The "Wisdom of the Hour" Willed to Black Americans in Douglass's "Slavery"

IF 0.1 0 LITERATURE, AMERICAN J19-The Journal of Nineteenth-Century Americanists Pub Date : 2023-03-01 DOI:10.1353/jnc.2023.a909292
Kelvin C. Black
{"title":"The \"Wisdom of the Hour\" Willed to Black Americans in Douglass's \"Slavery\"","authors":"Kelvin C. Black","doi":"10.1353/jnc.2023.a909292","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"The \"Wisdom of the Hour\" Willed to Black Americans in Douglass's \"Slavery\" Kelvin C. Black (bio) As Leslie Leonard notes in her introduction, our understanding of Frederick Douglass's \"Slavery,\" unpublished till now, profits from being placed in conversation with his contemporaneous speech \"Lessons of the Hour\" (1894).1 One of the most striking points of connection between these two late-life works is Douglass's apparent resumption of a position he held briefly prior to his famous change of opinion in 1851 on the proslavery character of the Constitution. Namely, Douglass appears to take back up in \"Slavery\" the position he espoused in 1849 that the American people lacked the \"moral power\" to reform the institutional and interpersonal life of the nation in ways that would defend against Black subjugation.2 His career after his change of opinion up to \"Lessons of the Hour\" and \"Slavery,\" a period of approximately forty-three years, is marked by his belief that the \"noble purposes of the preamble\"3 reflect the true character not only of the Constitution but also of the \"People of the United States\" who formed it.4 However, in \"Lessons of the Hour\" Douglass states that the disenfranchisement of Black Americans in the wake of Reconstruction \"has shaken my faith in the nobility of the nation.\"5 This admission is striking given that his career following his change of opinion seems to have been rooted in the strategic, and perhaps even good faith, calculation that the moral power of white Americans could be increased and then directed in the service of Black American liberation and social equality. Douglass seemed to believe that such a thing was possible both by affirming the pervasive sense among white Americans that the nation's historical foundations and cultural touchstones were virtuous and then [End Page 25] by instructing them how to view that foundational virtue to be fundamentally at odds with Black enslavement and social inequality.6 Remarkably, Douglass's \"Slavery\" appears to do away with this long-held calculation to increase the moral power of white Americans, in favor instead of a new one that seeks to fortify the moral power or \"character\" of Black Americans to \"bear and forebear\" their subjugation.7 Conspicuously absent from Douglass's essay is his familiar defense of the foundational virtue of the nation's ideals, as articulated in the Declaration of Independence and in the Constitution. Instead, he now contends that \"[submission to slavery] implies the possession of those strong elements of character upon which the best institutions of mankind are predicted and permanent-ly founded.\"8 Statements like this one and others throughout the essay hold out the tantalizing possibility that the Black American experience of subjugation might provide better foundational virtues than the ones that allowed the American institution of slavery to stand. This call to \"remagin[e] the world,\" as Leonard describes, \"through a fresh set of ideals and ethics,\"9 is reminiscent of Douglass's erstwhile Garrisonian goal of a national moral regeneration along explicit antislavery principles.10 His late-life vision of national moral regeneration, however, appears to place its trust in the eventual triumph of Black American character instead of in the moral suasion of white Americans. Notably, William Lloyd Garrison's notion of moral regeneration also argued against violent resistance. Whereas Garrisonian nonresistance is rooted in a pacifism modeled on the life of Christ, Douglass's argument against violent resistance by Black Americans in \"Slavery\" is rooted in what he describes as a pragmatic recognition of the \"super-ior force [sic],\"11 not character, of one's oppressors.12 Douglass is not on principle opposed to violent struggle in \"Slavery\" but rather rejects it based on strategic considerations of its viability as a means for collective liberation.13 In his vindication of Black American \"submission\" as a shrewd strategy for group survival and eventual triumph, Douglass evinces a worldview more in line with Sun Tzu than with the authors of the Gospels. If we then view Douglass's late-life emphasis on Black forbearance of oppression as a tactic, we must in turn understand that emphasis as following from his assessment of the Black American predicament...","PeriodicalId":41876,"journal":{"name":"J19-The Journal of Nineteenth-Century Americanists","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1000,"publicationDate":"2023-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"J19-The Journal of Nineteenth-Century Americanists","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1353/jnc.2023.a909292","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"LITERATURE, AMERICAN","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

The "Wisdom of the Hour" Willed to Black Americans in Douglass's "Slavery" Kelvin C. Black (bio) As Leslie Leonard notes in her introduction, our understanding of Frederick Douglass's "Slavery," unpublished till now, profits from being placed in conversation with his contemporaneous speech "Lessons of the Hour" (1894).1 One of the most striking points of connection between these two late-life works is Douglass's apparent resumption of a position he held briefly prior to his famous change of opinion in 1851 on the proslavery character of the Constitution. Namely, Douglass appears to take back up in "Slavery" the position he espoused in 1849 that the American people lacked the "moral power" to reform the institutional and interpersonal life of the nation in ways that would defend against Black subjugation.2 His career after his change of opinion up to "Lessons of the Hour" and "Slavery," a period of approximately forty-three years, is marked by his belief that the "noble purposes of the preamble"3 reflect the true character not only of the Constitution but also of the "People of the United States" who formed it.4 However, in "Lessons of the Hour" Douglass states that the disenfranchisement of Black Americans in the wake of Reconstruction "has shaken my faith in the nobility of the nation."5 This admission is striking given that his career following his change of opinion seems to have been rooted in the strategic, and perhaps even good faith, calculation that the moral power of white Americans could be increased and then directed in the service of Black American liberation and social equality. Douglass seemed to believe that such a thing was possible both by affirming the pervasive sense among white Americans that the nation's historical foundations and cultural touchstones were virtuous and then [End Page 25] by instructing them how to view that foundational virtue to be fundamentally at odds with Black enslavement and social inequality.6 Remarkably, Douglass's "Slavery" appears to do away with this long-held calculation to increase the moral power of white Americans, in favor instead of a new one that seeks to fortify the moral power or "character" of Black Americans to "bear and forebear" their subjugation.7 Conspicuously absent from Douglass's essay is his familiar defense of the foundational virtue of the nation's ideals, as articulated in the Declaration of Independence and in the Constitution. Instead, he now contends that "[submission to slavery] implies the possession of those strong elements of character upon which the best institutions of mankind are predicted and permanent-ly founded."8 Statements like this one and others throughout the essay hold out the tantalizing possibility that the Black American experience of subjugation might provide better foundational virtues than the ones that allowed the American institution of slavery to stand. This call to "remagin[e] the world," as Leonard describes, "through a fresh set of ideals and ethics,"9 is reminiscent of Douglass's erstwhile Garrisonian goal of a national moral regeneration along explicit antislavery principles.10 His late-life vision of national moral regeneration, however, appears to place its trust in the eventual triumph of Black American character instead of in the moral suasion of white Americans. Notably, William Lloyd Garrison's notion of moral regeneration also argued against violent resistance. Whereas Garrisonian nonresistance is rooted in a pacifism modeled on the life of Christ, Douglass's argument against violent resistance by Black Americans in "Slavery" is rooted in what he describes as a pragmatic recognition of the "super-ior force [sic],"11 not character, of one's oppressors.12 Douglass is not on principle opposed to violent struggle in "Slavery" but rather rejects it based on strategic considerations of its viability as a means for collective liberation.13 In his vindication of Black American "submission" as a shrewd strategy for group survival and eventual triumph, Douglass evinces a worldview more in line with Sun Tzu than with the authors of the Gospels. If we then view Douglass's late-life emphasis on Black forbearance of oppression as a tactic, we must in turn understand that emphasis as following from his assessment of the Black American predicament...
查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
道格拉斯《奴隶制》中赋予美国黑人的“时政智慧”
开尔文·c·布莱克(传记)正如莱斯利·伦纳德在她的引言中所指出的,我们对弗雷德里克·道格拉斯的《奴隶制》的理解,至今尚未发表,得益于与他同时代的演讲《时刻的教训》(1894)的对话这两部晚年作品之间最引人注目的联系之一是,道格拉斯显然恢复了他在1851年就宪法的亲奴隶制性质改变观点之前的短暂立场。也就是说,道格拉斯在《奴隶制》一书中似乎重新采纳了他在1849年所支持的立场,即美国人民缺乏“道德力量”来改革国家的制度和人际生活,以防止黑人被征服从他改变观点到《时刻的教训》和《奴隶制》的大约43年期间,他的职业生涯以他的信念为标志,即“序言的崇高目的”不仅反映了宪法的真实性质,而且反映了制定宪法的“合众国人民”的真实性质然而,在《时刻的教训》一书中,道格拉斯指出,美国黑人在重建之后被剥夺了公民权,“动摇了我对国家高贵的信念”。这一承认令人吃惊,因为在他改变观点之后,他的职业生涯似乎植根于一种战略性的、甚至是善意的盘算,即美国白人的道德力量可以得到增强,然后用于为美国黑人的解放和社会平等服务。道格拉斯似乎相信这样的事情是可能的,一方面他肯定了美国白人普遍认为国家的历史基础和文化试金石是高尚的,另一方面他指导他们如何看待这种基本美德与黑人奴隶制和社会不平等的根本矛盾值得注意的是,道格拉斯的《奴隶制》似乎抛弃了这种长期以来为增加美国白人的道德力量而进行的算计,而代之以一种新的算计,即寻求巩固美国黑人的道德力量或“性格”,以“忍受和忍受”他们的被奴役道格拉斯的文章中明显缺失的是他对国家理想的基本美德的辩护,正如《独立宣言》和《宪法》中所阐述的那样。相反,他现在认为,“(屈服于奴隶制)意味着拥有那些强有力的性格要素,而人类最好的制度正是建立在这些要素之上的。”像这样的陈述以及贯穿整篇文章的其他陈述提出了一种诱人的可能性,即美国黑人被奴役的经历可能比那些允许美国奴隶制制度存在的东西提供了更好的基本美德。正如伦纳德所描述的那样,这种“通过一套新的理想和伦理”来“重塑世界”的呼吁,让人想起了道格拉斯以前的加里森式目标,即沿着明确的反奴隶制原则实现国家道德复兴然而,他晚年对国家道德复兴的愿景,似乎把信任寄托在美国黑人性格的最终胜利上,而不是寄托在美国白人的道德劝诱上。值得注意的是,威廉·劳埃德·加里森的道德再生概念也反对暴力抵抗。加里森式的不抵抗根植于以基督生平为模板的和平主义,而道格拉斯在《奴隶制》中反对美国黑人暴力抵抗的论点根植于他所描述的对压迫者“优势力量”(原文如此)的实用主义承认,而不是性格道格拉斯在《奴隶制》一书中并非在原则上反对暴力斗争,而是基于其作为集体解放手段的可行性的战略考虑而拒绝它道格拉斯为美国黑人“服从”辩护,认为这是群体生存和最终胜利的精明策略,他的世界观更接近孙子,而不是福音书的作者。如果我们把道格拉斯晚年对黑人忍受压迫的强调看作是一种策略,那么我们必须反过来理解,他对美国黑人困境的评价所强调的是……
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
0.10
自引率
0.00%
发文量
15
期刊最新文献
Decency's Requirements The Painter's Dream: Written for the Evening Gazette Author Bios Thoreau's Animal Thinking: Sympathetic Tracking to Epiphany The "Wisdom of the Hour" Willed to Black Americans in Douglass's "Slavery"
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1