首页 > 最新文献

Philosophy & Public Affairs最新文献

英文 中文
Kolodny Against Hierarchy 科洛德尼反对等级制度
IF 2.2 1区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-22 DOI: 10.1111/papa.12273
Jake Zuehl
{"title":"Kolodny Against Hierarchy","authors":"Jake Zuehl","doi":"10.1111/papa.12273","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12273","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":47999,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Public Affairs","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-08-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142213237","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Universal Statism 普世国家主义
IF 2.2 1区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-14 DOI: 10.1111/papa.12270
Adam Kern
{"title":"Universal Statism","authors":"Adam Kern","doi":"10.1111/papa.12270","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12270","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":47999,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Public Affairs","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-08-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142227833","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Individuality as Difference 作为差异的个性
IF 2.2 1区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-06-29 DOI: 10.1111/papa.12267
Guy Kahane
{"title":"Individuality as Difference","authors":"Guy Kahane","doi":"10.1111/papa.12267","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12267","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":47999,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Public Affairs","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-06-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141510410","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Moral Understanding Between You and Me 你我之间的道德理解
IF 2.2 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-05-27 DOI: 10.1111/papa.12259
Samuel Dishaw
{"title":"Moral Understanding Between You and Me","authors":"Samuel Dishaw","doi":"10.1111/papa.12259","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12259","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":47999,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Public Affairs","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-05-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141197832","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Role of Civility in Political Disobedience 礼貌在政治不服从中的作用
IF 2.2 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-03-12 DOI: 10.1111/papa.12258
Steve Coyne

I. INTRODUCTION

In modern liberal democracies, politically motivated disobedience of the law is generally tolerated as a way of challenging and changing social and legal practices. This paper concerns the role of civility in such political disobedience.1

In his seminal work on political disobedience, John Rawls identified three characteristics that many philosophers now take to be the crux of civility: openness, acceptance of legal consequences, and nonviolence. While Rawls and others thought that these features play an essential role in the internal logic of political disobedience, today civility faces increasing skepticism from both practitioners of political disobedience and philosophers who theorize about it. Many of the recent examples of political disobedience that have done the most to capture the public's attention, including Edward Snowden's whistleblowing, Extinction Rebellion's road blockades, Le mouvement des Gilets jaunes in France, and the trucker convoys in Canada, have all been decidedly uncivil in some way or another. Mirroring these real-life trends, many philosophers working on political disobedience have also become increasingly skeptical of civility and increasingly supportive of incivility. As Candice Delmas urges, “It is thus time to start thinking about uncivil disobedience—to wit, disobedient acts that are principled yet also deliberately offensive, covert, anonymous, more than minimally destructive, not respectful of their targets, or which do not aim to communicate to an audience the need to reform laws, policies or institutions.”2

To evaluate this shift in attitude toward civility, we first need to better understand what civility contributes to political disobedience. This, in turn, requires a detailed analysis of the mechanisms by which political disobedience is intended to influence the reasons of others. Philosophers who write on political disobedience have tended to focus on two of these mechanisms, which I will label “drawing attention” and “triggering conditional reasons,” and I will grant that civility is largely unimportant for these mechanisms. However, I will also argue that political disobedience often proceeds by other mechanisms, including the expression of speech acts like demands, requests, and testimony, and that civility is much more important in these mechanisms.

In Section II, I describe the formal characteristics of civility identified by Rawls (openness, nonviolence, and the acceptance of legal consequences), and argue that his account fails to identify a clear mechanism by which political disobedience affects the reasons of its audience. In Section III, I distinguish five mechanisms through which it might affect those reasons: drawing attention, giving testimony, triggering conditional reasons, making demands, and making requests. In Sections IV–IX, IV–IX, I discuss these mechanisms in detail and explore the role that civility plays in each of them.

I.引言在现代自由民主国家,出于政治动机而不服从法律的行为通常被容忍,以此来挑战和改变社会和法律惯例。1 约翰-罗尔斯(John Rawls)在其关于政治不服从的开创性著作中指出了许多哲学家现在认为是文明关键的三个特征:开放、接受法律后果和非暴力。虽然罗尔斯等人认为这些特征在政治不服从的内在逻辑中起着至关重要的作用,但如今,无论是政治不服从的实践者,还是对其进行理论研究的哲学家,都对公民意识持越来越怀疑的态度。最近,爱德华-斯诺登(Edward Snowden)的告密行动、"灭绝叛乱"(Extinction Rebellion)的封路行动、法国的 "青年运动"(Le mouvement des Gilets jaunes)以及加拿大的卡车司机车队(trucker convoys in Canada)等许多政治不服从的例子都在某种程度上表现出了明显的不文明。与现实生活中的这些趋势相呼应,许多研究政治不服从的哲学家也越来越怀疑文明,越来越支持不文明。正如坎迪斯-德尔马斯(Candice Delmas)所呼吁的,"因此,现在是时候开始思考不文明的不服从了--也就是说,不服从行为是有原则的,但也是故意冒犯、隐蔽、匿名、超过最低限度的破坏性、不尊重目标,或者不是为了向受众传达改革法律、政策或制度的必要性。这反过来又需要详细分析政治不服从意在影响他人理由的机制。研究政治不服从的哲学家们倾向于关注其中的两种机制,我将把它们称为 "引起注意 "和 "触发有条件的理由",我承认,对于这些机制来说,文明程度基本上并不重要。在第二节中,我描述了罗尔斯所指出的文明的形式特征(公开、非暴力和接受法律后果),并认为他的论述未能指出政治不服从影响受众理由的明确机制。在第三节中,我区分了政治不服从可能影响这些理由的五种机制:引起注意、提供证词、引发有条件的理由、提出要求和请求。在第四-九节和第四-九节中,我将详细讨论这些机制,并探讨文明在每个机制中发挥的作用。
{"title":"The Role of Civility in Political Disobedience","authors":"Steve Coyne","doi":"10.1111/papa.12258","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12258","url":null,"abstract":"<h2>I. INTRODUCTION</h2>\u0000<p>In modern liberal democracies, politically motivated disobedience of the law is generally tolerated as a way of challenging and changing social and legal practices. This paper concerns the role of civility in such political disobedience.1</p>\u0000<p>In his seminal work on political disobedience, John Rawls identified three characteristics that many philosophers now take to be the crux of civility: openness, acceptance of legal consequences, and nonviolence. While Rawls and others thought that these features play an essential role in the internal logic of political disobedience, today civility faces increasing skepticism from both practitioners of political disobedience and philosophers who theorize about it. Many of the recent examples of political disobedience that have done the most to capture the public's attention, including Edward Snowden's whistleblowing, Extinction Rebellion's road blockades, <i>Le mouvement des Gilets jaunes</i> in France, and the trucker convoys in Canada, have all been decidedly <i>uncivil</i> in some way or another. Mirroring these real-life trends, many philosophers working on political disobedience have also become increasingly skeptical of civility and increasingly supportive of incivility. As Candice Delmas urges, “It is thus time to start thinking about uncivil disobedience—to wit, disobedient acts that are principled yet also deliberately offensive, covert, anonymous, more than minimally destructive, not respectful of their targets, or which do not aim to communicate to an audience the need to reform laws, policies or institutions.”2</p>\u0000<p>To evaluate this shift in attitude toward civility, we first need to better understand what civility contributes to political disobedience. This, in turn, requires a detailed analysis of the mechanisms by which political disobedience is intended to influence the reasons of others. Philosophers who write on political disobedience have tended to focus on two of these mechanisms, which I will label “drawing attention” and “triggering conditional reasons,” and I will grant that civility is largely unimportant for these mechanisms. However, I will also argue that political disobedience often proceeds by other mechanisms, including the expression of speech acts like demands, requests, and testimony, and that civility is much more important in these mechanisms.</p>\u0000<p>In Section II, I describe the formal characteristics of civility identified by Rawls (openness, nonviolence, and the acceptance of legal consequences), and argue that his account fails to identify a clear mechanism by which political disobedience affects the reasons of its audience. In Section III, I distinguish five mechanisms through which it might affect those reasons: drawing attention, giving testimony, triggering conditional reasons, making demands, and making requests. In Sections IV–IX, IV–IX, I discuss these mechanisms in detail and explore the role that civility plays in each of them.</","PeriodicalId":47999,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Public Affairs","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-03-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140107597","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Which Majority Should Rule? 哪种多数应占统治地位?
IF 2.2 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-03-01 DOI: 10.1111/papa.12257
Daniel Wodak
{"title":"Which Majority Should Rule?","authors":"Daniel Wodak","doi":"10.1111/papa.12257","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12257","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":47999,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Public Affairs","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140037036","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Political Equality and Epistemic Constraints on Voting 政治平等与投票的认识限制
IF 2.2 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-01-17 DOI: 10.1111/papa.12255
Michele Giavazzi

I. INTRODUCTION

The idea that voting procedures should be accessible to every citizen who wishes to participate is a fundamental principle of democracy. In recent years, however, this idea has been challenged. As part of a resurgent skepticism about the epistemic qualities of democracy, some political philosophers have argued that participation in voting practices should be made conditional, through specifically designed formal mechanisms or procedures, upon having a sufficient level of political competence. Call these mechanisms epistemic constraints on voting (ECV).

The idea of employing criteria of competence to restrict participation in voting practices is taken, by many, to be inherently incompatible with political equality. In this paper, my purpose is to challenge this common claim and to show how, once properly reframed, the idea of setting up ECV need not violate political equality in any normatively significant fashion. I intend to do so by suggesting that it is possible to construct a justification for ECV that overcomes at least two problems that egalitarians commonly associate with ECV: the disrespect problem and the hierarchy problem.

Such a justification, which provides an alternative to the standard instrumental one presented in the literature, appeals to non-instrumental reasons. More precisely, it appeals to the idea that, qua participants in a shared practice, voters stand to one another in a normative relation that obligates them to act in an epistemically responsible fashion and makes them reciprocally accountable for their conduct in this regard. Modest ECV are justifiable because they ensure that voting practices conform to this relation and to the requirement of epistemic responsibility that follows from it. Call this the civic accountability justification for ECV.

The paper is structured in two parts. The first part clarifies the scope and assumptions of the paper (1) and sketches the broad outline of the civic accountability justification for ECV (2), with a particular focus on explicating its distinctive non-instrumental commitments. The second part discusses how the civic accountability justification for ECV can overcome two prominent issues of political equality: the disrespect problem (3) and the hierarchy problem (4).

For what concerns the former, which rests on a commitment to pay proper respect for the political judgments of all citizens, I will argue that the civic accountability justification does not resort to the kind of considerations of competence—i.e., comparative assessments, competence rankings, educational qualifications, etc.—that can be plausibly regarded as disrespectful. As for what concerns the latter, which rests on a commitment to avoid hierarchical social relations, I will argue that the civic accountability justification for ECV is based precisely on the idea that participation in voting creates a new normative relation, one that commands an

I.每个希望参与投票的公民都应能够利用投票程序,这是民主的一项基本原则。然而,近年来这一理念受到了挑战。一些政治哲学家认为,作为对民主的认识论特质的重新怀疑的一部分,参与投票实践应通过专门设计的正式机制或程序,以具备足够的政治能力为条件。许多人认为,采用能力标准来限制参与投票实践的想法本质上与政治平等是不相容的。在本文中,我的目的是对这一常见说法提出质疑,并说明一旦对其进行适当的重构,设立ECV的想法不一定会以任何规范上重要的方式违反政治平等。为此,我打算提出,我们有可能为ECV构建一个理由,它至少可以克服平等主义者通常与ECV联系在一起的两个问题:不尊重问题和等级问题。更确切地说,它所诉诸的理念是,作为共同实践的参与者,选民之间存在着一种规范关系,这种关系使他们有义务以一种在认识论上负责任的方式行事,并使他们在这方面对自己的行为承担对等责任。适度的欧洲共同体成员票是合理的,因为它确保投票实践符合这种关系以及由此产生的认识论责任要求。本文分为两部分。第一部分阐明了本文的研究范围和假设(1),并勾勒了ECV的公民责任论证的大致轮廓(2),重点阐述了其独特的非工具性承诺。第二部分论述了ECV的公民问责理由如何克服政治平等的两个突出问题:不尊重问题(3)和等级问题(4)。就前者而言,其基础是对所有公民的政治判断给予应有尊重的承诺,我将论证公民问责理由并不诉诸能力方面的考虑--即比较评估、能力排名、教育资格等--这些都可以被合理地视为不尊重。至于后者,其基础是对避免等级社会关系的承诺,我将论证,欧洲共同体选举的公民问责理由正是基于这样一种观点,即参与投票创造了一种新的规范关系,一种要求在认识论上负责任的行为。因此,这种关系抵消了对关系平等的担忧,而这种担忧正是等级问题的根源。此外,由于公民问责的理由并不致力于工具最优性,因此它可以支持避免社会等级实例化的ECV。
{"title":"Political Equality and Epistemic Constraints on Voting","authors":"Michele Giavazzi","doi":"10.1111/papa.12255","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12255","url":null,"abstract":"<h2>I. INTRODUCTION</h2>\u0000<p>The idea that voting procedures should be accessible to every citizen who wishes to participate is a fundamental principle of democracy. In recent years, however, this idea has been challenged. As part of a resurgent skepticism about the epistemic qualities of democracy, some political philosophers have argued that participation in voting practices should be made conditional, through specifically designed formal mechanisms or procedures, upon having a sufficient level of political competence. Call these mechanisms <i>epistemic constraints on voting</i> (ECV).</p>\u0000<p>The idea of employing criteria of competence to restrict participation in voting practices is taken, by many, to be inherently incompatible with political equality. In this paper, my purpose is to challenge this common claim and to show how, once properly reframed, the idea of setting up ECV need not violate political equality in any normatively significant fashion. I intend to do so by suggesting that it is possible to construct a justification for ECV that overcomes at least two problems that egalitarians commonly associate with ECV: the disrespect problem and the hierarchy problem.</p>\u0000<p>Such a justification, which provides an alternative to the standard instrumental one presented in the literature, appeals to non-instrumental reasons. More precisely, it appeals to the idea that, qua participants in a shared practice, voters stand to one another in a normative relation that obligates them to act in an epistemically responsible fashion and makes them reciprocally accountable for their conduct in this regard. Modest ECV are justifiable because they ensure that voting practices conform to this relation and to the requirement of epistemic responsibility that follows from it. Call this the <i>civic accountability justification for ECV</i>.</p>\u0000<p>The paper is structured in two parts. The first part clarifies the scope and assumptions of the paper (1) and sketches the broad outline of the civic accountability justification for ECV (2), with a particular focus on explicating its distinctive non-instrumental commitments. The second part discusses how the civic accountability justification for ECV can overcome two prominent issues of political equality: the disrespect problem (3) and the hierarchy problem (4).</p>\u0000<p>For what concerns the former, which rests on a commitment to pay proper respect for the political judgments of all citizens, I will argue that the civic accountability justification does not resort to the kind of considerations of competence—i.e., comparative assessments, competence rankings, educational qualifications, etc.—that can be plausibly regarded as disrespectful. As for what concerns the latter, which rests on a commitment to avoid hierarchical social relations, I will argue that the civic accountability justification for ECV is based precisely on the idea that participation in voting creates a new normative relation, one that commands an ","PeriodicalId":47999,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Public Affairs","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-01-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139515291","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Mobilizing Falsehoods 制造假象
IF 2.2 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-01-15 DOI: 10.1111/papa.12254
Maxime Lepoutre

I. INTRODUCTION

In July 1852, on the occasion of the American Independence Day celebration, the former slave and abolitionist Frederick Douglass delivered a blistering attack on his contemporaries' continued toleration of slavery. In this celebrated speech, Douglass famously accused his contemporaries of failing to honor the ideals championed by the American “Founders”:

The signers of the Declaration of Independence […] were great men […] great enough to give fame to a great age. It does not often happen to a nation to raise, at one time, such a number of truly great men. […] They were statesmen, patriots and heroes […] With them, nothing was “settled” that was not right. With them, justice, liberty, and humanity were “final;” not slavery and oppression. You may well cherish the memory of such men. They were great in their day and generation. Their solid manhood stands out the more as we contrast it with these degenerate times. They seized upon eternal principles, and set a glorious example in their defense. Mark them! [But] [m]y business, if I have any here today, is with the present […] I do not hesitate to declare, with all my soul, that the character and conduct of this nation never looked blacker to me than on this Fourth of July! […] America is false to the past […]1

Central to Douglass's denunciation, here, is the contrast between Americans' “glorious” past and their “degenerate” present. What is striking about this contrast, moreover, is that it relies on a clearly distorted and idealized picture of the past. It is evidently false that the Founders were paragons of virtue, for whom “justice, liberty, and humanity were ‘final’; not slavery and oppression.” Indeed, the vast majority of them were—as Douglass well knew—slaveholders. Yet, Douglass's idealization serves a crucial rhetorical function. It helps construct a moral gulf between his contemporaries, on the one hand, and the Founders they revere, on the other. And, by doing so, it helps shame his contemporaries into taking action against slavery.2

Douglass's speech exemplifies an important rhetorical practice. Public speakers often use their speech to mobilize their audience—in other words, to motivate their audience to take action, collectively, in support of a political cause. Yet, in non-ideal circumstances, successfully mobilizing a group can be extremely difficult. This might be, for instance, because taking action is costly for potential participants (e.g., if protestors would face arrest or violent retaliation); because the odds of achieving political change are very low (e.g., if powerful decision-makers have insulated themselves from pressure); or simply because the mobilizer's audience is suffering from weakness of will. To overcome such obstacles to motivating people, mobilizers often resort to deploying falsehoods: that is, they put forward propositions that misrepresent re

I.引言 1852 年 7 月,在庆祝美国独立日之际,前奴隶和废奴主义者弗雷德里克-道格拉斯对他的同代人继续容忍奴隶制进行了猛烈抨击。在这篇著名的演讲中,道格拉斯指责他同时代的人没有尊重美国 "建国者 "所倡导的理想:独立宣言》的签署者[......]都是伟人[......],他们的伟大足以让一个伟大的时代声名远播。一个国家在同一时期涌现出如此众多的真正伟人,这种情况并不多见。[......]他们是政治家、爱国者和英雄[......]在他们身上,没有什么是 "不正确 "的。在他们那里,正义、自由和人性是 "最终的",而不是奴役和压迫。你们完全可以怀念这些人。他们在他们的时代和年代是伟大的。与这个堕落的时代相比,他们坚实的男子气概更加突出。他们抓住永恒的原则,为捍卫这些原则树立了光辉的榜样。请记住他们![我毫不犹豫地宣布,在我看来,这个国家的品格和行为从来没有像今天的国庆日这样黑暗过![......]美国对过去是虚假的[......]1道格拉斯谴责的核心是美国人 "辉煌 "的过去与 "堕落 "的现在之间的对比。此外,这种对比的惊人之处在于,它依赖于对过去明显扭曲和理想化的描述。建国者是美德的典范,对他们来说,"正义、自由和人性是'最终的',而不是奴役和压迫",这显然是错误的。事实上,正如道格拉斯所熟知的那样,他们中的绝大多数人都是奴隶主。然而,道格拉斯的理想化具有重要的修辞功能。一方面,它有助于在他同时代的人与他们所崇敬的建国者之间构建道德鸿沟。2 杜格拉斯的演讲体现了一种重要的修辞手法。公众演讲者通常利用演讲来动员听众--换句话说,激励听众集体采取行动,支持某项政治事业。然而,在非理想的情况下,成功动员一个群体可能极其困难。例如,这可能是因为采取行动对潜在参与者来说代价高昂(如抗议者将面临逮捕或暴力报复);因为实现政治变革的几率非常低(如强大的决策者使自己免受压力);或者仅仅是因为动员者的受众意志薄弱。为了克服这些激励人们的障碍,动员者往往会采用虚假的方式:即提出歪曲事实的命题。实际上,动员者经常会意外地使用虚假的方式:他们本想说一些真实的东西,但却搞错了,因此反而说了一些虚假的东西。3 然而,我的重点将放在有意的假话上,即说话者认为他们提出的假命题歪曲了现实。因此,在道格拉斯一案中,我假设--似乎很有可能4--道格拉斯认为他的宣言歪曲了建国者在奴隶制问题上的记录。虽然偶然的谬误可能在道德上有问题--尤其是在说话者对自己的错误负有责任的情况下--但我认为蓄意的谬误初步看来更令人不安,因此也更难辩护,理由已在第二节中概述5。此外,请注意,动员性谬误可以直接传达(如通过陈述或断言),也可以更间接地传达(如通过对话暗示)。6 然而,在实践中,我将研究的大多数案例都涉及断言或陈述的谬误,许多人认为这比仅仅暗示的谬误更有道德问题。7 使用有意的动员性谬误--即故意断言或暗示谬误以动员政治行动--是现实世界公共话语的一个常见特征。首先,这种假话在国家叙事中非常普遍。8 例如,通过有意将杰出的国家人物理想化并将其描述为正义的楷模,演讲者可以利用民族归属感所构成的动机库,并将其导向正义事业。
{"title":"Mobilizing Falsehoods","authors":"Maxime Lepoutre","doi":"10.1111/papa.12254","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12254","url":null,"abstract":"<h2>I. INTRODUCTION</h2>\u0000<div>In July 1852, on the occasion of the American Independence Day celebration, the former slave and abolitionist Frederick Douglass delivered a blistering attack on his contemporaries' continued toleration of slavery. In this celebrated speech, Douglass famously accused his contemporaries of failing to honor the ideals championed by the American “Founders”: <blockquote><p>The signers of the Declaration of Independence […] were great men […] great enough to give fame to a great age. It does not often happen to a nation to raise, at one time, such a number of truly great men. […] They were statesmen, patriots and heroes […] With them, nothing was “<i>settled</i>” that was not right. With them, justice, liberty, and humanity were “<i>final</i>;” not slavery and oppression. You may well cherish the memory of such men. They were great in their day and generation. Their solid manhood stands out the more as we contrast it with these degenerate times. They seized upon eternal principles, and set a glorious example in their defense. Mark them! [But] [m]y business, if I have any here today, is with the present […] I do not hesitate to declare, with all my soul, that the character and conduct of this nation never looked blacker to me than on this Fourth of July! […] America is false to the past […]1</p>\u0000<div></div>\u0000</blockquote>Central to Douglass's denunciation, here, is the contrast between Americans' “glorious” past and their “degenerate” present. What is striking about this contrast, moreover, is that it relies on a clearly distorted and idealized picture of the past. It is evidently false that the Founders were paragons of virtue, for whom “justice, liberty, and humanity were ‘<i>final</i>’; not slavery and oppression.” Indeed, the vast majority of them were—as Douglass well knew—slaveholders. Yet, Douglass's idealization serves a crucial rhetorical function. It helps construct a moral gulf between his contemporaries, on the one hand, and the Founders they revere, on the other. And, by doing so, it helps shame his contemporaries into taking action against slavery.2</div>\u0000<p>Douglass's speech exemplifies an important rhetorical practice. Public speakers often use their speech to <i>mobilize</i> their audience—in other words, to motivate their audience to take action, collectively, in support of a political cause. Yet, in non-ideal circumstances, successfully mobilizing a group can be extremely difficult. This might be, for instance, because taking action is costly for potential participants (e.g., if protestors would face arrest or violent retaliation); because the odds of achieving political change are very low (e.g., if powerful decision-makers have insulated themselves from pressure); or simply because the mobilizer's audience is suffering from weakness of will. To overcome such obstacles to motivating people, mobilizers often resort to deploying <i>falsehoods</i>: that is, they put forward propositions that misrepresent re","PeriodicalId":47999,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Public Affairs","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-01-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139515279","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Joint Ought 联合应
1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-11-07 DOI: 10.1111/papa.12252
Rowan Mellor
Sometimes, what you ought to do depends on what other people will do: whether or not Dad ought to pick the kids up from school depends on whether Mom is going to do it. This seems obvious enough. Yet, it leads to a problem. Suppose that several agents each have two options: A or B. It would be best if they all did A, significantly worse if they all did B, and worst of all if some did A while others did B. As it happens, each is going to do B, regardless of what the others do. Given how everyone is else going to act, it seems as though each of these agents ought to choose B: since if they were to pick A, they would bring about the worst possible result. Nevertheless, there seems to be something wrong here: after all, they could all pick A and bring about the best result. But how could it be wrong for everyone to do what they ought to do?1 Cases like this pose an obvious problem for act-consequentialists. Act-consequentialism says that you are morally obligated to do whatever will have the best outcome. But in cases like the above, the theory implies that everyone ought to act in ways which will collectively bring about a suboptimal outcome. While it isn't strictly inconsistent, many consequentialists find this conclusion hard to swallow.2 Slice and Patch Go Golfing: Mr. Patient needs a life-saving operation from two surgeons, Ms. Slice and Mr. Patch. If left unattended, Patient will die, though not painfully. If Slice cuts and Patch stitches, then he will survive. But cutting without stitching would cause his death to be agonizing, as would stitching without cutting. As it happens, Slice and Patch will each go golfing, regardless of what the other does. This paper defends the following solution. I will argue that, as well as individual “oughts” which apply to individual agents, there are also joint “oughts” which apply irreducibly to pluralities of agents. Moreover, in cases like Slice and Patch, individual and joint “oughts” can pull in different directions: while Slice ought not to cut and Patch ought not to stitch, they jointly ought to operate on Patient. This joint requirement corresponds to Patient's moral claim to be saved, and the surgeons' failure to satisfy it (in part) accounts for the wrong he stands to suffer. A version of this view is presented in some old papers by Frank Jackson4 and Derek Parfit,5 and has recently been revived by Alexander Dietz.6 According to these authors, “we” together can be morally required to do something, even if none of “us” is required to do our parts. I develop this view in two ways. First, I argue that we should think of joint “oughts” not as “oughts” which are held by group agents, but rather as “oughts” which are held jointly by several agents.7 This may or may not be the view which Dietz, Jackson, and Parfit meant to defend. But, for reasons I will explain, I think it should be. Second, I address the question of who wrongs whom when a joint “ought” goes unmet. I propose that if Patient is wronged by S
有时候,你应该做什么取决于别人会做什么:爸爸是否应该去学校接孩子取决于妈妈是否会去做。这似乎是显而易见的。然而,这导致了一个问题。假设几个agent各有两种选择:A或B,如果他们都选择A是最好的,如果他们都选择B是最糟糕的,如果一些人选择A而另一些人选择B是最糟糕的。事实上,每个agent都会选择B,而不管其他人怎么做。考虑到其他人的行为,似乎每个人都应该选择B:因为如果他们选择A,他们会带来最坏的结果。然而,这里似乎有一些问题:毕竟,他们都可以选择A,并带来最好的结果。但是,每个人都做他们应该做的事,这怎么可能是错的呢?像这样的案例给行为结果主义者带来了一个明显的问题。行为结果主义认为你在道德上有义务去做任何能带来最好结果的事。但在上述情况下,该理论意味着,每个人都应该以一种共同带来次优结果的方式行事。虽然这并不是严格意义上的不一致,但许多结果主义者发现这个结论很难让人接受去打高尔夫球:这位病人需要两位外科医生——Slice女士和Patch先生——为他做一次挽救生命的手术。如果无人照料,病人将会死去,虽然并不痛苦。如果切片和补丁缝合,他就能活下来。但不缝合而切开会让他死得很痛苦,就像不切开而缝合一样。碰巧的是,Slice和Patch将各自去打高尔夫球,而不管对方在做什么。本文为以下解决方案进行了辩护。我将论证,除了适用于个体行为人的个体“应当”之外,也存在不可简化地适用于多个行为人的共同“应当”。此外,在像Slice和Patch这样的案例中,个体和关节的“应该”可以向不同的方向拉动:Slice不应该切割,Patch不应该缝合,它们应该共同对患者进行手术。这一共同要求与病人要求被拯救的道德要求相一致,而外科医生未能满足这一要求(部分地)说明了他将遭受的错误。这种观点的一个版本出现在弗兰克·杰克逊和德里克·帕菲特的一些旧论文中,最近又被亚历山大·迪茨重新发扬。根据这些作者的观点,“我们”可以在道德上被要求一起做某事,即使“我们”没有被要求做我们该做的事。我从两个方面阐述了这一观点。首先,我认为我们不应该把共同的“应该”看作是由群体主体持有的“应该”,而应该看作是由几个主体共同持有的“应该”这可能是迪茨、杰克逊和帕菲特想要捍卫的观点,也可能不是。但是,出于我将解释的原因,我认为它应该是。其次,我要解决的问题是,当一个共同的“应该”没有得到满足时,是谁冤枉了谁。我的建议是,如果病人因为Slice和Patch没有按照他们共同的职责行事而受到了伤害,那么他就是被他们中的一个或两个单独伤害了,即使每个外科医生都按照他们单独的职责行事。我认为,“病人”取决于他们行动的动机。本文的工作如下。在第二部分中,我将批判最近解决Slice和Patch难题的四种尝试。第三节提出了我的共同责任解决方案,第四节讨论了侵权问题。在第五节中,我考虑了一个反对我的观点,即Slice和Patch应该共同操作,而Slice不应该切割,Patch不应该缝合;这种反对意见源于对工具规范性的考虑。Slice和Patch等案例所带来的问题最近引起了许多关注。在我提出我的解决方案之前,考虑一些现有的解决方案及其面临的困难将会有所帮助。Niko Kolodny8区分了两种可能的Slice和Patch版本。在他所谓的“动机良好”的版本中,两位外科医生都希望病人能得救,所以如果他们相信对方会做他们的手术,他们就会做自己的手术。然而,每个人都拒绝了,因为他们合理地(尽管是错误的)认为,如果他们做自己的工作,对方就不会做他们的工作(他们不想让病人遭受不必要的痛苦)。Kolodny说,我也同意,认为Patient在这些版本中受到了冤枉是不直观的。在这里,他的死似乎类似于一场自然灾害:虽然很糟糕,但在道德上并不令人反感。相比之下,在Kolodny所说的“不良动机”版本中,至少有一名外科医生宁愿去打高尔夫球也不愿拯救病人的生命,因此即使他们相信另一名外科医生会做他们该做的事,他们也不会做。似乎正是这些说法才促使人们作出这样的判断:Patient受到了冤枉;除非另有说明,否则它们将是我这里的重点。 区分“切片”和“补丁”的好动机和坏动机的版本为这个谜题提供了一个简单的解决方案:既然“病人”只是在坏动机的版本中被冤枉了,那么一定是一个或两个外科医生的坏动机造成了这种错误。我将在第四节解释,我认为这是部分正确的。但这并不是故事的全部。外科医生的动机如何解释病人在不良动机的情况下承受的痛苦?以下是Kolodny的回答。当两位外科医生都拒绝做他们该做的事时,他们各自做了正确的事。但如果,比方说,Slice宁愿打高尔夫球也不愿救“病人”的命,所以即使她认为Patch会缝合,她也不会缝合,那么她就表现出对“病人”缺乏应有的关心。应有的关注要求Slice适当地重视患者的利益;由于她更关心的是打高尔夫球,而不是拯救Patient,如果让她选择的话,她会选择前者而不是后者,她的动机心理学就达不到这个标准。Slice的行为反映了她缺乏应有的关心,她冤枉了Patient,尽管她做了她应该做的事情。然而,这似乎错误地描述了病人将要遭受的痛苦。为了说明这一点,假设Slice和Patch都更喜欢打高尔夫球,而不是在病人出现紧急情况的一年前挽救他的生命,当时他非常健康。科洛德尼的观点是,Slice和Patch当时亏待了Patient,因为他们没有给予他应有的关心让我们承认这是真的。即便如此,这种错误似乎与外科医生让他自生自死时他所遭受的痛苦有很大的不同。但Kolodny似乎无法解释这一点:因为,在他看来,仅仅是外科医生缺乏应有的关注,才导致了这两种情况的错误。科洛德尼有一个可能的答案。仅仅因为一个人在不同的情况下被同样的行为或态度所冤枉,这并不意味着这些冤枉的严重程度是一样的。如果有问题的行为/态度使受害者的情况更糟,那么错误可能会更严重。例如,假设有人开车不顾一切地穿过你的社区。在场景1中,没有人受伤。在场景2中,司机严重伤害了你。在科洛德尼看来,司机在这两种情况下都有可能伤害了你:因为他们在这两种情况下都同样无视你的安全。但他不必说这些错误同样严重。相反,他可以说,尽管司机的无视解释了两种情况下的错误,但情况2中的错误更严重,因为他们的无视让你的处境比情况1更糟。回到Slice和Patch, Kolodny可能会说一些类似的话来回应前一段的担忧。在动机不良的情况下,病人会自生自灭,而在他不需要手术的情况下,病人都因为医生缺乏应有的关心而受到了冤枉。但是,正如在鲁莽驾驶的例子中,错误在第一个版本中更为严重,因为外科医生的无视使他的情况更糟然而,这两个版本的Slice和Patch之间的道德差异似乎比这个提议所认识到的更重要。不仅仅是病人的情况会更糟,因此会受到更严重的冤枉,在最初的情况下,他需要手术,而不是在他不需要手术的情况下。在原作中,病人似乎有一种道德主张,而在第二篇中他却没有:即,对挽救生命的手术的主张。直觉上,正是由于这一要求被忽视,他才会受到冤枉。然而,科洛德尼不能这么说。如果某人对X有道德要求,那么其他人就有相应的道德要求来提供X.13由于Kolodny没有对外科医生提出进行手术的道德要求,他不能认为病人对X有道德要求。当然,病人在需要和不需要手术的时候,都可能有进一步
{"title":"Joint Ought","authors":"Rowan Mellor","doi":"10.1111/papa.12252","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12252","url":null,"abstract":"Sometimes, what you ought to do depends on what other people will do: whether or not Dad ought to pick the kids up from school depends on whether Mom is going to do it. This seems obvious enough. Yet, it leads to a problem. Suppose that several agents each have two options: A or B. It would be best if they all did A, significantly worse if they all did B, and worst of all if some did A while others did B. As it happens, each is going to do B, regardless of what the others do. Given how everyone is else going to act, it seems as though each of these agents ought to choose B: since if they were to pick A, they would bring about the worst possible result. Nevertheless, there seems to be something wrong here: after all, they could all pick A and bring about the best result. But how could it be wrong for everyone to do what they ought to do?1 Cases like this pose an obvious problem for act-consequentialists. Act-consequentialism says that you are morally obligated to do whatever will have the best outcome. But in cases like the above, the theory implies that everyone ought to act in ways which will collectively bring about a suboptimal outcome. While it isn't strictly inconsistent, many consequentialists find this conclusion hard to swallow.2 Slice and Patch Go Golfing: Mr. Patient needs a life-saving operation from two surgeons, Ms. Slice and Mr. Patch. If left unattended, Patient will die, though not painfully. If Slice cuts and Patch stitches, then he will survive. But cutting without stitching would cause his death to be agonizing, as would stitching without cutting. As it happens, Slice and Patch will each go golfing, regardless of what the other does. This paper defends the following solution. I will argue that, as well as individual “oughts” which apply to individual agents, there are also joint “oughts” which apply irreducibly to pluralities of agents. Moreover, in cases like Slice and Patch, individual and joint “oughts” can pull in different directions: while Slice ought not to cut and Patch ought not to stitch, they jointly ought to operate on Patient. This joint requirement corresponds to Patient's moral claim to be saved, and the surgeons' failure to satisfy it (in part) accounts for the wrong he stands to suffer. A version of this view is presented in some old papers by Frank Jackson4 and Derek Parfit,5 and has recently been revived by Alexander Dietz.6 According to these authors, “we” together can be morally required to do something, even if none of “us” is required to do our parts. I develop this view in two ways. First, I argue that we should think of joint “oughts” not as “oughts” which are held by group agents, but rather as “oughts” which are held jointly by several agents.7 This may or may not be the view which Dietz, Jackson, and Parfit meant to defend. But, for reasons I will explain, I think it should be. Second, I address the question of who wrongs whom when a joint “ought” goes unmet. I propose that if Patient is wronged by S","PeriodicalId":47999,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Public Affairs","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135432381","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Social Science, Policy and Democracy 社会科学、政策与民主
1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-10-17 DOI: 10.1111/papa.12250
Johanna Thoma
Can social science provide policy-guidance without undermining some basic democratic values? It would clearly be devastating if the answer was “no”: Most people are deeply committed both to democracy, as well as to the idea that policy decisions should be informed by the best available science, including the best available social science. Accordingly, the many philosophers who have worried about potential tensions between science and democracy have come out arguing that, if done right, good science and democracy mutually support rather than undermine each other, John Dewey and Philip Kitcher being paradigmatic examples.1 This article argues that there is an under-appreciated democratic challenge for policy-relevant science, which I will articulate specifically in the context of value-laden social scientific indicators. Value-ladenness has long been acknowledged to pose an obstacle for reconciling science and democracy: It creates the potential for the value judgments made by a small subset of the population to have a significant impact on policy decisions, in a way that bypasses normal processes of democratic legitimization. Consequently, solutions to this challenge have either defended the value-free ideal,2 or stressed the need to, in one way or another, democratically align the values entering science, in a way that is parallel to how democratic legitimacy is given to public decision-making more generally. The nature of many social scientific indicators makes the value-free ideal wholly unworkable, lest we give up the entire project of aiming to measure poverty, inequality, or wellbeing. And so only the second common type of response seems to be available in their case. But, I will argue, this response misses a significant part of the challenge value-ladenness poses to democracy. The solution, I will argue, is greater value pluralism rather than democratic alignment. As I write, the United Kingdom, like many countries around the world, is facing a devastating cost of living crisis. The incomes of large numbers of households cannot keep up with the rising prices of the goods and services they consume, pushing increasing numbers into poverty. To tackle this crisis, it is important that policy-makers have a clear picture of inflation—of how much the cost of living has increased, how it is projected to further increase, and how different policy options will affect the rate of change. In the United Kingdom, the Office of National Statistics (ONS) supplies a number of measures of inflation that are treated as key indicators by policy-makers, by the public and media holding them to account, and by social scientists studying the causal relationships between inflation and other social scientific variables or policy interventions. The most widely used and reported indicator is the Consumer Price Index (CPI). But what is the cost of living? The first thing to note is that it is clearly a value-laden concept and treated as such by those using it. Saying t
社会科学能在不破坏某些基本民主价值观的情况下提供政策指导吗?如果答案是“不”,那显然是毁灭性的:大多数人都深深信奉民主,以及政策决定应该由现有的最佳科学(包括现有的最佳社会科学)提供信息的观点。因此,许多担心科学与民主之间潜在紧张关系的哲学家已经站出来辩称,如果处理得当,好的科学和民主是相互支持而不是相互破坏的,约翰·杜威和菲利普·基彻就是典型的例子本文认为,与政策相关的科学面临着一个未被充分认识的民主挑战,我将在充满价值的社会科学指标的背景下具体阐述这一点。长期以来,价值负担一直被认为是调和科学与民主的障碍:它使一小部分人做出的价值判断有可能绕过民主合法化的正常过程,对政策决策产生重大影响。因此,应对这一挑战的解决方案要么捍卫价值自由的理想,2要么强调以某种方式民主地调整进入科学的价值观的必要性,这种方式与更普遍地赋予公共决策的民主合法性是平行的。许多社会科学指标的性质使得价值无关的理想完全不可行,否则我们就会放弃旨在衡量贫困、不平等或福祉的整个项目。所以在他们的情况下,似乎只有第二种常见的反应。但是,我认为,这种反应忽略了价值负担对民主构成挑战的一个重要部分。我认为,解决方案是更大程度的价值多元化,而不是民主结盟。在我写这篇文章的时候,英国和世界上许多国家一样,正面临着一场毁灭性的生活成本危机。大量家庭的收入跟不上他们消费的商品和服务价格的上涨,使越来越多的人陷入贫困。为了应对这场危机,重要的是政策制定者要对通货膨胀有一个清晰的认识——生活成本增加了多少,预计将如何进一步增加,以及不同的政策选择将如何影响变化的速度。在英国,国家统计局(ONS)提供了一系列衡量通货膨胀的指标,这些指标被决策者、要求他们承担责任的公众和媒体以及研究通货膨胀与其他社会科学变量或政策干预之间因果关系的社会科学家视为关键指标。最广泛使用和报道的指标是消费者价格指数(CPI)。但是生活成本是多少呢?首先要注意的是,它显然是一个充满价值的概念,并且被使用它的人视为这样的概念。说生活成本上升是指对价格变化前后家庭能够负担的商品种类和生活方式进行比较评估。一般来说,人们能够负担得起过得好是件好事,而生活成本变化的衡量标准旨在捕捉家庭能够做到这一点的程度。然而,很明显,有不同的方法可以使这个想法变得精确。有两种明显的方法可以使它至少在某种程度上更加精确,一种是把它看作满足一个人基本需求的成本,另一种是把它看作消费人们实际消费的东西的成本——在许多情况下,这些东西将超出满足一个人的基本需求。无论哪种情况,生活成本实际上是因人而异的。显然,不同的人实际上消费不同的东西,这些东西的价格可能会有不同程度的变化。但即使是满足基本需求的成本也可能因人而异;我需要矫正眼镜才能正常生活,而你可能不需要。尽管存在这种异质性,但对大规模政策有用的通货膨胀衡量标准需要捕捉总生活成本的变化“生活成本”概念的选择,以及如何在多样化的人口中聚集的选择,都涉及到重要的价值判断,关于什么让生活变得美好,关于谁重要多少,关于我们有权期望从彼此和国家得到什么补偿,以及关于我们的政策重点。实际的通胀指标包含了这些价值判断。在实践中,国家统计局发布的标题CPI渴望捕捉家庭实际消费的东西的价格变化它使用700种商品的代表性篮子,定期从全国不同类型的商店收集价格报价。在决定篮子中每种商品的数量时,总体CPI服从于家庭的消费决策。 更具体地说,它根据不同家庭在所有家庭总支出中所占的比例赋予不同家庭的权重,使CPI对较富裕家庭的消费决策更加敏感。近年来,反贫困活动人士对国家统计局施加了越来越大的压力,他们认为,总体通胀数据并没有很好地反映出最贫困家庭所经历的生活成本危机的程度批评的声音一方面是,国家统计局使用的标准篮子没有包括最贫困家庭满足基本需求所消费的足够多的商品,比如超市自有品牌的产品;另一方面,作为汇总效应,这些产品的较高价格上涨被较富裕家庭不成比例地消费的商品的较低价格上涨所抵消。国家统计局进行的定期分类在一定程度上可以解决第二个问题,但不能解决第一个问题。这里的核心争议在于价值观和政策优先事项:相对于通胀措施可能有助于实现的其他目的,活动人士希望在政策上更优先考虑为满足基本需求的成本增加而补偿最贫困家庭,或者从一开始就防止这种增长发生。因此,他们希望通胀措施的设计能够最大程度地服务于这些目的,而他们传统上并没有做到这一点。国家统计局目前正在做出一些改变,以更好地应对这些挑战,我们将在下面回到为了深入了解我在本文中关注的核心问题,请注意这个争议有两个层面。一方面,由于被政策导向的社会科学指标所捕捉,最终将影响公共政策的价值观存在分歧。在这方面,这场争议就像政治领域的任何其他分歧一样。但另一方面,也有人抱怨说,这场辩论的一方无法获得有助于他们在公开辩论中提出自己观点的测量方法(以及使用这些方法的科学研究),而另一方却可以。一方可以诉诸官方统计数据,抓住他们关心的问题,而另一方则需要依靠轶事证据。他们并没有平等地进入公众审议。这是一个与第一个截然不同的问题,我认为,这是一个被旨在调和民主与科学价值的文献所忽视的问题。由于下文探讨的原因,这也是一个在民主社会不太可能充分自我纠正的问题。通货膨胀指标只是一种社会科学指标,它既承载着价值,又与指导政策高度相关。如果所讨论的价值判断完全是由未经选举的社会科学家做出的,完全基于个人价值观,而不代表广大人口,那么任何合理的民主规范理论都将存在问题。在价值判断对政策产生影响的程度上,我们可能希望确保其中嵌入的价值观是以民主合法的方式选出的,就像我们的目标是确保任何重大政策决定的民主合法性一样。但是,与政策相关的科学与民主之间的关系还有另一个重要方面。与政策相关的科学产出,如社会科学指标,不仅用于为决策者的选择提供信息。它们也会反馈到公众审议中,并被用来问责政策制定者。只关注进入研究的价值的民主选择,然后用于指导政策选择,忽略了与政策相关的科学的第二个目的。这在价值观存在重大分歧的情况下尤其成问题。现代民主国家经常发现自己在一项政策决策中面临着无法解决的价值观分歧,包括与政策相关的社会科学指标中所包含的价值观类型。尽管如此,大多数关于民主的解释都允许在不要求实际上达成共识的情况下做出这样的决定。同样,我们可以以民主合法的方式确定嵌入社会科学指标的价值观,然后用来指导特定类型的政策,而实际上没有就这些价值观是否正确达成共识。然而,如果除了民主选择的指标之外,没有其他社会科学指标可供公众和社会科学家广泛使用,我认为,这就提出了一个认识不平等的问题:只有那些认同所选指标中嵌入的民主选择的价值判断的人,才能在公共审议中充分可靠地使用这些指标,并在要求政策制定者承担责任时使用它们。 下一节详细阐述了这种现象可能对民主构成的一种威胁,这种威胁在关于科学价值的更广泛讨论中很常见。然后,它将概述旨在解决这一威胁的科学民主化的哲学解释,所有这些都旨在某种形式的我称之为民主联盟。最后,我将论证,还有另一种民主威胁是这些论述没有充分解决的,而这种威胁只能通过更大的价值多元化来应对。考虑一下这个假设的充满价值的社会科学如何指导政策的例子:一个社会科学家开发了一种衡量国民福祉的方法,仅根据她自己的道德直觉,理论化和阅读关于福祉的哲学文献,做出所有必要的
{"title":"Social Science, Policy and Democracy","authors":"Johanna Thoma","doi":"10.1111/papa.12250","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12250","url":null,"abstract":"Can social science provide policy-guidance without undermining some basic democratic values? It would clearly be devastating if the answer was “no”: Most people are deeply committed both to democracy, as well as to the idea that policy decisions should be informed by the best available science, including the best available social science. Accordingly, the many philosophers who have worried about potential tensions between science and democracy have come out arguing that, if done right, good science and democracy mutually support rather than undermine each other, John Dewey and Philip Kitcher being paradigmatic examples.1 This article argues that there is an under-appreciated democratic challenge for policy-relevant science, which I will articulate specifically in the context of value-laden social scientific indicators. Value-ladenness has long been acknowledged to pose an obstacle for reconciling science and democracy: It creates the potential for the value judgments made by a small subset of the population to have a significant impact on policy decisions, in a way that bypasses normal processes of democratic legitimization. Consequently, solutions to this challenge have either defended the value-free ideal,2 or stressed the need to, in one way or another, democratically align the values entering science, in a way that is parallel to how democratic legitimacy is given to public decision-making more generally. The nature of many social scientific indicators makes the value-free ideal wholly unworkable, lest we give up the entire project of aiming to measure poverty, inequality, or wellbeing. And so only the second common type of response seems to be available in their case. But, I will argue, this response misses a significant part of the challenge value-ladenness poses to democracy. The solution, I will argue, is greater value pluralism rather than democratic alignment. As I write, the United Kingdom, like many countries around the world, is facing a devastating cost of living crisis. The incomes of large numbers of households cannot keep up with the rising prices of the goods and services they consume, pushing increasing numbers into poverty. To tackle this crisis, it is important that policy-makers have a clear picture of inflation—of how much the cost of living has increased, how it is projected to further increase, and how different policy options will affect the rate of change. In the United Kingdom, the Office of National Statistics (ONS) supplies a number of measures of inflation that are treated as key indicators by policy-makers, by the public and media holding them to account, and by social scientists studying the causal relationships between inflation and other social scientific variables or policy interventions. The most widely used and reported indicator is the Consumer Price Index (CPI). But what is the cost of living? The first thing to note is that it is clearly a value-laden concept and treated as such by those using it. Saying t","PeriodicalId":47999,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Public Affairs","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135995210","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Philosophy & Public Affairs
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1