Mobilizing Falsehoods

IF 3.3 1区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS Philosophy & Public Affairs Pub Date : 2024-01-15 DOI:10.1111/papa.12254
Maxime Lepoutre
{"title":"Mobilizing Falsehoods","authors":"Maxime Lepoutre","doi":"10.1111/papa.12254","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"<h2>I. INTRODUCTION</h2>\n<div>In July 1852, on the occasion of the American Independence Day celebration, the former slave and abolitionist Frederick Douglass delivered a blistering attack on his contemporaries' continued toleration of slavery. In this celebrated speech, Douglass famously accused his contemporaries of failing to honor the ideals championed by the American “Founders”: <blockquote><p>The signers of the Declaration of Independence […] were great men […] great enough to give fame to a great age. It does not often happen to a nation to raise, at one time, such a number of truly great men. […] They were statesmen, patriots and heroes […] With them, nothing was “<i>settled</i>” that was not right. With them, justice, liberty, and humanity were “<i>final</i>;” not slavery and oppression. You may well cherish the memory of such men. They were great in their day and generation. Their solid manhood stands out the more as we contrast it with these degenerate times. They seized upon eternal principles, and set a glorious example in their defense. Mark them! [But] [m]y business, if I have any here today, is with the present […] I do not hesitate to declare, with all my soul, that the character and conduct of this nation never looked blacker to me than on this Fourth of July! […] America is false to the past […]1</p>\n<div></div>\n</blockquote>Central to Douglass's denunciation, here, is the contrast between Americans' “glorious” past and their “degenerate” present. What is striking about this contrast, moreover, is that it relies on a clearly distorted and idealized picture of the past. It is evidently false that the Founders were paragons of virtue, for whom “justice, liberty, and humanity were ‘<i>final</i>’; not slavery and oppression.” Indeed, the vast majority of them were—as Douglass well knew—slaveholders. Yet, Douglass's idealization serves a crucial rhetorical function. It helps construct a moral gulf between his contemporaries, on the one hand, and the Founders they revere, on the other. And, by doing so, it helps shame his contemporaries into taking action against slavery.2</div>\n<p>Douglass's speech exemplifies an important rhetorical practice. Public speakers often use their speech to <i>mobilize</i> their audience—in other words, to motivate their audience to take action, collectively, in support of a political cause. Yet, in non-ideal circumstances, successfully mobilizing a group can be extremely difficult. This might be, for instance, because taking action is costly for potential participants (e.g., if protestors would face arrest or violent retaliation); because the odds of achieving political change are very low (e.g., if powerful decision-makers have insulated themselves from pressure); or simply because the mobilizer's audience is suffering from weakness of will. To overcome such obstacles to motivating people, mobilizers often resort to deploying <i>falsehoods</i>: that is, they put forward propositions that misrepresent reality.</p>\n<p>Now, in practice, mobilizers frequently deploy falsehoods accidentally: they intend to say something true, but are mistaken, and therefore say something false instead. For instance, mobilizers who promulgate false conspiracy theories to motivate their audience (e.g., by claiming that climate change is a hoax) often believe these theories.3 Yet, my focus will be on intentional falsehoods, where the speaker believes that the false proposition they are putting forward misrepresents reality. Thus, in the Douglass case, I am assuming, as seems very likely,4 that Douglass believed that his declaration misrepresented the Founders' record on slavery. While accidental falsehoods <i>can</i> be morally problematic—particularly in situations where the speaker is culpable for their mistake—I consider intentional falsehoods to be prima facie more troubling, and therefore more difficult to defend, for reasons outlined in Section II.5</p>\n<p>Note, furthermore, that mobilizing falsehoods can be communicated directly (e.g., by being stated or asserted) but also more indirectly (e.g., by means of conversational implicature). The defense of mobilizing falsehoods developed below is in principle meant to apply to both.6 In practice, however, most of the cases I will examine involve falsehoods that are asserted or stated, which many consider to be more morally problematic than falsehoods that are merely implied.7</p>\n<p>The practice of deploying intentional mobilizing falsehoods—that is, of deliberately asserting or implying falsehoods to mobilize political action—is a common feature of real-world public discourse. For one thing, such falsehoods are widespread in the context of national narratives. As Douglass's speech illustrates, national stories are often rife with misrepresentations of past events and historical figures.8 For example, by intentionally idealizing prominent national figures and characterizing them as exemplars of justice, speakers can tap into the motivational reservoir constituted by feelings of national belonging and direct it toward just causes.9</p>\n<p>But the use of mobilizing falsehoods extends far beyond the case of national narratives. Indeed, public speakers often mobilize groups of people by intentionally disseminating falsehoods that are unrelated to national events and heroes. For instance, because achieving political change can be extremely difficult, social movement leaders who wish to mobilize their movement sometimes need to misrepresent the political situation that they currently face.10 This might involve, say, knowingly downplaying the risks associated with political action (“We have nothing to lose.”); or knowingly exaggerating the odds of success associated with a given political cause (“If we pull together, we are guaranteed to succeed.”).</p>\n<p>So mobilizing falsehoods are pervasive in real-world public discourse. And, as will be shown, they can provide powerful resources for mobilizing action in non-ideal circumstances. Yet the practice of deploying such falsehoods is regarded by many with suspicion. In his influential exploration of democratic leadership, for example, Eric Beerbohm rejects the idea of intentionally using false or misleading assertions to mobilize a group. Likewise, Arash Abizadeh severely criticizes the deployment of historical claims that deliberately misrepresent a nation's past, even if these claims help motivate unified political action.11</p>\n<p>I wish to bracket two immediate concerns that risk confounding the assessment of mobilizing falsehoods. The first relates to the justice of the cause being pursued. Encouraging people to promote injustices seems clearly problematic. Hence, it seems intuitively wrong to use falsehoods as a way of mobilizing support for unjust causes (e.g., by embellishing a nation's imperialist past to mobilize support for colonialism; or by falsely alleging, as Donald Trump's “big lie” has done, that an election is fraudulent to mobilize an anti-democratic coup). Since the wrongness of such pronouncements seems relatively uncontroversial, I wish to focus instead on the practice, exemplified by Douglass's Fourth of July speech, of knowingly deploying falsehoods to mobilize action <i>in support of a just cause</i>.</p>\n<p>The second concern relates to vilification. A speaker might motivate their audience to pursue a just political cause by falsely representing opponents of that cause as subhuman or ineradicably evil. Lawyers and philosophers disagree about whether such hateful utterances should be legally restricted. But they nonetheless typically agree that they are morally undesirable.12 My focus will therefore be on the more contested case, where speakers deploy falsehoods that mobilize action <i>without vilifying opponents</i>.</p>\n<p>Is it ever permissible to intentionally deploy (non-vilifying) falsehoods in order to mobilize action that serves a just cause?13 Even when qualified in this way, the use of mobilizing falsehoods remains deeply controversial, for reasons to be introduced shortly. But I will argue that such falsehoods <i>can</i> be permissible in a meaningful set of cases—including, most controversially, in cases where they constitute deception. Opposition to mobilizing falsehoods notably tends to overlook the diversity of ways in which falsehoods can mobilize action, as well as their potential integration within a broader system of democratic contestation. My purpose, in delivering this argument, is therefore threefold. It is, first, to enhance our understanding of the diverse ways in which mobilizing falsehoods operate; second, to defend the moral permissibility of deploying some of these falsehoods in a democratic society; and, third, to identify the conditions in which, in such a society, it is permissible to deploy these falsehoods.</p>\n<p>My argument will proceed as follows. Section II outlines the central challenge to mobilizing falsehoods: namely, that they are deceptive, which in turn makes them problematic for reasons relating to both autonomy and democracy. I then develop two complementary responses to this challenge. Second III demonstrates that some falsehoods, which I refer to as “transparent” falsehoods, can mobilize without purporting to be true—and so, without deceiving. On its own, however, this first response does not go far enough, not least because it leaves undefended many highly potent mobilizing falsehoods. Section IV therefore goes on to argue that some mobilizing falsehoods are justified despite being deceptive, and, by extension, that transparency is not a necessary condition of their permissibility.</p>","PeriodicalId":47999,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Public Affairs","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.3000,"publicationDate":"2024-01-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Philosophy & Public Affairs","FirstCategoryId":"98","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12254","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

I. INTRODUCTION

In July 1852, on the occasion of the American Independence Day celebration, the former slave and abolitionist Frederick Douglass delivered a blistering attack on his contemporaries' continued toleration of slavery. In this celebrated speech, Douglass famously accused his contemporaries of failing to honor the ideals championed by the American “Founders”:

The signers of the Declaration of Independence […] were great men […] great enough to give fame to a great age. It does not often happen to a nation to raise, at one time, such a number of truly great men. […] They were statesmen, patriots and heroes […] With them, nothing was “settled” that was not right. With them, justice, liberty, and humanity were “final;” not slavery and oppression. You may well cherish the memory of such men. They were great in their day and generation. Their solid manhood stands out the more as we contrast it with these degenerate times. They seized upon eternal principles, and set a glorious example in their defense. Mark them! [But] [m]y business, if I have any here today, is with the present […] I do not hesitate to declare, with all my soul, that the character and conduct of this nation never looked blacker to me than on this Fourth of July! […] America is false to the past […]1

Central to Douglass's denunciation, here, is the contrast between Americans' “glorious” past and their “degenerate” present. What is striking about this contrast, moreover, is that it relies on a clearly distorted and idealized picture of the past. It is evidently false that the Founders were paragons of virtue, for whom “justice, liberty, and humanity were ‘final’; not slavery and oppression.” Indeed, the vast majority of them were—as Douglass well knew—slaveholders. Yet, Douglass's idealization serves a crucial rhetorical function. It helps construct a moral gulf between his contemporaries, on the one hand, and the Founders they revere, on the other. And, by doing so, it helps shame his contemporaries into taking action against slavery.2

Douglass's speech exemplifies an important rhetorical practice. Public speakers often use their speech to mobilize their audience—in other words, to motivate their audience to take action, collectively, in support of a political cause. Yet, in non-ideal circumstances, successfully mobilizing a group can be extremely difficult. This might be, for instance, because taking action is costly for potential participants (e.g., if protestors would face arrest or violent retaliation); because the odds of achieving political change are very low (e.g., if powerful decision-makers have insulated themselves from pressure); or simply because the mobilizer's audience is suffering from weakness of will. To overcome such obstacles to motivating people, mobilizers often resort to deploying falsehoods: that is, they put forward propositions that misrepresent reality.

Now, in practice, mobilizers frequently deploy falsehoods accidentally: they intend to say something true, but are mistaken, and therefore say something false instead. For instance, mobilizers who promulgate false conspiracy theories to motivate their audience (e.g., by claiming that climate change is a hoax) often believe these theories.3 Yet, my focus will be on intentional falsehoods, where the speaker believes that the false proposition they are putting forward misrepresents reality. Thus, in the Douglass case, I am assuming, as seems very likely,4 that Douglass believed that his declaration misrepresented the Founders' record on slavery. While accidental falsehoods can be morally problematic—particularly in situations where the speaker is culpable for their mistake—I consider intentional falsehoods to be prima facie more troubling, and therefore more difficult to defend, for reasons outlined in Section II.5

Note, furthermore, that mobilizing falsehoods can be communicated directly (e.g., by being stated or asserted) but also more indirectly (e.g., by means of conversational implicature). The defense of mobilizing falsehoods developed below is in principle meant to apply to both.6 In practice, however, most of the cases I will examine involve falsehoods that are asserted or stated, which many consider to be more morally problematic than falsehoods that are merely implied.7

The practice of deploying intentional mobilizing falsehoods—that is, of deliberately asserting or implying falsehoods to mobilize political action—is a common feature of real-world public discourse. For one thing, such falsehoods are widespread in the context of national narratives. As Douglass's speech illustrates, national stories are often rife with misrepresentations of past events and historical figures.8 For example, by intentionally idealizing prominent national figures and characterizing them as exemplars of justice, speakers can tap into the motivational reservoir constituted by feelings of national belonging and direct it toward just causes.9

But the use of mobilizing falsehoods extends far beyond the case of national narratives. Indeed, public speakers often mobilize groups of people by intentionally disseminating falsehoods that are unrelated to national events and heroes. For instance, because achieving political change can be extremely difficult, social movement leaders who wish to mobilize their movement sometimes need to misrepresent the political situation that they currently face.10 This might involve, say, knowingly downplaying the risks associated with political action (“We have nothing to lose.”); or knowingly exaggerating the odds of success associated with a given political cause (“If we pull together, we are guaranteed to succeed.”).

So mobilizing falsehoods are pervasive in real-world public discourse. And, as will be shown, they can provide powerful resources for mobilizing action in non-ideal circumstances. Yet the practice of deploying such falsehoods is regarded by many with suspicion. In his influential exploration of democratic leadership, for example, Eric Beerbohm rejects the idea of intentionally using false or misleading assertions to mobilize a group. Likewise, Arash Abizadeh severely criticizes the deployment of historical claims that deliberately misrepresent a nation's past, even if these claims help motivate unified political action.11

I wish to bracket two immediate concerns that risk confounding the assessment of mobilizing falsehoods. The first relates to the justice of the cause being pursued. Encouraging people to promote injustices seems clearly problematic. Hence, it seems intuitively wrong to use falsehoods as a way of mobilizing support for unjust causes (e.g., by embellishing a nation's imperialist past to mobilize support for colonialism; or by falsely alleging, as Donald Trump's “big lie” has done, that an election is fraudulent to mobilize an anti-democratic coup). Since the wrongness of such pronouncements seems relatively uncontroversial, I wish to focus instead on the practice, exemplified by Douglass's Fourth of July speech, of knowingly deploying falsehoods to mobilize action in support of a just cause.

The second concern relates to vilification. A speaker might motivate their audience to pursue a just political cause by falsely representing opponents of that cause as subhuman or ineradicably evil. Lawyers and philosophers disagree about whether such hateful utterances should be legally restricted. But they nonetheless typically agree that they are morally undesirable.12 My focus will therefore be on the more contested case, where speakers deploy falsehoods that mobilize action without vilifying opponents.

Is it ever permissible to intentionally deploy (non-vilifying) falsehoods in order to mobilize action that serves a just cause?13 Even when qualified in this way, the use of mobilizing falsehoods remains deeply controversial, for reasons to be introduced shortly. But I will argue that such falsehoods can be permissible in a meaningful set of cases—including, most controversially, in cases where they constitute deception. Opposition to mobilizing falsehoods notably tends to overlook the diversity of ways in which falsehoods can mobilize action, as well as their potential integration within a broader system of democratic contestation. My purpose, in delivering this argument, is therefore threefold. It is, first, to enhance our understanding of the diverse ways in which mobilizing falsehoods operate; second, to defend the moral permissibility of deploying some of these falsehoods in a democratic society; and, third, to identify the conditions in which, in such a society, it is permissible to deploy these falsehoods.

My argument will proceed as follows. Section II outlines the central challenge to mobilizing falsehoods: namely, that they are deceptive, which in turn makes them problematic for reasons relating to both autonomy and democracy. I then develop two complementary responses to this challenge. Second III demonstrates that some falsehoods, which I refer to as “transparent” falsehoods, can mobilize without purporting to be true—and so, without deceiving. On its own, however, this first response does not go far enough, not least because it leaves undefended many highly potent mobilizing falsehoods. Section IV therefore goes on to argue that some mobilizing falsehoods are justified despite being deceptive, and, by extension, that transparency is not a necessary condition of their permissibility.

查看原文
分享 分享
微信好友 朋友圈 QQ好友 复制链接
本刊更多论文
制造假象
I.引言 1852 年 7 月,在庆祝美国独立日之际,前奴隶和废奴主义者弗雷德里克-道格拉斯对他的同代人继续容忍奴隶制进行了猛烈抨击。在这篇著名的演讲中,道格拉斯指责他同时代的人没有尊重美国 "建国者 "所倡导的理想:独立宣言》的签署者[......]都是伟人[......],他们的伟大足以让一个伟大的时代声名远播。一个国家在同一时期涌现出如此众多的真正伟人,这种情况并不多见。[......]他们是政治家、爱国者和英雄[......]在他们身上,没有什么是 "不正确 "的。在他们那里,正义、自由和人性是 "最终的",而不是奴役和压迫。你们完全可以怀念这些人。他们在他们的时代和年代是伟大的。与这个堕落的时代相比,他们坚实的男子气概更加突出。他们抓住永恒的原则,为捍卫这些原则树立了光辉的榜样。请记住他们![我毫不犹豫地宣布,在我看来,这个国家的品格和行为从来没有像今天的国庆日这样黑暗过![......]美国对过去是虚假的[......]1道格拉斯谴责的核心是美国人 "辉煌 "的过去与 "堕落 "的现在之间的对比。此外,这种对比的惊人之处在于,它依赖于对过去明显扭曲和理想化的描述。建国者是美德的典范,对他们来说,"正义、自由和人性是'最终的',而不是奴役和压迫",这显然是错误的。事实上,正如道格拉斯所熟知的那样,他们中的绝大多数人都是奴隶主。然而,道格拉斯的理想化具有重要的修辞功能。一方面,它有助于在他同时代的人与他们所崇敬的建国者之间构建道德鸿沟。2 杜格拉斯的演讲体现了一种重要的修辞手法。公众演讲者通常利用演讲来动员听众--换句话说,激励听众集体采取行动,支持某项政治事业。然而,在非理想的情况下,成功动员一个群体可能极其困难。例如,这可能是因为采取行动对潜在参与者来说代价高昂(如抗议者将面临逮捕或暴力报复);因为实现政治变革的几率非常低(如强大的决策者使自己免受压力);或者仅仅是因为动员者的受众意志薄弱。为了克服这些激励人们的障碍,动员者往往会采用虚假的方式:即提出歪曲事实的命题。实际上,动员者经常会意外地使用虚假的方式:他们本想说一些真实的东西,但却搞错了,因此反而说了一些虚假的东西。3 然而,我的重点将放在有意的假话上,即说话者认为他们提出的假命题歪曲了现实。因此,在道格拉斯一案中,我假设--似乎很有可能4--道格拉斯认为他的宣言歪曲了建国者在奴隶制问题上的记录。虽然偶然的谬误可能在道德上有问题--尤其是在说话者对自己的错误负有责任的情况下--但我认为蓄意的谬误初步看来更令人不安,因此也更难辩护,理由已在第二节中概述5。此外,请注意,动员性谬误可以直接传达(如通过陈述或断言),也可以更间接地传达(如通过对话暗示)。6 然而,在实践中,我将研究的大多数案例都涉及断言或陈述的谬误,许多人认为这比仅仅暗示的谬误更有道德问题。7 使用有意的动员性谬误--即故意断言或暗示谬误以动员政治行动--是现实世界公共话语的一个常见特征。首先,这种假话在国家叙事中非常普遍。8 例如,通过有意将杰出的国家人物理想化并将其描述为正义的楷模,演讲者可以利用民族归属感所构成的动机库,并将其导向正义事业。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 去求助
来源期刊
CiteScore
3.90
自引率
4.50%
发文量
23
期刊最新文献
Kolodny Against Hierarchy Universal Statism Individuality as Difference Moral Understanding Between You and Me The Role of Civility in Political Disobedience
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
已复制链接
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
×
扫码分享
扫码分享
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1