首页 > 最新文献

JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY最新文献

英文 中文
Husserl and Mathematics by Mirja Hartimo (review) 胡塞尔与数学》,Mirja Hartimo 著(评论)
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-05 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2024.a916722
Andrea Staiti
<span><span>In lieu of</span> an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:</span><p> <span>Reviewed by:</span> <ul> <li><!-- html_title --> <em>Husserl and Mathematics</em> by Mirja Hartimo <!-- /html_title --></li> <li> Andrea Staiti </li> </ul> Mirja Hartimo. <em>Husserl and Mathematics</em>. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2021. Pp. 214. Hardback, $99.99. <p>Mirja Hartimo has written the first book-length study of Husserl's evolving views on mathematics that takes his intellectual context into full consideration. Most importantly, Hartimo's historically informed approach to the topic benefits from her extensive knowledge of Husserl's library. Throughout the book, she provides references to texts and articles that Husserl read, marked, and annotated, although regrettably, very few of these sources are quoted explicitly in his published works. The overall picture that emerges from Hartimo's book shows that Husserl continued to read and engage with mathematics throughout his career, and, even though extensive discussions of mathematical issues are not frequent in his later works, some of the ideas he develops, for instance, in <em>The Crisis of the European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology</em>, can be read against the backdrop of the developments of mathematics in his time.</p> <p>Chapter 1 sets the method for the rest of the book. Hartimo emphasizes the importance of a methodological device that takes center stage in Husserl's work from the 1920s onward: <em>Besinnung</em>. Hartimo claims that <em>Besinnung</em> is a method to reactivate the "goals and purposes" (21) that originally motivated scientists engaging in a particular line of research. According to Husserl, as specialized research progresses and becomes standard practice, such original goals and purposes might be blurred by other concerns. When applied to mathematics, <em>Besinnung</em> thus amounts to a reflection "on what mathematicians should do, on what the genuine goal of their activities should be" (21–22). Hartimo argues that this kind of approach to mathematics comes close to Penelope Maddy's naturalism, which takes its departure from what mathematicians are actually doing and then proceeds to inquire into the ontological status of mathematical objects and theories. Hartimo identifies particularly in David Hilbert, a colleague of Husserl's at Göttingen, a vivid embodiment of what Husserl considered to be exemplary work oriented toward the ideal goal of mathematics.</p> <p>In chapters 2 and 3, Hartimo expands upon Husserl's conception of what the true goal of mathematics should be. She does so, first, by addressing the classical topic of Husserl's psychologism in his first (and only) work entirely devoted to mathematics, <em>The Philosophy of Arithmetic</em>, and Frege's well-known critical review of it. In Hartimo's rendition, Husserl criticizes Frege for his attempt to provide formal definitions of basic notions, such as equality. For Husserl, such ba
以下是内容的简要摘录,以代替摘要:评论者 胡塞尔与数学》,作者:Mirja Hartimo Andrea Staiti Mirja Hartimo。胡塞尔与数学》。剑桥:剑桥大学出版社,2021 年。第 214 页。精装本,99.99 美元。米里娅-哈蒂莫(Mirja Hartimo)撰写了第一本关于胡塞尔不断演变的数学观点的长篇研究,充分考虑到了胡塞尔的思想背景。最重要的是,哈蒂莫对胡塞尔图书馆的广泛了解,使她对这一主题的研究具有历史依据。在全书中,她提供了胡塞尔阅读、标注和注释过的文本和文章的参考资料,但遗憾的是,这些资料很少在他出版的作品中被明确引用。从哈蒂莫的书中可以看出,胡塞尔在他的整个职业生涯中一直在阅读和接触数学,尽管在他的晚期作品中并不经常对数学问题进行广泛的讨论,但他提出的一些观点,例如在《欧洲科学的危机》和《超验现象学》中提出的观点,可以在他那个时代数学发展的背景下进行解读。第一章为本书的其余部分设定了方法。哈蒂莫强调了一种方法论手段的重要性,这种手段在胡塞尔 20 年代以后的著作中占据了中心位置:Besinnung.哈蒂莫认为,Besinnung 是一种重新激活 "目标和目的"(21)的方法,而这些目标和目的正是科学家从事某一特定研究的最初动机。胡塞尔认为,随着专业研究的进展和标准实践的形成,这些最初的目标和目的可能会被其他关注点所模糊。因此,当应用于数学时,"Besinnung "等同于 "对数学家应该做什么,对他们活动的真正目标应该是什么 "的反思(21-22)。哈蒂莫认为,这种数学研究方法接近佩内洛普-麦迪的自然主义,即从数学家的实际工作出发,进而探究数学对象和理论的本体论地位。哈蒂莫特别从胡塞尔在哥廷根大学的同事大卫-希尔伯特(David Hilbert)身上发现了胡塞尔所认为的面向数学理想目标的模范工作的生动体现。在第 2 章和第 3 章中,哈蒂莫阐述了胡塞尔关于数学真正目标的概念。首先,她探讨了胡塞尔在其第一部(也是唯一一部)专门论述数学的著作《算术哲学》中的心理主义这一经典话题,以及弗雷格对该著作的著名评论。在哈蒂莫的演绎中,胡塞尔批评弗雷格试图为平等等基本概念提供形式化的定义。在胡塞尔看来,这些基本概念凭直觉即可获得,无需定义--相反,它们应该被用来澄清模糊的概念。弗雷格则反过来攻击胡塞尔对数字的肤浅的心理学解释,认为胡塞尔的解释围绕着收集物品的具体行为,并从这些物品的具体内容中抽象出来。哈蒂莫认为,胡塞尔最终接受了弗雷格的批评,在后来的《序言》中不再追求数的心理学基础,而是强调数学的主观和客观的区别,哲学家研究前者,数学家则专注于后者。虽然哈蒂莫对这场争论在哲学上的结果的判断与弗雷格的评论促使胡塞尔反心理学转向的标准解释一致,但她的一句话或许值得进一步讨论:"胡塞尔的争论是关于逻辑主义的,而弗雷格则将争论转向了心理主义,在这方面,评论家们效仿了弗雷格的做法"(50)。弗雷格认为形式定义对于平等这样的基本概念毫无用处,弗雷格对胡塞尔观点的回答可能会是什么样子,我们不妨想象一下。无论如何,哈蒂莫的重构清楚地表明,无论动机如何,胡塞尔对心理主义的拒绝并不等于对逻辑主义的接受。在第 3 章中,哈蒂莫提出了她的两个核心主张:(1) 胡塞尔是一个数学结构主义者;(2) 对胡塞尔而言,现代数学的目标包含在确定性概念中。根据(1),数学是关于系统的形式结构的,这些结构可以被分离和比较。而确定性则是系统的属性......
{"title":"Husserl and Mathematics by Mirja Hartimo (review)","authors":"Andrea Staiti","doi":"10.1353/hph.2024.a916722","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2024.a916722","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;span&gt;&lt;span&gt;In lieu of&lt;/span&gt; an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:&lt;/span&gt;\u0000&lt;p&gt; &lt;span&gt;Reviewed by:&lt;/span&gt; &lt;ul&gt; &lt;li&gt;&lt;!-- html_title --&gt; &lt;em&gt;Husserl and Mathematics&lt;/em&gt; by Mirja Hartimo &lt;!-- /html_title --&gt;&lt;/li&gt; &lt;li&gt; Andrea Staiti &lt;/li&gt; &lt;/ul&gt; Mirja Hartimo. &lt;em&gt;Husserl and Mathematics&lt;/em&gt;. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2021. Pp. 214. Hardback, $99.99. &lt;p&gt;Mirja Hartimo has written the first book-length study of Husserl's evolving views on mathematics that takes his intellectual context into full consideration. Most importantly, Hartimo's historically informed approach to the topic benefits from her extensive knowledge of Husserl's library. Throughout the book, she provides references to texts and articles that Husserl read, marked, and annotated, although regrettably, very few of these sources are quoted explicitly in his published works. The overall picture that emerges from Hartimo's book shows that Husserl continued to read and engage with mathematics throughout his career, and, even though extensive discussions of mathematical issues are not frequent in his later works, some of the ideas he develops, for instance, in &lt;em&gt;The Crisis of the European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology&lt;/em&gt;, can be read against the backdrop of the developments of mathematics in his time.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;Chapter 1 sets the method for the rest of the book. Hartimo emphasizes the importance of a methodological device that takes center stage in Husserl's work from the 1920s onward: &lt;em&gt;Besinnung&lt;/em&gt;. Hartimo claims that &lt;em&gt;Besinnung&lt;/em&gt; is a method to reactivate the \"goals and purposes\" (21) that originally motivated scientists engaging in a particular line of research. According to Husserl, as specialized research progresses and becomes standard practice, such original goals and purposes might be blurred by other concerns. When applied to mathematics, &lt;em&gt;Besinnung&lt;/em&gt; thus amounts to a reflection \"on what mathematicians should do, on what the genuine goal of their activities should be\" (21–22). Hartimo argues that this kind of approach to mathematics comes close to Penelope Maddy's naturalism, which takes its departure from what mathematicians are actually doing and then proceeds to inquire into the ontological status of mathematical objects and theories. Hartimo identifies particularly in David Hilbert, a colleague of Husserl's at Göttingen, a vivid embodiment of what Husserl considered to be exemplary work oriented toward the ideal goal of mathematics.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;In chapters 2 and 3, Hartimo expands upon Husserl's conception of what the true goal of mathematics should be. She does so, first, by addressing the classical topic of Husserl's psychologism in his first (and only) work entirely devoted to mathematics, &lt;em&gt;The Philosophy of Arithmetic&lt;/em&gt;, and Frege's well-known critical review of it. In Hartimo's rendition, Husserl criticizes Frege for his attempt to provide formal definitions of basic notions, such as equality. For Husserl, such ba","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"63 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-01-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139376413","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Power of Courage in Plato's Republic 柏拉图的《共和国》中勇气的力量
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-05 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2024.a916709
Merrick Anderson

abstract:

This paper offers a new interpretation of courage in Plato's Republic. Despite the attention that this dialogue has received in the past, scholars have been disinclined to explore the metaphysics of the virtues. I argue that courage is, by its very nature, a δύναμις of the sort described in book 5. In particular, I argue that courage is the power over reason's correct practical deliberations about what one ought to do and that it accomplishes the preservation of these deliberations in the face of appetitive threats. I then explore the implications this has for the moral psychology of the virtuous agent and the question of who can be genuinely courageous.

摘要:本文对柏拉图《共和国》中的勇气进行了新的阐释。尽管这段对话在过去备受关注,但学者们一直不愿探讨美德的形而上学。我认为,就其本质而言,勇气是第五卷中描述的那种δύναμις。特别是,我认为勇气是理性对一个人应该做什么的正确实践思考的力量,它在面对食欲的威胁时保持了这些思考。然后,我将探讨这对良性代理人的道德心理以及谁能真正勇敢的问题的影响。
{"title":"The Power of Courage in Plato's Republic","authors":"Merrick Anderson","doi":"10.1353/hph.2024.a916709","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2024.a916709","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>abstract:</p><p>This paper offers a new interpretation of courage in Plato's <i>Republic</i>. Despite the attention that this dialogue has received in the past, scholars have been disinclined to explore the metaphysics of the virtues. I argue that courage is, by its very nature, a δύναμις of the sort described in book 5. In particular, I argue that courage is the power over reason's correct practical deliberations about what one ought to do and that it accomplishes the preservation of these deliberations in the face of appetitive threats. I then explore the implications this has for the moral psychology of the virtuous agent and the question of who can be genuinely courageous.</p></p>","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"56 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-01-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139373633","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Généalogie de la liberté by Olivier Boulnois (review) 奥利维耶-布尔诺瓦的《自由谱系》(评论)
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-05 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2024.a916717
Kristell Trego
<span><span>In lieu of</span> an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:</span><p> <span>Reviewed by:</span> <ul> <li><!-- html_title --> <em>Généalogie de la liberté</em> by Olivier Boulnois <!-- /html_title --></li> <li> Kristell Trego </li> </ul> Olivier Boulnois. <em>Généalogie de la liberté</em>. Paris: Seuil, 2021. Pp. 496. Paperback, €24.00. <p>The author starts from an apparently simple question: are we free? But such a question is not as simple as it seems. This book shows that it is neither eternal nor universally asked; rather, it is a question linked to a specific culture (the West), and it has a history. This is why the author intends to draw up its genealogy.</p> <p>In order to draw up a genealogy of the concept of freedom, we must leave aside the standard theoretical framework that assumes freedom as a given. Rather, we should ask: Does <strong>[End Page 152]</strong> freedom exist? What is its nature? Should it be described as the absence of compulsion or as the power of choice? We must also be wary of any systematic approach to these questions, such as those that have opposed partisans of freedom to determinists or intellectualists to voluntarists throughout the ages. If we want to draw up a genealogy of freedom, we should rather think about the theoretical conditions that made possible the birth and the development of this theoretical "artifact," as Boulnois calls it (23). Contemporary discussions about freedom tend to debate its nature without wondering why such a concept was forged in the first place. By contrast, Boulnois takes a step back and tries to discover the nature of freedom by turning to the moment of its birth.</p> <p>Boulnois has adopted a genealogical approach in his previous books. He used it in his <em>Être et représentation</em>, whose subtitle is <em>une généalogie de la métaphysique moderne à l'époque de Duns Scot</em> (Paris: PUF, 1999). He also mentioned it in the title of a collection of edited essays, where he preferred to talk of "genealog<em>ies</em>" in the plural in order to accommodate the diversity of approaches adopted by the authors of the contributions to that volume (Olivier Boulnois, ed., <em>Généalogies du sujet: de saint Anselme à Malebranche</em> [Paris: Vrin, 2007]). In his new book, Boulnois explains his choice of the genealogical method as an attempt to give a history of freedom that might reconcile the so-called continental and analytic approaches (18). Instead of giving a simple description of theories of freedom, by his genealogical method Boulnois intends to show how the Western approach to freedom has resulted in an aporia—the very aporia that Kant diagnosed as an insoluble problem in his <em>Critique of Pure Reason</em>. Boulnois's genealogy should be distinguished from the so-called archeology as heralded by the French scholar of the Middle Ages Alain de Libera. Although both the genealogical and the archeological methods originate in the writings of Michel Foucault, and
以下是内容的简要摘录,以代替摘要:评论者 奥利维尔-布尔努瓦著《自由的源流》 克里斯特雷戈-奥利维尔-布尔努瓦。Généalogie de la liberté.巴黎:Seuil,2021 年。Pp.496.平装本,24.00 欧元。作者从一个看似简单的问题出发:我们自由吗?但这个问题并不像看上去那么简单。本书表明,这个问题既不是永恒的,也不是普遍存在的;相反,它是一个与特定文化(西方)相关联的问题,是有历史的。这就是作者打算绘制其谱系的原因。为了勾勒出自由概念的谱系,我们必须抛开将自由假定为既定事实的标准理论框架。相反,我们应该问自由是否存在?它的本质是什么?它应该被描述为没有强迫还是有选择的权力?我们还必须警惕对这些问题采取任何系统化的方法,例如,古往今来将自由的游击队员与决定论者或知识分子与意志论者对立起来的方法。如果我们想要勾勒出自由的谱系,那么我们更应该思考的是,这一理论 "艺术品"(布尔诺瓦称之为 "自由")得以诞生和发展的理论条件(23)。当代关于自由的讨论倾向于争论自由的本质,而不去思考为什么要首先创建这样一个概念。相比之下,布尔诺瓦则退后一步,试图从自由诞生的那一刻来发现自由的本质。布尔诺瓦在之前的著作中采用了谱系学的方法。他在《存在与再现》(Être et représentation)一书中采用了这种方法,该书的副标题是 "邓斯-斯考特时代的现代形而上学谱系"(une généalogie de la métaphysique moderne à l'époque de Duns Scot,巴黎:PUF,1999 年)。他还在编辑的论文集的标题中提到了这一点,他倾向于用复数来谈论 "系谱",以适应该书作者所采用的方法的多样性(Olivier Boulnois, ed., Généalogies du sujet: de saint Anselme à Malebranche [Paris: Vrin, 2007])。在新书中,布尔诺瓦解释说,他选择系谱学方法是为了试图描述一部自由史,以调和所谓的大陆方法和分析方法(18)。布尔诺瓦并没有简单地描述自由理论,而是通过他的谱系学方法,试图说明西方的自由方法是如何导致 "poria "的--康德在《纯粹理性批判》中将 "poria "诊断为一个无法解决的问题。布尔诺瓦的谱系学应该与法国中世纪学者阿兰-德-利伯拉(Alain de Libera)所倡导的所谓考古学有所区别。虽然谱系学方法和考古学方法都源于米歇尔-福柯的著作,因此不可否认两者之间存在着联系,但谱系学的目的是 "解构 "过去哲学家的主张,而不是像考古学方法那样将其抛在脑后并加以摒弃,而是要充分认识到这些哲学家的理论选择和承诺(见 Boulnois, Être et representation, 16)。因此,家谱学应该通过揭示我们思考的框架来 "解放 "我们的思想。为了解构自由问题,布尔诺瓦分四个主要步骤进行。首先,他通过考察一组相关概念(自由意志、意志、权力和行动),发现了自由意志的缺憾(aporia),即自由意志似乎既是不容置疑的,又是不可能概念化的,从而展示了自由问题是如何建构起来的。其次,布诺瓦转向亚里士多德的伦理学和行动理论,该理论设想了人类的选择,但没有诉诸自由的理念。第三,他探讨了 "自由的发明",或者说自由意志的发明(拉丁语:liberum arbitrium voluntatis),强调了三个主要时刻:斯多葛学派对世界秩序的认同;阿弗罗狄西亚的亚历山大的思考,在亚里士多德的框架内为自由意志留出了空间,即使从未对其进行命名;最后,奥古斯丁围绕自由意志这一概念对伦理学进行了重组。第四,也是最后一点,布尔诺瓦着重探讨了中世纪关于自由的争论,以及这些争论是如何将人类与自然界进行对比的。
{"title":"Généalogie de la liberté by Olivier Boulnois (review)","authors":"Kristell Trego","doi":"10.1353/hph.2024.a916717","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2024.a916717","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;span&gt;&lt;span&gt;In lieu of&lt;/span&gt; an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:&lt;/span&gt;\u0000&lt;p&gt; &lt;span&gt;Reviewed by:&lt;/span&gt; &lt;ul&gt; &lt;li&gt;&lt;!-- html_title --&gt; &lt;em&gt;Généalogie de la liberté&lt;/em&gt; by Olivier Boulnois &lt;!-- /html_title --&gt;&lt;/li&gt; &lt;li&gt; Kristell Trego &lt;/li&gt; &lt;/ul&gt; Olivier Boulnois. &lt;em&gt;Généalogie de la liberté&lt;/em&gt;. Paris: Seuil, 2021. Pp. 496. Paperback, €24.00. &lt;p&gt;The author starts from an apparently simple question: are we free? But such a question is not as simple as it seems. This book shows that it is neither eternal nor universally asked; rather, it is a question linked to a specific culture (the West), and it has a history. This is why the author intends to draw up its genealogy.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;In order to draw up a genealogy of the concept of freedom, we must leave aside the standard theoretical framework that assumes freedom as a given. Rather, we should ask: Does &lt;strong&gt;[End Page 152]&lt;/strong&gt; freedom exist? What is its nature? Should it be described as the absence of compulsion or as the power of choice? We must also be wary of any systematic approach to these questions, such as those that have opposed partisans of freedom to determinists or intellectualists to voluntarists throughout the ages. If we want to draw up a genealogy of freedom, we should rather think about the theoretical conditions that made possible the birth and the development of this theoretical \"artifact,\" as Boulnois calls it (23). Contemporary discussions about freedom tend to debate its nature without wondering why such a concept was forged in the first place. By contrast, Boulnois takes a step back and tries to discover the nature of freedom by turning to the moment of its birth.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;Boulnois has adopted a genealogical approach in his previous books. He used it in his &lt;em&gt;Être et représentation&lt;/em&gt;, whose subtitle is &lt;em&gt;une généalogie de la métaphysique moderne à l'époque de Duns Scot&lt;/em&gt; (Paris: PUF, 1999). He also mentioned it in the title of a collection of edited essays, where he preferred to talk of \"genealog&lt;em&gt;ies&lt;/em&gt;\" in the plural in order to accommodate the diversity of approaches adopted by the authors of the contributions to that volume (Olivier Boulnois, ed., &lt;em&gt;Généalogies du sujet: de saint Anselme à Malebranche&lt;/em&gt; [Paris: Vrin, 2007]). In his new book, Boulnois explains his choice of the genealogical method as an attempt to give a history of freedom that might reconcile the so-called continental and analytic approaches (18). Instead of giving a simple description of theories of freedom, by his genealogical method Boulnois intends to show how the Western approach to freedom has resulted in an aporia—the very aporia that Kant diagnosed as an insoluble problem in his &lt;em&gt;Critique of Pure Reason&lt;/em&gt;. Boulnois's genealogy should be distinguished from the so-called archeology as heralded by the French scholar of the Middle Ages Alain de Libera. Although both the genealogical and the archeological methods originate in the writings of Michel Foucault, and","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-01-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139373626","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Pragmatism's Evolution: Organism and Environment in American Philosophy by Trevor Pearce (review) 实用主义的演变:Trevor Pearce 著的《美国哲学中的有机体与环境》(评论)
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-05 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2024.a916721
Alexander Klein
<span><span>In lieu of</span> an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:</span><p> <span>Reviewed by:</span> <ul> <li><!-- html_title --> <em>Pragmatism's Evolution: Organism and Environment in American Philosophy</em> by Trevor Pearce <!-- /html_title --></li> <li> Alexander Klein </li> </ul> Trevor Pearce. <em>Pragmatism's Evolution: Organism and Environment in American Philosophy</em>. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2020. Pp. 384. Paperback, $35.00. <p>Pragmatist pioneers were young lions in the days of Darwin. Evolutionary-biological thinking infused this philosophical movement from the start. And yet the last time a major monograph appeared on classic pragmatism and evolutionary biology—Philip Wiener's <em>Evolution and the Founders of Pragmatism</em> (New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1949)—the author could personally thank Ralph Barton Perry, William James's junior colleague and eventual biographer. John Dewey himself wrote the foreword.</p> <p>Almost seventy-five years later, we have Trevor Pearce's painstakingly researched <em>Pragmatism's Evolution</em>. The author has graduate training in both biology and philosophy and is a former student of William Wimsatt and Robert Richards's (343). The book offers an intricate portrait of how debates about evolutionary biology informed the thinking of a loose-knit group of pragmatists between the years 1860 and 1910. While a remarkable variety of figures are discussed, ten pragmatists command the most attention: Chauncey Wright, C. S. Peirce, Francis Ellingwood Abbot, John Fiske, William James, Josiah Royce, John Dewey, Jane Addams, G. H. Mead, and W. E. B. Du Bois (18). Call them "the American Ten."</p> <p>Without downplaying Darwin, an overarching theme is the special significance of Herbert Spencer. Despite many specific disagreements with him (see e.g. 74, 207–8, 253–54, 281), the American Ten all accepted something more fundamental from Spencer: an intellectual framework that explains mind and morality in terms of functional relationships between organism and environment.</p> <p>After an introduction outlining what Pearce identifies as four chronological "cohorts" of pragmatists (more on this concept below), he examines the 1860s and 1870s reception of Darwin (chapter 1) and Spencer (chapter 2), showing how senior pragmatists like Wright, Peirce, and James defended evolution during this period. In chapter 2, we meet the Metaphysical Club's arch Spencerian, John Fiske, and we get a reading of James's critique of Spencer's psychology and sociology. Chapter 3 gives a highly detailed, reference-work-like portrait of the second cohort's training in evolutionary biology during the 1880s—chiefly Royce, Dewey, Addams, Mead, and Du Bois. In chapter 4, we learn that in the 1880s and 1890s, idealists like Edward Caird, Samuel Alexander, David George Ritchie, and Josiah Royce all co-opted ideas from evolutionary biology, which they apparently thought compatible with Hegelian dialectics.
以下是内容的简要摘录,以代替摘要:评论者: 实用主义的演变:美国哲学中的有机体与环境 Trevor Pearce Alexander Klein Trevor Pearce 著。实用主义的演变:美国哲学中的有机体与环境》。芝加哥:芝加哥大学出版社,2020 年。Pp.384.平装本,35.00 美元。实用主义先驱是达尔文时代的年轻雄狮。生物进化论思想从一开始就注入了这场哲学运动。然而,上一次出现关于经典实用主义与生物进化论的重要专著--菲利普-维纳的《进化论与实用主义的奠基人》(纽约:哈珀火炬图书公司,1949 年)--作者本人要感谢拉尔夫-巴顿-佩里,他是威廉-詹姆斯的小同事,也是他最终的传记作者。约翰-杜威亲自撰写了前言。将近七十五年后,我们迎来了特雷弗-皮尔斯(Trevor Pearce)精心研究的《实用主义的演变》(Pragmatism's Evolution)。作者在生物学和哲学方面都受过研究生训练,曾是威廉-温萨特和罗伯特-理查兹(343)的学生。该书细致入微地描绘了 1860 年至 1910 年间,关于生物学进化论的争论是如何影响一群松散的实用主义者的思想的。书中讨论的人物种类繁多,但有十位实用主义者最受关注:称他们为 "美国十杰"。在不贬低达尔文的前提下,赫伯特-斯宾塞(Herbert Spencer)的特殊意义是一个总的主题。尽管与他有许多具体的分歧(见第 74、207-8、253-54、281 页),但 "美国十杰 "都从斯宾塞那里接受了一些更基本的东西:一个从有机体与环境之间的功能关系来解释心灵和道德的知识框架。皮尔斯在引言中概述了实用主义者的四个年代 "队列"(下文将详细介绍这一概念),随后他考察了 19 世纪 60 年代和 70 年代对达尔文(第 1 章)和斯宾塞(第 2 章)的接受情况,展示了赖特、皮尔斯和詹姆斯等资深实用主义者在此期间是如何为进化论辩护的。在第 2 章中,我们见到了形而上学俱乐部的头号斯宾塞主义者约翰-费斯克(John Fiske),并解读了詹姆斯对斯宾塞心理学和社会学的批判。第 3 章详细介绍了 1880 年代第二批进化生物学研究人员(主要是罗伊斯、杜威、亚当斯、米德和杜波依斯)在进化生物学方面所接受的培训。在第 4 章中,我们了解到,在 19 世纪 80 年代和 90 年代,爱德华-凯尔德、塞缪尔-亚历山大、大卫-乔治-里奇和约赛亚-罗伊斯等唯心主义者都从进化生物学中吸收了一些思想,他们显然认为这些思想与黑格尔辩证法是一致的。第 5 章表明,皮尔斯的形而上学和杜威的伦理学的核心内容回应了 1890 年代关于选择作用于生物变异的原因的争论(所谓的 "因素 "争论)。最后两章展示了实用主义伦理学(第 6 章)和认识论(第 7 章)是如何注入关于进化论和更广泛的科学实验的实质性思想的。这里所提供的历史学术研究的深度和使用都非常出色。在深度方面,Pearce 利用了从加利福尼亚到英国曼彻斯特的 19 个机构收藏的特殊藏品和档案。参考文献列表(发布在皮尔斯的网站上)长达 118 页 [尾页 160],显然因为太长而无法纳入本书。在当今的哲学史中,档案研究和冗长的参考书目是意料之中的。但无论从哪个角度看,皮尔斯的资料来源之广泛都令人印象深刻。他对这些资料的运用也很有启发性。细读,尤其是论证重构,通常是哲学史学者的专长。皮尔斯采用了一种不同的方法(7),通过一种哲学网络分析来寻求解释性洞察力。节点主要是哲学家、科学家和社会批评家。与数字网络分析不同的是,皮尔斯通过大量的社会、教育和知识关系,手工连接他的节点。我们可以了解到谁在哪里、与谁一起、何时学习了进化论;在所选课程和所教课程中指定了哪些特定文本;谁攻击了谁、谁站在谁一边,等等。由此产生的网络是丰富的,尽管由于其复杂性而难以追踪。该书的精华之处在于,它利用网络产生了真正的洞察力,从而...
{"title":"Pragmatism's Evolution: Organism and Environment in American Philosophy by Trevor Pearce (review)","authors":"Alexander Klein","doi":"10.1353/hph.2024.a916721","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2024.a916721","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;span&gt;&lt;span&gt;In lieu of&lt;/span&gt; an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:&lt;/span&gt;\u0000&lt;p&gt; &lt;span&gt;Reviewed by:&lt;/span&gt; &lt;ul&gt; &lt;li&gt;&lt;!-- html_title --&gt; &lt;em&gt;Pragmatism's Evolution: Organism and Environment in American Philosophy&lt;/em&gt; by Trevor Pearce &lt;!-- /html_title --&gt;&lt;/li&gt; &lt;li&gt; Alexander Klein &lt;/li&gt; &lt;/ul&gt; Trevor Pearce. &lt;em&gt;Pragmatism's Evolution: Organism and Environment in American Philosophy&lt;/em&gt;. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2020. Pp. 384. Paperback, $35.00. &lt;p&gt;Pragmatist pioneers were young lions in the days of Darwin. Evolutionary-biological thinking infused this philosophical movement from the start. And yet the last time a major monograph appeared on classic pragmatism and evolutionary biology—Philip Wiener's &lt;em&gt;Evolution and the Founders of Pragmatism&lt;/em&gt; (New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1949)—the author could personally thank Ralph Barton Perry, William James's junior colleague and eventual biographer. John Dewey himself wrote the foreword.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;Almost seventy-five years later, we have Trevor Pearce's painstakingly researched &lt;em&gt;Pragmatism's Evolution&lt;/em&gt;. The author has graduate training in both biology and philosophy and is a former student of William Wimsatt and Robert Richards's (343). The book offers an intricate portrait of how debates about evolutionary biology informed the thinking of a loose-knit group of pragmatists between the years 1860 and 1910. While a remarkable variety of figures are discussed, ten pragmatists command the most attention: Chauncey Wright, C. S. Peirce, Francis Ellingwood Abbot, John Fiske, William James, Josiah Royce, John Dewey, Jane Addams, G. H. Mead, and W. E. B. Du Bois (18). Call them \"the American Ten.\"&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;Without downplaying Darwin, an overarching theme is the special significance of Herbert Spencer. Despite many specific disagreements with him (see e.g. 74, 207–8, 253–54, 281), the American Ten all accepted something more fundamental from Spencer: an intellectual framework that explains mind and morality in terms of functional relationships between organism and environment.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;After an introduction outlining what Pearce identifies as four chronological \"cohorts\" of pragmatists (more on this concept below), he examines the 1860s and 1870s reception of Darwin (chapter 1) and Spencer (chapter 2), showing how senior pragmatists like Wright, Peirce, and James defended evolution during this period. In chapter 2, we meet the Metaphysical Club's arch Spencerian, John Fiske, and we get a reading of James's critique of Spencer's psychology and sociology. Chapter 3 gives a highly detailed, reference-work-like portrait of the second cohort's training in evolutionary biology during the 1880s—chiefly Royce, Dewey, Addams, Mead, and Du Bois. In chapter 4, we learn that in the 1880s and 1890s, idealists like Edward Caird, Samuel Alexander, David George Ritchie, and Josiah Royce all co-opted ideas from evolutionary biology, which they apparently thought compatible with Hegelian dialectics. ","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"56 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-01-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139373632","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Newton's Metaphysics: Essays by Eric Schliesser (review) 牛顿的形而上学埃里克-施利瑟的论文(评论)
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-05 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2024.a916719
Marius Stan
<span><span>In lieu of</span> an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:</span><p> <span>Reviewed by:</span> <ul> <li><!-- html_title --> <em>Newton's Metaphysics: Essays</em> by Eric Schliesser <!-- /html_title --></li> <li> Marius Stan </li> </ul> Eric Schliesser. <em>Newton's Metaphysics: Essays</em>. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2021. Pp. 328. Hardback, $99.90. <p>Newton owes his high regard to the quantitative science he left us, but his overall picture of the world had some robustly metaphysical threads woven in as well. Posthumous judgment about the value of these threads has varied wildly. Christian Wolff thought him a metaphysical rustic, as did Hans Reichenbach some two centuries later ("Die Bewegungslehre bei Newton, Leibniz und Huygens," <em>Kant-Studien</em> 29 [1924]: 416–38). In the 1960s, the tide would turn, as Howard Stein and James Edward McGuire separately began to show that Newton's metaphysics was not just sophisticated, but often more compelling than its early modern alternatives (see respectively "Newtonian Spacetime," <em>Texas Quarterly</em> 10 [1967]: 174–200; and <em>Tradition and Innovation: Newton's Metaphysics of Nature</em> [Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1995]). Eric Schliesser's book unfolds in that same register of appreciative, high scholarship, and it attests to the enduring attraction of its subject.</p> <p>The book grew out of previous discrete papers, to which he added a few more for this occasion. Accordingly, it does not come with a master argument. Rather, it is an in-depth exploration of some key metaphysical themes in Newton. As such, it befits its subject figure, who reflected on themes and concepts while stopping short of working out systems.</p> <p>The first major theme is Newton and Spinozism. The latter does not denote Spinoza's metaphysics. In fact, Schliesser explains, Newton shared with Spinoza some weighty commitments, for example, to space being actually infinite, and to substance monism: "for Newton, there is strictly speaking only one genuine substance," namely, God (33). Rather, "Spinozism" is an interpreter's category for a bundle of three theses: identifying God and nature; denying final causation in the physical world; and the assumption of "blind" metaphysical necessity. Some counted Hobbes and John Toland as Spinozist in this sense, and even Epicurus, <em>avant la lettre</em>. Newton and his followers argued vehemently against this package, as Schliesser shows in chapters 4, 5, and 8. Their chief complaint was that Spinozism is unable to account for the "origin of motion," for a certain type of order, and for the stability of cosmological structure—and to do so in a way that "meets the standards of Newtonian mechanics" (122). This interpretive lens allows Schliesser to draw Kant in, by reading his youthful <em>Theory of Heaven</em> as a possible Spinozist reply to their objections (chapter 3). <strong>[End Page 157]</strong></p> <p>A second theme is the metaphys
以下是内容的简要摘录,以代替摘要:评论者: 牛顿的形而上学:埃里克-施利瑟的论文 马里乌斯-斯坦 埃里克-施利瑟。牛顿的形而上学:Essays.牛津:牛津大学出版社,2021 年。Pp.328.精装本,99.90 美元。牛顿留给我们的定量科学是对他的高度评价,但他对世界的整体描绘中也交织着一些强有力的形而上学线索。后人对这些主线价值的评判大相径庭。克里斯蒂安-沃尔夫(Christian Wolff)认为他是一个形而上学的乡巴佬,大约两个世纪后,汉斯-莱辛巴赫(Hans Reichenbach)也这么认为("Die Bewegungslehre bei Newton, Leibniz und Huygens," Kant-Studien 29 [1924]:416-38).20 世纪 60 年代,随着霍华德-斯坦因(Howard Stein)和詹姆斯-爱德华-麦奎尔(James Edward McGuire)分别开始证明牛顿的形而上学不仅复杂,而且往往比其早期的现代替代品更有说服力(分别见《牛顿时空》,《德克萨斯季刊》10 [1967]:174-200; and Tradition and Innovation:牛顿的自然形而上学》[Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1995])。埃里克-施利瑟的这本书也是以这种欣赏性的高水平学术研究为背景展开的,它证明了其主题的持久吸引力。这本书是在以前的分散论文的基础上发展起来的,他在此基础上又增加了几篇论文。因此,这本书并没有一个主论点。相反,它是对牛顿的一些关键形而上学主题的深入探讨。因此,这也符合它的主题人物,他对主题和概念进行了反思,但并没有形成体系。第一个主题是牛顿与斯宾诺莎主义。后者并不表示斯宾诺莎的形而上学。事实上,Schliesser 解释说,牛顿与斯宾诺莎共享一些重要的承诺,例如空间实际上是无限的,以及物质一元论:"对牛顿来说,严格地说,真正的物质只有一个,即上帝"(33)。相反,"斯宾诺莎主义 "是一个解释者的范畴,它包含三个论点:上帝与自然;否认物理世界的最终因果关系;以及 "盲目的 "形而上学必然性假设。有些人认为霍布斯和约翰-托兰是这种意义上的斯宾诺莎主义者,甚至伊壁鸠鲁也是。正如 Schliesser 在第 4、5 和 8 章中指出的那样,牛顿及其追随者强烈反对这套理论。他们的主要抱怨是,斯宾诺莎主义无法解释 "运动的起源"、某种类型的秩序以及宇宙结构的稳定性,而且无法以 "符合牛顿力学标准 "的方式做到这一点(122)。这种解释学视角让施莱瑟能够把康德拉进来,把他年轻时的《天国论》解读为斯宾诺莎主义者对他们反对意见的可能回应(第 3 章)。[第 157 页尾)第二个主题是力学的形而上学,施莱瑟在这里将几条线索交织在一起。其一是万有引力的本体论,他对此提出了一种新颖的解释:对牛顿来说,万有引力是真实的,但只是在限定的意义上。也就是说,它不是本质的,也不是内在的:"即使在创世之后,宇宙中孤独的无部分物质粒子也不会被说成是有引力的"。万有引力是关系性的:两个或多个比特物质的 "共同品质",由于它们具有共同的性质而获得(19)。另一个方面是牛顿的时间本体论--实际上,这是一个长期被忽视的微妙而困难的话题。著名的是,牛顿在《原理》中为绝对时间、真实时间和数学时间辩护。问题在于这三个限定词的含义,以及牛顿是否认为它们是同义词。Schliesser 在第 7 章中提出了一个具有启发性的观点,即 "绝对 "时间和 "真实 "时间并不是完全相同的概念;相反,它们挑选的是不同的实体。这些实体具有共同的结构,即度量和拓扑结构。这使它们成为 "数学 "时间的种类(179)。但是,Schliesser 认为,牛顿的两个时间概念并没有得到同等的证明。另一个主题是形式因果关系。它在第 5 章中凸显出来,该章探讨了牛顿关于空间是一种 "发射效应 "的不明确观点。施莱瑟解释说,在这里,"发散挑出了形式因果关系的一个种类"(147),但这是一种新颖的、早期现代意义上的形式因果关系,它来自培根,而非亚里士多德。如果空间有一个形式因果,那么它的孪生兄弟时间也有一个形式因果,这就是第 7 章的主题。上帝是它们共同的形式原因。然后在第 6 章(与 Zvi Biener 合著)中,Schliesser 补充说,对牛顿来说,定律...
{"title":"Newton's Metaphysics: Essays by Eric Schliesser (review)","authors":"Marius Stan","doi":"10.1353/hph.2024.a916719","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2024.a916719","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;span&gt;&lt;span&gt;In lieu of&lt;/span&gt; an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:&lt;/span&gt;\u0000&lt;p&gt; &lt;span&gt;Reviewed by:&lt;/span&gt; &lt;ul&gt; &lt;li&gt;&lt;!-- html_title --&gt; &lt;em&gt;Newton's Metaphysics: Essays&lt;/em&gt; by Eric Schliesser &lt;!-- /html_title --&gt;&lt;/li&gt; &lt;li&gt; Marius Stan &lt;/li&gt; &lt;/ul&gt; Eric Schliesser. &lt;em&gt;Newton's Metaphysics: Essays&lt;/em&gt;. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2021. Pp. 328. Hardback, $99.90. &lt;p&gt;Newton owes his high regard to the quantitative science he left us, but his overall picture of the world had some robustly metaphysical threads woven in as well. Posthumous judgment about the value of these threads has varied wildly. Christian Wolff thought him a metaphysical rustic, as did Hans Reichenbach some two centuries later (\"Die Bewegungslehre bei Newton, Leibniz und Huygens,\" &lt;em&gt;Kant-Studien&lt;/em&gt; 29 [1924]: 416–38). In the 1960s, the tide would turn, as Howard Stein and James Edward McGuire separately began to show that Newton's metaphysics was not just sophisticated, but often more compelling than its early modern alternatives (see respectively \"Newtonian Spacetime,\" &lt;em&gt;Texas Quarterly&lt;/em&gt; 10 [1967]: 174–200; and &lt;em&gt;Tradition and Innovation: Newton's Metaphysics of Nature&lt;/em&gt; [Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1995]). Eric Schliesser's book unfolds in that same register of appreciative, high scholarship, and it attests to the enduring attraction of its subject.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;The book grew out of previous discrete papers, to which he added a few more for this occasion. Accordingly, it does not come with a master argument. Rather, it is an in-depth exploration of some key metaphysical themes in Newton. As such, it befits its subject figure, who reflected on themes and concepts while stopping short of working out systems.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;The first major theme is Newton and Spinozism. The latter does not denote Spinoza's metaphysics. In fact, Schliesser explains, Newton shared with Spinoza some weighty commitments, for example, to space being actually infinite, and to substance monism: \"for Newton, there is strictly speaking only one genuine substance,\" namely, God (33). Rather, \"Spinozism\" is an interpreter's category for a bundle of three theses: identifying God and nature; denying final causation in the physical world; and the assumption of \"blind\" metaphysical necessity. Some counted Hobbes and John Toland as Spinozist in this sense, and even Epicurus, &lt;em&gt;avant la lettre&lt;/em&gt;. Newton and his followers argued vehemently against this package, as Schliesser shows in chapters 4, 5, and 8. Their chief complaint was that Spinozism is unable to account for the \"origin of motion,\" for a certain type of order, and for the stability of cosmological structure—and to do so in a way that \"meets the standards of Newtonian mechanics\" (122). This interpretive lens allows Schliesser to draw Kant in, by reading his youthful &lt;em&gt;Theory of Heaven&lt;/em&gt; as a possible Spinozist reply to their objections (chapter 3). &lt;strong&gt;[End Page 157]&lt;/strong&gt;&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;A second theme is the metaphys","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"25 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-01-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139373668","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Law and Physics in Leibniz 莱布尼茨的法律与物理学
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-05 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2024.a916711
Hao Dong

abstract:

In this paper I argue that there is a structural parallelism between law and physics in Leibniz since his early years, which has significant influence on the formation of his views. I start by examining Leibniz's early physical system and an analogy with juridical laws that he uses to explain the structure of physical laws. Then, I argue that this analogy stems from an envisioned parallelism between law and physics. Finally, I illustrate the significance of this legal-physical parallelism by arguing that it underlies some of Leibniz's mature views. Most importantly, I argue that the parallelism explains the origin of architectonic principles or optimality principles in Leibniz's mature physics.

摘要:在本文中,我认为莱布尼茨自早年起就存在着法律与物理学之间的结构并行性,这对其观点的形成有着重要影响。我首先考察了莱布尼茨早期的物理体系,以及他用来解释物理定律结构的一个与司法定律的类比。然后,我论证了这一类比源于对法律与物理之间平行关系的设想。最后,我通过论证莱布尼茨一些成熟观点的基础,说明了这种法律与物理平行关系的意义。最重要的是,我认为这种平行关系解释了莱布尼茨成熟物理学中的建筑学原理或最优性原理的起源。
{"title":"Law and Physics in Leibniz","authors":"Hao Dong","doi":"10.1353/hph.2024.a916711","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2024.a916711","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>abstract:</p><p>In this paper I argue that there is a structural parallelism between law and physics in Leibniz since his early years, which has significant influence on the formation of his views. I start by examining Leibniz's early physical system and an analogy with juridical laws that he uses to explain the structure of physical laws. Then, I argue that this analogy stems from an envisioned parallelism between law and physics. Finally, I illustrate the significance of this legal-physical parallelism by arguing that it underlies some of Leibniz's mature views. Most importantly, I argue that the parallelism explains the origin of architectonic principles or optimality principles in Leibniz's mature physics.</p></p>","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"79 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-01-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139373672","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Boundaries of Existence: Mendelssohn's Proof in Light of Wolff and Boscovich 存在的边界:从沃尔夫和博斯科维奇看门德尔松的证明
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-05 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2024.a916712
Matteo Favaretti Camposampiero

abstract:

By revisiting the Phädon's proof of the indestructibility of the soul, this paper casts light on the sources that lie in the background of Mendelssohn's dialogue. After discussing Wolff's use of the Law of Continuity against the possibility of natural annihilation as a precedent for Mendelssohn's argument, I show that the latter is also heavily indebted to Boscovich's argument against the possibility of contiguity in the continuum. I contend that Mendelssohn's appropriation of Boscovich's argument is influenced by Wolff's treatment of the hypothesis of the soul's transformation. I conclude with some remarks on Kant's refutation of the Phädon's proof in light of his possible acquaintance with Boscovich's natural philosophy.

摘要:本文通过重温法顿对灵魂不灭的证明,揭示了门德尔松对话的背景来源。在讨论了沃尔夫利用 "连续性法则 "反对自然毁灭的可能性作为门德尔松论证的先例之后,我指出后者在很大程度上也借鉴了博斯科维奇反对连续性中毗连可能性的论证。我认为,门德尔松对博斯科维奇论证的引用受到了沃尔夫对灵魂转化假说的影响。最后,我将从康德可能了解博斯科维奇的自然哲学的角度,对康德驳斥费顿证明的观点发表一些看法。
{"title":"The Boundaries of Existence: Mendelssohn's Proof in Light of Wolff and Boscovich","authors":"Matteo Favaretti Camposampiero","doi":"10.1353/hph.2024.a916712","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2024.a916712","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>abstract:</p><p>By revisiting the <i>Phädon</i>'s proof of the indestructibility of the soul, this paper casts light on the sources that lie in the background of Mendelssohn's dialogue. After discussing Wolff's use of the Law of Continuity against the possibility of natural annihilation as a precedent for Mendelssohn's argument, I show that the latter is also heavily indebted to Boscovich's argument against the possibility of contiguity in the continuum. I contend that Mendelssohn's appropriation of Boscovich's argument is influenced by Wolff's treatment of the hypothesis of the soul's transformation. I conclude with some remarks on Kant's refutation of the <i>Phädon</i>'s proof in light of his possible acquaintance with Boscovich's natural philosophy.</p></p>","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"Suppl 11 0 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-01-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139373677","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
JHP Announcements JHP 公告
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-05 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2024.a916724
<span><span>In lieu of</span> an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:</span><p> <ul> <li><!-- html_title --> <em>JHP</em> Announcements <!-- /html_title --></li> </ul> <h2><em>JHP</em> S<small>ummer</small> S<small>eminar</small></h2> <p>Mindful of the challenges facing young scholars working in the history of philosophy, the Board of Directors of the <em>Journal of the History of Philosophy</em> has established a program of Summer Seminars in the History of Philosophy. The central idea of the program is that a senior scholar who works primarily in some area of the history of philosophy undertakes to direct an intensive week of classes for the benefit of a small group of recent PhDs whose main research and teaching are in the relevant area. Normally, the classes will focus on one or more texts that are typically not part of the material that the participants would have studied as graduate students. The goal of the program is the enhancement of the expertise and understanding of the young scholars in their area of specialization.</p> <p>Topic: "Heidegger on the Essence of Truth"</p> <p>Instructor: Daniel O. Dahlstrom (Boston University)</p> <p>Dates: June 3–7, 2024</p> <p>Location: Boston University</p> <p>Course Description: In a note appended to the second edition (1949) of Heidegger's essay "On the Essence of Truth" (first delivered as a lecture in 1930), he contends that the answer to the question of the essence of truth is to be found in the proposition: <em>The essence of truth is the truth of essence</em>. The aim of the seminar is to shed light on the meaning and soundness of this proposition. To this end, this seminar will give a close reading of the essay, against the backdrop of (a) Heidegger's treatment of the medieval conception of <em>essentia</em> in his 1927 lectures and (b) his critical appropriation of traditional concepts of essence and truth in <em>Being and Time</em> and later works.</p> <p>The <em>JHP</em> will select up to six individuals from among those who apply to participate in five days of intense classes on the announced subject. Travel, housing, and food for the duration of the classes will be paid by the <em>JHP</em> up to $2,000. Applicants should submit a letter of interest along with a CV.</p> <p>Application: Applicants should send a letter of interest along with a CV to Prof. Eileen Sweeney (eileen.sweeney@bc.edu). The deadline for applications is February 1, 2024. Notifications will be made by March 1, 2024. <strong>[End Page 167]</strong></p> <p>Qualifications: Applicants with a PhD in philosophy received no earlier than January 1, 2018 as well as advanced doctoral students in philosophy who are writing their dissertations are welcome to apply.</p> <p>AOS: This seminar will be useful to those interested in the development of Heidegger's philosophy, the history of early twentieth-century German philosophy, phenomenology, Continental philosophy, and the metaphysics of essence and truth. <strong>[En
以下是内容的简要摘录,以代替摘要: JHP 公告 JHP 暑期研讨班 考虑到从事哲学史研究的年轻学者所面临的挑战,《哲学史杂志》董事会设立了哲学史暑期研讨班项目。该计划的核心理念是,由一位主要从事哲学史某个领域研究的资深学者来指导为期一周的集中授课,受益者是一小部分主要从事相关领域研究和教学的新近博士。通常情况下,课程会集中在一篇或多篇文章上,而这些文章通常不属于参与者在研究生阶段学习的材料。该计划的目标是提高年轻学者在其专业领域的专业知识和理解能力。主题"海德格尔论真理的本质" 讲师:丹尼尔-O:Daniel O. Dahlstrom(波士顿大学) 日期: 2024 年 6 月 3-7 日2024 年 6 月 3-7 日 地点:波士顿大学波士顿大学在海德格尔《论真理的本质》一文(首次作为演讲发表于1930年)第二版(1949年)的附注中,他认为真理本质问题的答案可以在命题中找到:真理的本质就是本质的真理。本讲座的目的在于阐明这一命题的意义和合理性。为此,本研讨会将在以下背景下对这篇文章进行细读:(a) 海德格尔在其 1927 年的演讲中对中世纪本质概念的处理;(b) 他在《存在与时间》及其后期作品中对传统本质和真理概念的批判性挪用。JHP 将从申请者中最多挑选六人参加为期五天的集中课程,学习所宣布的主题。课程期间的旅费、住宿费和伙食费将由 JHP 支付,最高可达 2000 美元。申请者应提交意向书和个人简历。申请:申请者请将意向书和个人简历寄给 Eileen Sweeney 教授 (eileen.sweeney@bc.edu)。申请截止日期为 2024 年 2 月 1 日。通知将于 2024 年 3 月 1 日前发出。[End Page 167] 资格:欢迎不早于 2018 年 1 月 1 日获得哲学博士学位的申请人以及正在撰写论文的哲学专业高年级博士生申请。开放大学:本讲座将对那些对海德格尔哲学的发展、二十世纪早期德国哲学史、现象学、大陆哲学以及本质和真理的形而上学感兴趣的人有所帮助。[End Page 168] Copyright © 2024 Journal of the History of Philosophy, Inc. ...
{"title":"JHP Announcements","authors":"","doi":"10.1353/hph.2024.a916724","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2024.a916724","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;span&gt;&lt;span&gt;In lieu of&lt;/span&gt; an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:&lt;/span&gt;\u0000&lt;p&gt; &lt;ul&gt; &lt;li&gt;&lt;!-- html_title --&gt; &lt;em&gt;JHP&lt;/em&gt; Announcements &lt;!-- /html_title --&gt;&lt;/li&gt; &lt;/ul&gt; &lt;h2&gt;&lt;em&gt;JHP&lt;/em&gt; S&lt;small&gt;ummer&lt;/small&gt; S&lt;small&gt;eminar&lt;/small&gt;&lt;/h2&gt; &lt;p&gt;Mindful of the challenges facing young scholars working in the history of philosophy, the Board of Directors of the &lt;em&gt;Journal of the History of Philosophy&lt;/em&gt; has established a program of Summer Seminars in the History of Philosophy. The central idea of the program is that a senior scholar who works primarily in some area of the history of philosophy undertakes to direct an intensive week of classes for the benefit of a small group of recent PhDs whose main research and teaching are in the relevant area. Normally, the classes will focus on one or more texts that are typically not part of the material that the participants would have studied as graduate students. The goal of the program is the enhancement of the expertise and understanding of the young scholars in their area of specialization.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;Topic: \"Heidegger on the Essence of Truth\"&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;Instructor: Daniel O. Dahlstrom (Boston University)&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;Dates: June 3–7, 2024&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;Location: Boston University&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;Course Description: In a note appended to the second edition (1949) of Heidegger's essay \"On the Essence of Truth\" (first delivered as a lecture in 1930), he contends that the answer to the question of the essence of truth is to be found in the proposition: &lt;em&gt;The essence of truth is the truth of essence&lt;/em&gt;. The aim of the seminar is to shed light on the meaning and soundness of this proposition. To this end, this seminar will give a close reading of the essay, against the backdrop of (a) Heidegger's treatment of the medieval conception of &lt;em&gt;essentia&lt;/em&gt; in his 1927 lectures and (b) his critical appropriation of traditional concepts of essence and truth in &lt;em&gt;Being and Time&lt;/em&gt; and later works.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;The &lt;em&gt;JHP&lt;/em&gt; will select up to six individuals from among those who apply to participate in five days of intense classes on the announced subject. Travel, housing, and food for the duration of the classes will be paid by the &lt;em&gt;JHP&lt;/em&gt; up to $2,000. Applicants should submit a letter of interest along with a CV.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;Application: Applicants should send a letter of interest along with a CV to Prof. Eileen Sweeney (eileen.sweeney@bc.edu). The deadline for applications is February 1, 2024. Notifications will be made by March 1, 2024. &lt;strong&gt;[End Page 167]&lt;/strong&gt;&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;Qualifications: Applicants with a PhD in philosophy received no earlier than January 1, 2018 as well as advanced doctoral students in philosophy who are writing their dissertations are welcome to apply.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;AOS: This seminar will be useful to those interested in the development of Heidegger's philosophy, the history of early twentieth-century German philosophy, phenomenology, Continental philosophy, and the metaphysics of essence and truth. &lt;strong&gt;[En","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"56 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-01-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139376662","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Philosophy and Religion in Plato's Dialogues by Andrea Nightingale (review) 柏拉图对话录中的哲学与宗教》,作者 Andrea Nightingale(评论)
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-05 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2024.a916715
Marina Berzins McCoy
<span><span>In lieu of</span> an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:</span><p> <span>Reviewed by:</span> <ul> <li><!-- html_title --> <em>Philosophy and Religion in Plato's Dialogues</em> by Andrea Nightingale <!-- /html_title --></li> <li> Marina Berzins McCoy </li> </ul> Andrea Nightingale. <em>Philosophy and Religion in Plato's Dialogues</em>. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2021. Pp. 308. Hardback, $39.99. <p>Andrea Nightingale has written a scholarly work that will prove indispensable to restoring the centrality of religion and theology to Platonic philosophy. She demonstrates that Plato uses the language of Greek religion to inform his metaphysics and his very conception of philosophy. She deftly interweaves classical scholarship with close readings of a wide range of texts in order to build her claims. She gives especially good treatments of Eleusinian mysteries and Orphic ritual. She also explores the way in which the epiphanic nature of the encounter with the Forms has a transforming influence on the philosopher's soul.</p> <p>In the introduction, Nightingale presents an overview of key "divinity markers" (8–23) present in the dialogues—occurrences in which the Forms are described as godlike, references to Eleusinian and Orphic mysteries, poetic narratives of epiphanic encounters, and references to the sacred spectacle. She also assesses why these references are so often overlooked in contemporary scholarship, noting many contemporary scholars' unfamiliarity with the specific nature of Greek religion, and a general movement toward secularism in philosophy. She acknowledges some notable exceptions (e.g. Mark McPherran's work), but she might have given attention to others as well. Specifically, Jill Gordon's <em>Plato's Erotic World: From Cosmic Origins to Human Death</em> (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012) characterizes Platonic philosophy in terms of both striving for and alienation from the divine, and Ross Romero's <em>Without the Least Tremor: The Sacrifice of Socrates in Plato's</em> Phaedo (Albany: SUNY Press, 2009) on religious sacrifice in the <em>Phaedo</em> is another example. Still, Nightingale is accurate in her assessment of the field's tendency to ignore religious language or to assimilate it too quickly to later monotheistic traditions. Her book convincingly argues that religious language can serve a philosophical purpose in suggesting how union with Beauty and the Good is experienced. The book as a whole provides precious information about many connections between Greek religion and culture that add depth and richness to particular Platonic passages.</p> <p>Chapter 1 sketches out a theory of the Forms and argues that as a group they are treated as "divine." The <em>Phaedo</em> connects the Forms to concepts of eternality, unchangingness, and intelligibility (50). Human beings can connect with the Forms through contemplation (51). Similarly, the <em>Republic</em> describes the Forms as divin
以下是内容的简要摘录,以代替摘要:评论者 柏拉图对话录中的哲学与宗教》,作者 Andrea Nightingale Marina Berzins McCoy Andrea Nightingale。柏拉图对话录中的哲学与宗教》。剑桥:剑桥大学出版社,2021 年。Pp.308.精装本,39.99 美元。安德烈娅-南丁格尔(Andrea Nightingale)撰写的这部学术著作将被证明是恢复宗教和神学在柏拉图哲学中的中心地位所不可或缺的。她证明了柏拉图使用希腊宗教语言为其形而上学和哲学概念本身提供信息。她巧妙地将古典学术研究与对大量文本的细读交织在一起,从而提出了自己的主张。她对埃利乌西尼奥秘和奥菲克仪式的论述尤为精彩。她还探讨了与 "形式 "相遇的顿悟性如何影响哲学家的灵魂。在引言中,南丁格尔概述了对话中出现的关键 "神性标记"(8-23)--将形式描述为神性的情况、对埃琉西尼和奥尔菲奥秘的引用、关于顿悟式相遇的诗歌叙事以及对神圣奇观的引用。她还评估了为什么这些提法在当代学术研究中经常被忽视,指出许多当代学者不熟悉希腊宗教的特殊性质,以及哲学中普遍存在的世俗主义倾向。她承认有一些值得注意的例外(如马克-麦克弗兰的作品),但她可能也会关注其他作品。特别是吉尔-戈登(Jill Gordon)的《柏拉图的情色世界》(Plato's Erotic World):从宇宙起源到人类死亡》(剑桥:剑桥大学出版社,2012 年)从对神性的追求和疏离两方面描述了柏拉图哲学的特点,而罗斯-罗梅罗的《没有丝毫颤抖:另一个例子是罗斯-罗梅罗(Ross Romero)的《没有丝毫颤栗:柏拉图《斐多》中苏格拉底的牺牲》(The Sacrifice of Socrates in Plato's Phaedo)(奥尔巴尼:纽约州立大学出版社,2009 年),该书探讨了《斐多》中的宗教牺牲。尽管如此,南丁格尔对该领域忽视宗教语言或过快地将其与后来的一神教传统同化的倾向做出了准确的评价。她在书中令人信服地指出,宗教语言可以起到哲学的作用,暗示人们如何体验与 "美 "和 "善 "的结合。全书提供了有关希腊宗教与文化之间许多联系的珍贵信息,这些信息为柏拉图的特定段落增添了深度和丰富性。第 1 章勾勒了形式的理论,并认为作为一个群体,它们被视为 "神圣的"。斐多》将 "形式 "与永恒、不变和可理解性等概念联系起来(50)。人类可以通过沉思与形式联系起来(51)。同样,《共和国》将 "形式 "描述为神圣的,而沉思 "形式 "的灵魂则经历了一种神化。善的形式是最高的神性,对它的追求就是与神的相遇。南丁格尔指出,这并不意味着可以完全掌握 "善"。但柏拉图认为,只要我们能够思考 "善的形式",我们就能认识 "善",并变得更像 "善"。在第二章中,南丁格尔转向了人类渴望的话题,重点是《论语》。柏拉图认为,我们人类对不朽有两种不同但相关的渴望。虽然人类渴望一种神圣的不朽,但这种不朽最终是无法实现的,而人类可以通过对善的向往,生出灵魂的 "孩子",从而获得部分的不朽。对 "美 "的憧憬可以是一种神圣的顿悟,从而产生奇迹。南丁格尔通过《荷马史诗-狄奥尼修斯赞美诗》、希罗多德以及圣所碑文等文本对顿悟的概念进行了更深入的研究。顿悟验证了希腊的宗教体系。同样,柏拉图的形而上学也通过对形式的哲学思考得到了验证 [第 149 页完]。南丁格尔对埃莱乌西尼奥秘的详细论述汇集了许多哲学家所不熟悉的大量原始资料,这对学者们解释柏拉图中暗指奥秘的段落尤其有价值。南丁格尔还对阿尔西比亚德斯进行了引人入胜的解读,认为他在苏格拉底身上遇到了神性,但却未能理解它,因此在人际关系中 "亵渎 "了奥秘(107-13)。第 3 章探讨了苏格拉底在《斐多》中关于灵魂和不朽的论述。而那些...
{"title":"Philosophy and Religion in Plato's Dialogues by Andrea Nightingale (review)","authors":"Marina Berzins McCoy","doi":"10.1353/hph.2024.a916715","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2024.a916715","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;span&gt;&lt;span&gt;In lieu of&lt;/span&gt; an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:&lt;/span&gt;\u0000&lt;p&gt; &lt;span&gt;Reviewed by:&lt;/span&gt; &lt;ul&gt; &lt;li&gt;&lt;!-- html_title --&gt; &lt;em&gt;Philosophy and Religion in Plato's Dialogues&lt;/em&gt; by Andrea Nightingale &lt;!-- /html_title --&gt;&lt;/li&gt; &lt;li&gt; Marina Berzins McCoy &lt;/li&gt; &lt;/ul&gt; Andrea Nightingale. &lt;em&gt;Philosophy and Religion in Plato's Dialogues&lt;/em&gt;. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2021. Pp. 308. Hardback, $39.99. &lt;p&gt;Andrea Nightingale has written a scholarly work that will prove indispensable to restoring the centrality of religion and theology to Platonic philosophy. She demonstrates that Plato uses the language of Greek religion to inform his metaphysics and his very conception of philosophy. She deftly interweaves classical scholarship with close readings of a wide range of texts in order to build her claims. She gives especially good treatments of Eleusinian mysteries and Orphic ritual. She also explores the way in which the epiphanic nature of the encounter with the Forms has a transforming influence on the philosopher's soul.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;In the introduction, Nightingale presents an overview of key \"divinity markers\" (8–23) present in the dialogues—occurrences in which the Forms are described as godlike, references to Eleusinian and Orphic mysteries, poetic narratives of epiphanic encounters, and references to the sacred spectacle. She also assesses why these references are so often overlooked in contemporary scholarship, noting many contemporary scholars' unfamiliarity with the specific nature of Greek religion, and a general movement toward secularism in philosophy. She acknowledges some notable exceptions (e.g. Mark McPherran's work), but she might have given attention to others as well. Specifically, Jill Gordon's &lt;em&gt;Plato's Erotic World: From Cosmic Origins to Human Death&lt;/em&gt; (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012) characterizes Platonic philosophy in terms of both striving for and alienation from the divine, and Ross Romero's &lt;em&gt;Without the Least Tremor: The Sacrifice of Socrates in Plato's&lt;/em&gt; Phaedo (Albany: SUNY Press, 2009) on religious sacrifice in the &lt;em&gt;Phaedo&lt;/em&gt; is another example. Still, Nightingale is accurate in her assessment of the field's tendency to ignore religious language or to assimilate it too quickly to later monotheistic traditions. Her book convincingly argues that religious language can serve a philosophical purpose in suggesting how union with Beauty and the Good is experienced. The book as a whole provides precious information about many connections between Greek religion and culture that add depth and richness to particular Platonic passages.&lt;/p&gt; &lt;p&gt;Chapter 1 sketches out a theory of the Forms and argues that as a group they are treated as \"divine.\" The &lt;em&gt;Phaedo&lt;/em&gt; connects the Forms to concepts of eternality, unchangingness, and intelligibility (50). Human beings can connect with the Forms through contemplation (51). Similarly, the &lt;em&gt;Republic&lt;/em&gt; describes the Forms as divin","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"18 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-01-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139373630","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Between Pluralism and Objectivism: Reconsidering Ernst Cassirer's Teleology of Culture 多元主义与客观主义之间:重新审视恩斯特-卡西勒的文化目的论
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-05 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2024.a916714
Katherina Kinzel

abstract:

This paper revisits debates on a tension in Cassirer's philosophy of culture. On the one hand, Cassirer describes a plurality of symbolic forms and claims that each needs to be assessed by its own internal standards of validity. On the other hand, he ranks the symbolic forms in terms of a developmental hierarchy and states that one form, mathematical natural science, constitutes the highest achievement of culture. In my paper, I do not seek to resolve this tension. Rather, I aim to arrive at a better understanding of how it arises, and of the different options that it presents for understanding the development of culture. I discuss three recent attempts at resolving the tension, put forward by Sebastian Luft, Samatha Matherne, and Simon Truwant, respectively. Based on a reconstruction of Cassirer's system of symbolic forms that centralizes the concept of function, I show that the most promising of these attempts, formulated by Truwant, is not successful. I then turn to Cassirer's philosophy of the cultural sciences, the implications of which for the present problem have not yet been sufficiently explored. I argue that in this context, Cassirer develops the contours of an alternative to the function-based view of cultural development. I conclude that this alternative does not resolve the tension either, but that it allows for a reconceptualization of the teleology of culture as open.

摘要:本文重新讨论了卡西勒文化哲学中的一种紧张关系。一方面,卡西勒描述了符号形式的多元性,并声称每种符号形式都需要根据其自身的内在有效性标准进行评估。另一方面,他按照发展等级对符号形式进行排序,并指出数学自然科学这一形式是文化的最高成就。在我的论文中,我并不寻求解决这一矛盾。相反,我的目的是更好地理解它是如何产生的,以及它为理解文化的发展提供了哪些不同的选择。我将讨论最近分别由塞巴斯蒂安-卢夫特、萨玛塔-马瑟恩和西蒙-特鲁旺特提出的解决这一紧张关系的三种尝试。基于对卡西勒以功能概念为核心的符号形式体系的重构,我指出由特鲁旺特提出的最有希望的尝试并不成功。然后,我转向卡西勒的文化科学哲学,其对当前问题的影响尚未得到充分探讨。我认为,在这一背景下,卡西勒提出了一种替代基于功能的文化发展观的观点。我的结论是,这一替代方案也没有解决矛盾,但它使我们能够重新认识开放的文化目的论。
{"title":"Between Pluralism and Objectivism: Reconsidering Ernst Cassirer's Teleology of Culture","authors":"Katherina Kinzel","doi":"10.1353/hph.2024.a916714","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2024.a916714","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>abstract:</p><p>This paper revisits debates on a tension in Cassirer's philosophy of culture. On the one hand, Cassirer describes a plurality of symbolic forms and claims that each needs to be assessed by its own internal standards of validity. On the other hand, he ranks the symbolic forms in terms of a developmental hierarchy and states that one form, mathematical natural science, constitutes the highest achievement of culture. In my paper, I do not seek to resolve this tension. Rather, I aim to arrive at a better understanding of how it arises, and of the different options that it presents for understanding the development of culture. I discuss three recent attempts at resolving the tension, put forward by Sebastian Luft, Samatha Matherne, and Simon Truwant, respectively. Based on a reconstruction of Cassirer's system of symbolic forms that centralizes the concept of function, I show that the most promising of these attempts, formulated by Truwant, is not successful. I then turn to Cassirer's philosophy of the cultural sciences, the implications of which for the present problem have not yet been sufficiently explored. I argue that in this context, Cassirer develops the contours of an alternative to the function-based view of cultural development. I conclude that this alternative does not resolve the tension either, but that it allows for a reconceptualization of the teleology of culture as open.</p></p>","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"89 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-01-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139373669","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1