{"title":"Trace of Stoic logic in Descartes: Stoic <i>axiōma</i> and Descartes’s <i>pronuntiatum</i> in the Second Meditation","authors":"Ayumu Tamura","doi":"10.1080/0268117x.2023.2263840","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Click to increase image sizeClick to decrease image size Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.Notes1 This paper uses the following abbreviations: AT: Œuvres de Descartes, eds. Charles Adam & Paul Tannery, nouvelle présentation, 11 vols. (Paris: Vrin, 1964–1974). Conventional abbreviations, volume numbers (Roman numerals), and page numbers (Arabic numerals) are shown in this order. All emphases (Italics) in the quoted portions have been added by the author. Reference is made to the translation by Cotthingham, et al. (CSM[K]: The Philosophical Writings of Descartes) but some portions of these have been altered by the author.2 Marion, Sur la Théologie blanche de Descartes, 380–381; cf. Brown, Turning Points: Essays in the History of Cultural Expressions, 162.3 Rosenthal, ‘Will and the Theory of Judgment’, 422.4 According to Londey and Johanson, the word ‘propositio’ was established by Apuleius as a name for what is true or false; one can not find this specific usage in literature written prior to his work. See Londey and Johanson, The Logic of Apuleius, 35.5 Abelard, Dialectica, 153.6 Gracia, ‘Propositions as Premisses of Syllogisms in Medieval Logic’, 545.7 Gracia, ibid.8 The following study analyses in detail the distinction between the terms used for the cogito: Tamura, ‘Bringing an End to the Interpretative Dispute on Descartes’s Cogito: the Cogito as Vérité, Cognitio, Propositio, and Conclusio’, 38–48.9 Ramus used ‘propositio’ to name major premises of syllogisms and ‘axioma’, as well as ‘enuntiatio/enuntiatum’, to name propositions that do not constitute syllogisms. See Aho and Yrjönsuuri, ‘Late Medieval Logic’, 83; Kneale and Kneale, The Development of Logic, 303.10 Fonseca’s Institutionum dialecticarum was used as a textbook of Logic in La Flèche. See Camille de Rochemonteix, Un Collège de jésuites aux XVIIe et XVIIIe siècles: le Collège Henri IV de La Flèche, 27. In addition, Suárez’s Metaphysical Disputations is one of the few references that Descartes himself mentions by name (4ae Resp., AT-VII, 235). Furthermore, Descartes mentions the commentaries of the Coimbrans as a textbook of philosophy with which he was familiar: ‘[I beg you] to tell me which are the most commonly used, and whether they have any new ones since twenty years ago. I remember only some of the Coimbricenses […]’ (AT-III, 185; CSMK, 154). The commentaries are long, so it is impossible to ensure that Descartes read them all, but it is useful to understand how the Latin word ‘pronuntiatum’ was used at the time.11 However, in Fonseca’s Institutiones, ‘pronuntiatum’ is used only once in a way that could be considered a paraphrase of ‘enuntiatio’, as far as I have been able to ascertain: ‘This enuntiatio, “Socrates is not an animal”, […] contradicts the antecedent. […] this pronuntiatum, “Socrates is not a philosopher”, does not contradict the antecedent. ([…] haec enuntiatio, Socrates non est animal, […] repugnat Antecedenti. […] hoc pronunciatum, Socrates non est Philosophus, […] non repugnat Antecedenti.)’ (Fonseca, ‘Institutionum’, 102) Neverthless, we should still distinguish between the two because ‘pronuntiatum’, unlike ‘enuntiatio/propositio’, is never defined in his works and such usage is highly exceptional.12 In the original edition of the Meditations, unlike the AT edition, the sentence ‘I am, I exist (Ego sum, ego existo)’ is not in italics.13 Descartes explicitly denies in his Fourth Set of Replies that his cogito was borrowed from Augustine (whatever the fact is).14 As for Cicero’s Tusculun Disputations, we can estimate that Descartes almost certainly read it. One passage in Descartes’s letter to Elizabeth clearly relies on a passage in Cicero’s Tusculan Disputations. Descartes writes, ‘It is also true that the knowledge of the immortality of the soul and of the felicities of which it will be capable outside of this life, could give reasons to exit this life to those who are weary of it, if they were assured that they would enjoy all these felicities afterward. But no reason so assures them, and there is only the false philosophy of Hegesias, whose book was prohibited by Ptolemy and was the cause that many killed themselves after having read it, as it tried to argue that this life is evil. The true teaching, altogether on the contrary, is that even among the saddest accidents and the most pressing pains one can always be content, so long as one knows how to use one’s reason.’ (To Elizabeth, 1645, AT-IV, 304); Cicero writes in the Tusculan Disputations, ‘What does cause anguish, or rather torture, is the departure from all those things that are good in life. Take care it may not more truly be said, from all its evils! Why should I now bewail the life of man? I could do so with truth and justice. But what need is there, when my object is to avoid the thought that we shall be wretched after death, of rendering life still more wretched by lamentation? We have done this in the book in which we did our utmost to console ourselves. Death then withdraws us from evil, not from good, if truth is our object. Indeed this thought is discussed by Hegesias the Cyrenaic with such wealth of illustration that the story goes that he was stopped from lecturing on the subject by King Ptolemy, because a number of his listeners afterwards committed suicide.’ (Tusculan, I, 83) See Shapiro, The Correspondence between Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia and René Descartes, 121 [n. 86]. In addition, Descartes probably relied on Cicero’s Tusclan Disputations when he introduced in his letter to Huygens the city of Ephesus, in which it had been forbidden to excel; the same story can be found in it. See: AT-I, 388; Tusclans, V, 36. In addition, according to Menn, Descartes’s phrase ‘the mind may be led away from the senses (mentem a sensibus abducendam)’ (Med., AT-VII, 12) is based on Cicero’s phrase ‘it requires a powerful intellect to abstract the mind from the senses and separate thought from the force of habit (magni autem est ingenii sevocare mentem a sensibus et cogitationem ab consuetudine abducere)’ (Cicero, Tusculan, 45). Furthermore, when Descartes says, ‘Many people had previously said that in order to understand metaphysical matters the mind must be drawn away from the senses’ (2ae Resp., AT-VII, 131), he is referring to Cicero by ‘many people’; in fact, no one but Cicero had claimed this in the centuries before Descartes. See Menn, Descartes and Augustine, 223 [n. 17].15 Ritter and Gründer, Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, 1509–10.16 It is often claimed that Descartes did not read Sextus’s Outlines of Pyrrhonism. Floridi, for example, insists that Descartes probably never read the Outlines; if he had read it, he would have mentioned Chrysippus’s rational dog when he discussed animal rationality. See Floridi, ‘Scepticism and Animal Rationality’, 52. Fine, however, refutes him as follows: ‘It is true that he never mentions Sextus by name. But his failure to do so does not show that he had not read him: Descartes does not cite anyone very often; and he likes to present himself as someone who does not spend too much time reading. Sextus was certainly available, in both Greek and Latin.’ See Fine, ‘Descartes and Ancient Skepticism’, 195–234. What is more, ‘Chrysippus’s rational dog’ is also found in Montaigne’s Essays (Book II, Ch. 12: ‘Apology for Raymond Sebon’), which was Descartes’s favourite book, but if we take Floridi’s view, it follows that Descartes would not have read the Essays. In fact, there are several similarities in content between Descartes and Sextus: criticism of the syllogistic, criticism of definition, criticism of majority rule in the search for truth, establishment of guidelines for real-life (‘everyday observances’ in Sextus, ‘provisional moral code’ in Descartes), etc. See Curley, Descartes against the Skeptics, 27; Gaukroger, Cartesian Logic: an essay on Descartes’s conception of inference 11; Fine, ‘Descartes and Ancient Skepticism: Reheated Cabbage?’, sec. 6. Of course, the content similarities between the two are certainly circumstantial. However, in view of the fact that Sextus’s Outlines was quite widely circulated in Descartes’s time, and that Descartes himself writes that ‘I had seen many ancient writings by the Academics and Sceptics on this subject [= doubting all things, especially corporeal things]’ (2ae Resp., AT-VII, 130), it is highly probable that Descartes came into contact with Sextus’s Outlines.17 Cicero’s Academica was widely circulated from the 16th century onwards. As quoted in the immediately previous note, Descartes writes that ‘I had seen many ancient writings by the Academics and Sceptics’ (2ae. Resp., AT-VII, 130). In addition, according to Menn and Brown, Descartes’s deceiving God argument derives from Cicero’s Academica. On the influence of Cicero upon Descartes, see Menn, Descartes and Augustine, chap. 5, sec. B; and Brown, ‘Descartes and Content Skepticism’, 25–42.18 Alexander of Aphrodisiensis, Alexandri In Aristotelis Analyticorum Priorum Librum I Commentarium, 177–178.19 Bobzien, ‘Stoic Logic’, 87.20 Descartes writes in the Preface to the French edition of the Principles, ‘[one] should study logic. I do not mean the logic of the Schools, for this is strictly speaking nothing but a dialectic which teaches ways of expounding to others what one already knows or even of holding forth without judgement about things one does not know’ (AT-VIII, 13).","PeriodicalId":54080,"journal":{"name":"SEVENTEENTH CENTURY","volume":"86 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3000,"publicationDate":"2023-10-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"SEVENTEENTH CENTURY","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/0268117x.2023.2263840","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"MEDIEVAL & RENAISSANCE STUDIES","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Abstract
Click to increase image sizeClick to decrease image size Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.Notes1 This paper uses the following abbreviations: AT: Œuvres de Descartes, eds. Charles Adam & Paul Tannery, nouvelle présentation, 11 vols. (Paris: Vrin, 1964–1974). Conventional abbreviations, volume numbers (Roman numerals), and page numbers (Arabic numerals) are shown in this order. All emphases (Italics) in the quoted portions have been added by the author. Reference is made to the translation by Cotthingham, et al. (CSM[K]: The Philosophical Writings of Descartes) but some portions of these have been altered by the author.2 Marion, Sur la Théologie blanche de Descartes, 380–381; cf. Brown, Turning Points: Essays in the History of Cultural Expressions, 162.3 Rosenthal, ‘Will and the Theory of Judgment’, 422.4 According to Londey and Johanson, the word ‘propositio’ was established by Apuleius as a name for what is true or false; one can not find this specific usage in literature written prior to his work. See Londey and Johanson, The Logic of Apuleius, 35.5 Abelard, Dialectica, 153.6 Gracia, ‘Propositions as Premisses of Syllogisms in Medieval Logic’, 545.7 Gracia, ibid.8 The following study analyses in detail the distinction between the terms used for the cogito: Tamura, ‘Bringing an End to the Interpretative Dispute on Descartes’s Cogito: the Cogito as Vérité, Cognitio, Propositio, and Conclusio’, 38–48.9 Ramus used ‘propositio’ to name major premises of syllogisms and ‘axioma’, as well as ‘enuntiatio/enuntiatum’, to name propositions that do not constitute syllogisms. See Aho and Yrjönsuuri, ‘Late Medieval Logic’, 83; Kneale and Kneale, The Development of Logic, 303.10 Fonseca’s Institutionum dialecticarum was used as a textbook of Logic in La Flèche. See Camille de Rochemonteix, Un Collège de jésuites aux XVIIe et XVIIIe siècles: le Collège Henri IV de La Flèche, 27. In addition, Suárez’s Metaphysical Disputations is one of the few references that Descartes himself mentions by name (4ae Resp., AT-VII, 235). Furthermore, Descartes mentions the commentaries of the Coimbrans as a textbook of philosophy with which he was familiar: ‘[I beg you] to tell me which are the most commonly used, and whether they have any new ones since twenty years ago. I remember only some of the Coimbricenses […]’ (AT-III, 185; CSMK, 154). The commentaries are long, so it is impossible to ensure that Descartes read them all, but it is useful to understand how the Latin word ‘pronuntiatum’ was used at the time.11 However, in Fonseca’s Institutiones, ‘pronuntiatum’ is used only once in a way that could be considered a paraphrase of ‘enuntiatio’, as far as I have been able to ascertain: ‘This enuntiatio, “Socrates is not an animal”, […] contradicts the antecedent. […] this pronuntiatum, “Socrates is not a philosopher”, does not contradict the antecedent. ([…] haec enuntiatio, Socrates non est animal, […] repugnat Antecedenti. […] hoc pronunciatum, Socrates non est Philosophus, […] non repugnat Antecedenti.)’ (Fonseca, ‘Institutionum’, 102) Neverthless, we should still distinguish between the two because ‘pronuntiatum’, unlike ‘enuntiatio/propositio’, is never defined in his works and such usage is highly exceptional.12 In the original edition of the Meditations, unlike the AT edition, the sentence ‘I am, I exist (Ego sum, ego existo)’ is not in italics.13 Descartes explicitly denies in his Fourth Set of Replies that his cogito was borrowed from Augustine (whatever the fact is).14 As for Cicero’s Tusculun Disputations, we can estimate that Descartes almost certainly read it. One passage in Descartes’s letter to Elizabeth clearly relies on a passage in Cicero’s Tusculan Disputations. Descartes writes, ‘It is also true that the knowledge of the immortality of the soul and of the felicities of which it will be capable outside of this life, could give reasons to exit this life to those who are weary of it, if they were assured that they would enjoy all these felicities afterward. But no reason so assures them, and there is only the false philosophy of Hegesias, whose book was prohibited by Ptolemy and was the cause that many killed themselves after having read it, as it tried to argue that this life is evil. The true teaching, altogether on the contrary, is that even among the saddest accidents and the most pressing pains one can always be content, so long as one knows how to use one’s reason.’ (To Elizabeth, 1645, AT-IV, 304); Cicero writes in the Tusculan Disputations, ‘What does cause anguish, or rather torture, is the departure from all those things that are good in life. Take care it may not more truly be said, from all its evils! Why should I now bewail the life of man? I could do so with truth and justice. But what need is there, when my object is to avoid the thought that we shall be wretched after death, of rendering life still more wretched by lamentation? We have done this in the book in which we did our utmost to console ourselves. Death then withdraws us from evil, not from good, if truth is our object. Indeed this thought is discussed by Hegesias the Cyrenaic with such wealth of illustration that the story goes that he was stopped from lecturing on the subject by King Ptolemy, because a number of his listeners afterwards committed suicide.’ (Tusculan, I, 83) See Shapiro, The Correspondence between Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia and René Descartes, 121 [n. 86]. In addition, Descartes probably relied on Cicero’s Tusclan Disputations when he introduced in his letter to Huygens the city of Ephesus, in which it had been forbidden to excel; the same story can be found in it. See: AT-I, 388; Tusclans, V, 36. In addition, according to Menn, Descartes’s phrase ‘the mind may be led away from the senses (mentem a sensibus abducendam)’ (Med., AT-VII, 12) is based on Cicero’s phrase ‘it requires a powerful intellect to abstract the mind from the senses and separate thought from the force of habit (magni autem est ingenii sevocare mentem a sensibus et cogitationem ab consuetudine abducere)’ (Cicero, Tusculan, 45). Furthermore, when Descartes says, ‘Many people had previously said that in order to understand metaphysical matters the mind must be drawn away from the senses’ (2ae Resp., AT-VII, 131), he is referring to Cicero by ‘many people’; in fact, no one but Cicero had claimed this in the centuries before Descartes. See Menn, Descartes and Augustine, 223 [n. 17].15 Ritter and Gründer, Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, 1509–10.16 It is often claimed that Descartes did not read Sextus’s Outlines of Pyrrhonism. Floridi, for example, insists that Descartes probably never read the Outlines; if he had read it, he would have mentioned Chrysippus’s rational dog when he discussed animal rationality. See Floridi, ‘Scepticism and Animal Rationality’, 52. Fine, however, refutes him as follows: ‘It is true that he never mentions Sextus by name. But his failure to do so does not show that he had not read him: Descartes does not cite anyone very often; and he likes to present himself as someone who does not spend too much time reading. Sextus was certainly available, in both Greek and Latin.’ See Fine, ‘Descartes and Ancient Skepticism’, 195–234. What is more, ‘Chrysippus’s rational dog’ is also found in Montaigne’s Essays (Book II, Ch. 12: ‘Apology for Raymond Sebon’), which was Descartes’s favourite book, but if we take Floridi’s view, it follows that Descartes would not have read the Essays. In fact, there are several similarities in content between Descartes and Sextus: criticism of the syllogistic, criticism of definition, criticism of majority rule in the search for truth, establishment of guidelines for real-life (‘everyday observances’ in Sextus, ‘provisional moral code’ in Descartes), etc. See Curley, Descartes against the Skeptics, 27; Gaukroger, Cartesian Logic: an essay on Descartes’s conception of inference 11; Fine, ‘Descartes and Ancient Skepticism: Reheated Cabbage?’, sec. 6. Of course, the content similarities between the two are certainly circumstantial. However, in view of the fact that Sextus’s Outlines was quite widely circulated in Descartes’s time, and that Descartes himself writes that ‘I had seen many ancient writings by the Academics and Sceptics on this subject [= doubting all things, especially corporeal things]’ (2ae Resp., AT-VII, 130), it is highly probable that Descartes came into contact with Sextus’s Outlines.17 Cicero’s Academica was widely circulated from the 16th century onwards. As quoted in the immediately previous note, Descartes writes that ‘I had seen many ancient writings by the Academics and Sceptics’ (2ae. Resp., AT-VII, 130). In addition, according to Menn and Brown, Descartes’s deceiving God argument derives from Cicero’s Academica. On the influence of Cicero upon Descartes, see Menn, Descartes and Augustine, chap. 5, sec. B; and Brown, ‘Descartes and Content Skepticism’, 25–42.18 Alexander of Aphrodisiensis, Alexandri In Aristotelis Analyticorum Priorum Librum I Commentarium, 177–178.19 Bobzien, ‘Stoic Logic’, 87.20 Descartes writes in the Preface to the French edition of the Principles, ‘[one] should study logic. I do not mean the logic of the Schools, for this is strictly speaking nothing but a dialectic which teaches ways of expounding to others what one already knows or even of holding forth without judgement about things one does not know’ (AT-VIII, 13).
但是,如果我的目的是为了避免想到我们死后会变得悲惨,又有什么必要通过哀叹来使生活更加悲惨呢?我们在书中这样做了,在书中我们尽了最大的努力来安慰自己。如果真理是我们的目标,那么死亡将使我们远离恶,而不是善。事实上,昔兰尼人希格西亚斯用大量的例证讨论了这一思想,据说他被托勒密国王阻止讲授这一主题,因为他的许多听众后来自杀了。(Tusculan, I, 83)见夏皮罗:《波西米亚公主伊丽莎白与雷诺·笛卡儿的通信》,121 [n]。86]。此外,笛卡儿在给惠更斯的信中介绍以弗所城时,很可能参考了西塞罗的《图斯克兰论辩》,以弗所城被禁止在其中出类拔萃;同样的故事也可以在里面找到。参见:AT-I, 388;图斯科兰,弗吉尼亚州,36岁。此外,根据Menn的说法,笛卡尔的短语“心灵可能被引导离开感官(mentem a sensibus abducendam)”(Med., AT-VII, 12)是基于西塞罗的短语“它需要强大的智力将心灵从感官中抽象出来,并将思想从习惯的力量中分离出来(magni autem est ingenii sevocare mentem a sensibus et cognitationem ab consuetudine abducere)”(西塞罗,Tusculan, 45)。此外,当笛卡儿说:“许多人以前说过,为了理解形而上学的问题,心灵必须从感官中抽离出来。”, AT-VII, 131),他指的是西塞罗的“许多人”;事实上,在笛卡尔之前的几个世纪里,除了西塞罗没有人提出过这个观点。参见Menn, Descartes和Augustine, 223 [n]。17)含量里特和格里<e:1>德,Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, 1509-10.16人们经常声称笛卡尔没有读过塞克斯图斯的《皮龙主义纲要》。例如,弗洛里迪坚持认为,笛卡尔可能从未读过《纲要》;如果他读过这本书,他会在讨论动物理性时提到克里西普斯的理性狗。参见Floridi,“怀疑主义和动物理性”,第52页。然而,Fine反驳道:“他确实从来没有提到塞克斯都的名字。但他没有这样做并不表明他没有读过他的作品:笛卡尔不经常引用任何人;他喜欢把自己塑造成一个不花太多时间阅读的人。塞克斯图斯当然有希腊语和拉丁语版本。参见Fine,《笛卡儿与古代怀疑论》,195-234页。更重要的是,“克里西普斯的理性狗”也出现在蒙田的《随笔》(第二卷,第12章:“为雷蒙德·塞本道歉”)中,这是笛卡尔最喜欢的书,但如果我们接受弗洛里迪的观点,那么笛卡尔就不会读《随笔》。事实上,笛卡尔和塞克斯图斯在内容上有一些相似之处:对三段论的批评,对定义的批评,对寻求真理的多数决定原则的批评,对现实生活准则的建立(塞克斯图斯的“日常仪式”,笛卡尔的“临时道德准则”),等等。参见柯利,笛卡儿反对怀疑论者,第27页;高克罗格:笛卡儿逻辑:论笛卡儿的推理概念11好,《笛卡儿和古代怀疑论:重新加热的卷心菜?》’,第6节。当然,两者在内容上的相似之处当然是间接的。然而,考虑到塞克斯图斯的《概论》在笛卡尔时代广为流传,而且笛卡尔自己也写道:“我看过许多学者和怀疑论者关于这个问题的古代著作[=怀疑一切事物,特别是物质的事物]”(2ae Resp.)。, AT-VII, 130),笛卡尔极有可能接触到塞克斯图斯的《提纲》。17西塞罗的《学院论》从16世纪开始广为流传。正如前面的注释所引用的,笛卡尔写道:“我看过许多学者和怀疑论者的古代著作。”分别地。, at-vii, 130)。此外,根据Menn和Brown的观点,笛卡尔欺骗上帝的论点来源于西塞罗的《学院论》。关于西塞罗对笛卡儿的影响,见门恩、笛卡儿和奥古斯丁,第五章B节;布朗,《笛卡尔与内容怀疑论》,25-42.18阿佛洛狄西亚的亚历山大,Alexandri In Aristotelis Analyticorum Priorum Librum I Commentarium, 177-178.19 Bobzien,《斯多亚逻辑》,87.20笛卡尔在《原理》的法文版序言中写道,“(一个人)应该研究逻辑。”我并不是指学派的逻辑,因为严格地说,这只不过是一种辩证法,它教导人们如何向别人解释自己已经知道的东西,甚至如何对自己不知道的东西不加评判地滔滔不绝。
期刊介绍:
The Seventeenth Century is an interdisciplinary journal which aims to encourage the study of the period in a way that looks beyond national boundaries or the limits of narrow intellectual approaches. Its intentions are twofold: to serve as a forum for interdisciplinary approaches to seventeenth-century studies, and at the same time to offer to a multidisciplinary readership stimulating specialist studies on a wide range of subjects. There is a general preference for articles embodying original research.