{"title":"Constituer le Réel. Noétique et Métaphysique chez Dietrich de Freiberg by Véronique Decaix (review)","authors":"Brian Francis Conolly","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.a909132","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Reviewed by: Constituer le Réel. Noétique et Métaphysique chez Dietrich de Freiberg by Véronique Decaix Brian Francis Conolly Véronique Decaix. Constituer le Réel. Noétique et Métaphysique chez Dietrich de Freiberg. Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, 2021. Pp. 336. Paperback, $48.00. Dietrich of Freiberg's theory of the constitutive power of the intellect, as presented in his De origine rerum praedicamentalium, has proved unusually resistant to contextualization within the philosophical and theological discussions at the University of Paris in the last two decades of the thirteenth century. There is little indication in the quodlibet literature that any of his contemporaries were aware of his unusual doctrine, let alone interested in responding to it, and Dietrich himself provides few hints as to which quaestiones of contemporary interest he is responding to. One therefore welcomes this study by Véronique Decaix in which it is argued that \"il est irréfutable que les concepts centraux du De origine ont été forgés dans une discussion permanente avec Henri de Gand\" (223). Drawing upon and developing the work of Pasquale Porro, Jan Aersten, and others, Decaix establishes Dietrich's indebtedness to Henry of Ghent, all while providing a comprehensive and remarkably clear, detailed, and precise presentation of Dietrich's theory of the constitutive power of the intellect. [End Page 706] Particularly noteworthy is the manner in which Decaix clarifies that there are several distinct ways in which the intellect, on Dietrich's theory, exercises its constitutive power. Thus, for instance, \"categorial constitution,\" whereby certain relations and the six posterior relative categories are constituted, is distinguished from \"quidditative constitution,\" wherein a real natural thing is constituted in its quidditative being, which is at the same time the mode or manner in which the intellect constitutes its own proper object. Decaix clarifies that such modes of constitution differ not only with respect to what is constituted, but by the kind of causality exercised by the intellect. Categorial constitution is a kind of formal causality—because it concerns only accidents, and because intellect grasps these accidents \"sur une modalité déduite d'un élément extrinsèque\" (284)—whereas quidditative constitution is efficient—it is \"plus fondamentale, car elle est plus essentielle et plus intérieure\" and \"s'exerce sur la forme substantielle et cause l'étant en tant qu'étant\" (286). In either case, whether the mode of constitution is categorial or quidditative, Decaix makes clear that constitution is not creation, and does not pertain to the reality or absolute entity of the thing affected by the intellect's constitutive power. Rather, constitution in the relevant sense here entails introducing and imposing upon the real natural thing a new mode of being: with respect to categorial constitution, that mode of being is ad aliud (to be in relation to another); with respect to quidditative constitution, the constituted mode of being is quidditative being. Decaix argues that Dietrich consciously develops his theory of categorial relation within the framework provided by Henry of Ghent. She cites as evidence, among other factors, that Dietrich concludes his analysis of categorial relation with what Decaix calls the \"exacte contre-pied\" (154) to question 3 of Henry's Quodlibet IX: \"Utrum circumscripta re sui fundamenti relatio possit signari per nomen primae impositionis?\" Dietrich in effect responds: \"Si autem ab huiusmodi entibus removeamus actum rationis, tunc secundum nullum modum sunt entia quantum ad id, quod significatur per nomen, sed relinquitur sola realitas et entitas fundamenti\" (160). Question 3 of Henry's Quodlibet IX is still more important for Decaix's argument. For she sees herein more than a germ of Dietrich's doctrine of the constitutive power of the intellect. As Decaix explains, in addition to the real foundation (quantity or quality) provided by nature, and the pure ratio of relation, provided by the intellect, Henry introduces the modus characterizatus a re, whereby the peculiar nature of the foundation (e.g. the length or the color) particularizes the general notion of the pure relation (157–58). Thus, the real, particular relation, for example, \"is shorter than\" or \"is similar to,\" arises only from both nature and the intellect as joint contributing causes. In this...","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2023-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.a909132","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Abstract
Reviewed by: Constituer le Réel. Noétique et Métaphysique chez Dietrich de Freiberg by Véronique Decaix Brian Francis Conolly Véronique Decaix. Constituer le Réel. Noétique et Métaphysique chez Dietrich de Freiberg. Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, 2021. Pp. 336. Paperback, $48.00. Dietrich of Freiberg's theory of the constitutive power of the intellect, as presented in his De origine rerum praedicamentalium, has proved unusually resistant to contextualization within the philosophical and theological discussions at the University of Paris in the last two decades of the thirteenth century. There is little indication in the quodlibet literature that any of his contemporaries were aware of his unusual doctrine, let alone interested in responding to it, and Dietrich himself provides few hints as to which quaestiones of contemporary interest he is responding to. One therefore welcomes this study by Véronique Decaix in which it is argued that "il est irréfutable que les concepts centraux du De origine ont été forgés dans une discussion permanente avec Henri de Gand" (223). Drawing upon and developing the work of Pasquale Porro, Jan Aersten, and others, Decaix establishes Dietrich's indebtedness to Henry of Ghent, all while providing a comprehensive and remarkably clear, detailed, and precise presentation of Dietrich's theory of the constitutive power of the intellect. [End Page 706] Particularly noteworthy is the manner in which Decaix clarifies that there are several distinct ways in which the intellect, on Dietrich's theory, exercises its constitutive power. Thus, for instance, "categorial constitution," whereby certain relations and the six posterior relative categories are constituted, is distinguished from "quidditative constitution," wherein a real natural thing is constituted in its quidditative being, which is at the same time the mode or manner in which the intellect constitutes its own proper object. Decaix clarifies that such modes of constitution differ not only with respect to what is constituted, but by the kind of causality exercised by the intellect. Categorial constitution is a kind of formal causality—because it concerns only accidents, and because intellect grasps these accidents "sur une modalité déduite d'un élément extrinsèque" (284)—whereas quidditative constitution is efficient—it is "plus fondamentale, car elle est plus essentielle et plus intérieure" and "s'exerce sur la forme substantielle et cause l'étant en tant qu'étant" (286). In either case, whether the mode of constitution is categorial or quidditative, Decaix makes clear that constitution is not creation, and does not pertain to the reality or absolute entity of the thing affected by the intellect's constitutive power. Rather, constitution in the relevant sense here entails introducing and imposing upon the real natural thing a new mode of being: with respect to categorial constitution, that mode of being is ad aliud (to be in relation to another); with respect to quidditative constitution, the constituted mode of being is quidditative being. Decaix argues that Dietrich consciously develops his theory of categorial relation within the framework provided by Henry of Ghent. She cites as evidence, among other factors, that Dietrich concludes his analysis of categorial relation with what Decaix calls the "exacte contre-pied" (154) to question 3 of Henry's Quodlibet IX: "Utrum circumscripta re sui fundamenti relatio possit signari per nomen primae impositionis?" Dietrich in effect responds: "Si autem ab huiusmodi entibus removeamus actum rationis, tunc secundum nullum modum sunt entia quantum ad id, quod significatur per nomen, sed relinquitur sola realitas et entitas fundamenti" (160). Question 3 of Henry's Quodlibet IX is still more important for Decaix's argument. For she sees herein more than a germ of Dietrich's doctrine of the constitutive power of the intellect. As Decaix explains, in addition to the real foundation (quantity or quality) provided by nature, and the pure ratio of relation, provided by the intellect, Henry introduces the modus characterizatus a re, whereby the peculiar nature of the foundation (e.g. the length or the color) particularizes the general notion of the pure relation (157–58). Thus, the real, particular relation, for example, "is shorter than" or "is similar to," arises only from both nature and the intellect as joint contributing causes. In this...
审议人:勒·雷泽尔议员。由vacry Decaix和Brian Francis Conolly所著。构成勒·雷森哲。在Freiberg的Dietrich de Freiberg那里,没有任何的前程前程。巴黎:J. Vrin哲学图书馆,2021。336页。平装,48.00美元。弗莱伯格的智力构成力理论的迪特里希,在他的《论本源论》(De origine rerum praedicamentalium)中提出,在13世纪最后20年巴黎大学的哲学和神学讨论中,被证明对语境化有着不同寻常的抵制。在二手文学中,几乎没有迹象表明他的同时代人意识到他的不寻常的学说,更不用说有兴趣回应它了,而迪特里希本人也没有提供多少暗示,说明他正在回应哪些当代感兴趣的问题。因此,人们欢迎vsamronique Decaix的这项研究,在这项研究中,他认为“在与Henri De Gand的永久讨论中,将无法确定是否存在不确定的概念,而不能确定是否存在不确定的概念”(223)。德凯借鉴并发展了帕斯夸莱·波尔罗、扬·阿尔斯滕等人的著作,确立了迪特里希对根特亨利的亏欠,同时全面、清晰、详细、准确地阐述了迪特里希关于智力构成力的理论。特别值得注意的是,德凯在书中阐明,在迪特里希的理论中,智力有几种不同的方式来行使其构成力量。因此,例如,“范畴构成”,即构成某些关系和六个后向相对范畴的“范畴构成”,与“本质构成”是有区别的,“本质构成”是一个真实的自然事物在其本质存在中被构成,而本质存在同时也是智力构成其自身固有客体的模式或方式。德凯澄清说,这些构成模式的不同之处不仅在于构成的内容,还在于智力所运用的因果关系。范畴构成是一种形式的因果关系——因为它只涉及偶然事件,而且因为智力掌握了这些偶然事件“sur une modalit dsamuite d'un samuement extrins”(284)——而基础构成是有效的——它是“加上基本的,加上基本的,加上基本的,加上基本的,加上基本的,加上基本的,加上基本的,加上基本的,加上基本的,加上基本的,加上基本的,加上基本的,加上基本的,加上基本的,加上基本的,加上基本的,加上基本的,”和“我们的实践,确定了形式的实质,所以导致了1’samutant en tant qu’samutant”(286)。在这两种情况下,无论构成模式是范畴的还是基础的,德凯都清楚地表明,构成不是创造,也不属于受智力构成力影响的事物的现实或绝对实体。反之,这里的规定,就其相关的意义而言,就是在现实的自然事物上,引入并强加一种新的存在方式。就范畴规定而言,这种存在方式是与另一事物相联系的。就本质构成而言,被建构的存在方式是本质存在。德凯认为,迪特里希在根特的亨利提供的框架内有意识地发展了他的范畴关系理论。在其他因素中,她引用了迪特里希对范畴关系的分析,将其与德凯所称的“精确的矛盾”(154)总结为亨利的《论文集》第九卷第3题:“Utrum circumscripta re sui fundamenti relations possit signari per nomen primae impositionis?”迪特里希实际上是这样回答的:“我认为,如果我的理论是完全正确的,那么我的理论是完全正确的,我的理论是完全正确的,我的理论是完全正确的,我的理论是完全正确的。”亨利的《辩证法九》中的第三个问题对德凯的观点来说更为重要。因为她在这里看到的不仅仅是迪特里希关于智力构成力量学说的萌芽。正如德凯所解释的,除了自然界所提供的实在的基础(量或质)和理智所提供的纯粹的关系的比例之外,亨利还引入了一种特性方式,即基础的特殊性质(如长度或颜色)使纯粹关系的一般概念特化(157-58)。因此,真实的、特殊的关系,例如,“短于”或“类似于”,只产生于自然和智力作为共同贡献的原因。在这个…
期刊介绍:
Since January 2002, the Journal of the History of Philosophy has been published by The Johns Hopkins University Press. For subscriptions, change of address, and back issues, please contact Subscription Services. In addition to photocopying allowed by the "fair use" doctrine, JHP authorizes personal or educational multiple-copying by instructors for use within a course. This policy does not cover photocopying for commercial use either by individuals or publishers. All such uses must be authorized by JHP.