们从战争范式的角度来理解他们的行为的话,即使不是所有这些特征也会被破坏。这也说明,即使在缺乏正式的跨国民主机构的情况下,我们也可以有意义地将跨境政治描述为“民主”:杜波依斯和他的盟友没有构成一个具有选举和执行能力的跨国国家机构,但这并不意味着他们的运动不是“民主”的。同样,瓦尔迪兹对杜波依斯的处理说明,当理论家从战争范式过渡到政治斗争范式时,他们如何避免不恰当地将战争般的心态和行为投射到跨境政治的参与者身上,从而失去理解和鼓励跨境民主政治新形式的机会。瓦尔迪兹(2019b,第175页)明确地将杜波依斯的活动描述为一种“政治手段”,开创了一种“跨国反公众”,她建议我们应该将其视为一种demos。另外,采用战争范式可能会导致瓦尔迪兹将帝国的斗争理解为“殖民者”和“被殖民者”之间的对抗冲突,而反过来恰恰忽略了杜波依斯通过超越这种二元“我们对他们”框架而开启的那种政治联盟和活动。事实上,瓦尔迪兹(2019a)批评当代全球正义理论家正是这样做的,尽管她没有将这种疏忽与战争范式的采用联系起来。总而言之,采用政治斗争范式来分析跨境政治鼓励并呈现了有利于相互学习和跨国界团结合作的相互尊重关系。它阻碍了机构(如媒体)的合作或转变,否则这些机构可能会成为民主政治的催化剂,成为战争机器中的齿轮。它鼓励参与者认真对待他人的道德批评,而不是草率地将其视为“敌人”战争战略的一部分。也就是说,采用政治斗争范式为真正的民主跨境政治铺平了道路。诚然,仅采用政治斗争范式并不能保证跨境政治会突然变得民主。但是,无论培育民主政治还需要什么,通过政治斗争范式而不是战争范式来理解政治活动,都让我们朝着这个方向迈出了一步。正如我的分析所显示的,我们可以在现有的跨境政治参与文献中找到战争范式和政治斗争范式的例子。然而,使用这些范式的学者通常不会表现出他们选择了一种范式而不是另一种范式,或者甚至认为这两种范式是相互替代的。通过关注战争范式和政治斗争范式作为对立的框架,我的分析有助于更深入地理解使用这些范式的学者(通常没有反思他们的优点)。我的分析也可能鼓励人们更认真地反思在两种范式之间的选择,因为当面对竞争的选择时,人们可能会更慎重地选择采用哪种框架(Chong &;Druckman, 2007, pp. 110-111)。我还超越了现有的学术研究,明确了战争范式和政治斗争范式背后往往隐含的假设。通常,学者们只是简单地使用他们选择的框架,采用相应的假设。那些采用战争范式的人认为,边界两侧的行为者是陷入敌对关系的敌人,其行为应受正义战争理论、LOAC或军事战略的支配。那些采用政治斗争范式的人认为行为者是政治斗争的共同参与者,他们可能会在边界的任何一边找到对手或盟友,他们的行为应该受到政治责任原则的约束。但无论是战争范式的支持者还是政治斗争范式的支持者,都没有充分承认这些假设,也没有承认这些假设与他们所选择的范式之间的联系。在每个范式的基础上识别假设是在它们之间做出认真选择的先决条件。我对采用战争模式的民主代价的研究进一步促进了这种认真的选择。也许这些代价有时是值得的。但要对它们是否存在做出明智的判断,我们必须首先对它们是什么有一个彻底的了解。 虽然也有其他人采用了政治斗争范式——其中一些原因与他们的民主承诺有关——但我的分析已经产生了一种原始的(更详细的)关于采用战争范式对跨国政治产生的民主成本的描述。这反过来又使我能够在与框架效应的经验学者的对话中说明,拒绝战争范式而支持政治斗争范式如何促进跨境政治空间成为真正民主政治的场所。不采取实际动能战争形式的跨境政治有可能以战争所不具备的方式实现民主。但是,当参与者不经思考地使用战争范式来理解他们的环境并指导他们的行为时,他们就有可能浪费这种潜力。同样,如果理论家们做同样的事情,他们可能会失去理解和鼓励民主政治新形式的机会。这使得在战争范式和政治斗争范式之间进行选择的谨慎尤为重要。毕竟,政治不只是以其他方式进行的战争。